2002 - Societe Internationale de Defense Sociale
Transcrição
2002 - Societe Internationale de Defense Sociale
La Société internationale de défense sociale pour une politique criminelle humaniste dédie ce Volume à la mémoire de Adolfo Beria di Argentine, son secrétaire général puis son vice-président de 1966 à 2000. The International Society of Social Defence and Humane Criminal Policy dedicates this Volume to the memory of Adolfo Beria di Argentine, former ISSD Secretary-General and Vice-President (1966 to 2000). DEFENSE SOCIALE ET DROIT PENAL POUR LA PROTECTION DES GENERATIONS FUTURES, EN PRESENCE DES RISQUES NOUVEAUX Actes du XIVème CONGRES INTERNATIONAL DE DEFENSE SOCIALE SOCIAL DEFENCE AND CRIMINAL LAW FOR THE PROTECTION OF COMING GENERATIONS, IN VIEW OF THE NEW RISKS Proceedings of XIVth INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS ON SOCIAL DEFENCE Lisbon, Portugal, 17-19 May 2002 Centro Cultural de Belém à l'initiative de/at the initiative of Société internationale de défense sociale pour une politique criminelle humaniste Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale sous les auspices du/under the auspices of Ministry of Justice of Portugal en coopération avec/in co-operation with Centre for International Crime Prevention (CICP) of the United Nations Office for Drug Control and Crime Prevention (ODCCP) CAHIERS DE DEFENSE SOCIALE Direction et Rédaction / Editorial Board Directeur / Director Mario PISANI, professeur de procédure pénale à l’Université de Milan Comité de rédaction / Editorial Committee Edmondo BRUTI LIBERATI − Adolfo CERETTI − Vitaliano ESPOSITO − Gioacchino POLIMENI − Giovanni TAMBURINO Secrétariat de rédaction / Editorial Secretariat CENTRO NAZIONALE DI PREVENZIONE E DIFESA SOCIALE Palazzo Comunale delle Scienze Sociali − Piazza Castello, 3 − 20121 MILANO − Italie Les Cahiers ne sont pas en vente. Ils sont réservés aux membres de la SIDS The Cahiers are not on sale. Only ISSD Members are entitled to receive them TABLE DES MATIERES TABLE OF CONTENTS Présentation/Presentation/ Presentación Mario PISANI page 9 Présidence du Congrès/ Chairmanship of the Congress « 15 Les participants Participants « 17 Commentaire du Thème du Congrès / Overview of the Theme of the Congress « 23 Programme du Congrès / Programme of the Congress « 27 « « « 33 37 41 « 43 Le Quatorzième Congrès international de défense sociale / The Fourteenth International Congress on Social Defence au Congrès/ The Congress SEANCE INAUGURALE / OPENING SESSION Allocutions/ Addresses by: Simone ROZES Eduardo VETERE Mota CAMPOS RAPPORT GENERAL INTRODUCTORY REPORT INTRODUCTIF/ Jorge DE FIGUEIREDO DIAS GENERAL I. LES PROBLEMES POSES PAR LE DEVELOPPEMENT ET PAR L'EVOLUTION DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE (NUISANCES DIVERSES, TECHNOLOGIE GENETIQUE ET DEVELOPPEMENT DURABLE)/ PROBLEMS POSED BY DEVELOPMENT AND THE EVOLVING SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH (DIFFERENT KINDS OF HARMS, GENETIC ENGINEERING AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT) Miriam BLUMBERG-MOKRI Manuel DA COSTA ANDRADE Gustavo GHIDINI Antonio VERCHER page « « « 61 89 97 103 « « « 129 139 151 « 171 II. LES DEFIS DE LA RESPONSABILITE PENALE: NOUVELLES ALTERNATIVES ET LIMITES, NOUVELLES FORMES ET NOUVEAUX OBJECTIFS / THE CHALLENGES OF CRIMINAL LIABILITY: NEW ALTERNATIVES AND LIMITS, NEW FORMS AND NEW GOALS Mariano CIAFARDINI William S. LAUFER − Gilbert GEIS Joachim VOGEL III. LA CHARTE DES DROITS FONDAMENTAUX DE L'UNION EUROPEENNE / THE CHARTER OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS OF THE EUROPEAN UNION Rui Manuel MOURA RAMOS IV. COURS PENALES INTERNATIONALES ET COMMISSIONS DE RECONCILIATION: REPONSES ADAPTEES AUX MENACES DE GUERRES, GENOCIDES OU DISCRIMINATIONS PESANT SUR LES GENERATIONS FUTURES / INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL COURTS AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSIONS: SUITABLE RESPONSES TO THREATS OF WARS, GENOCIDES OR DISCRIMINATIONS FACING COMING GENERATIONS Adolfo CERETTI − Alberto NOSENZO Fausto POCAR page « 201 261 João TIAGO SILVEIRA Simone ROZES « « 273 275 Les Congrès internationaux de défense sociale / The International Congresses on Social Defence « 277 SEANCE DE CLOTURE / CLOSING SESSION SOCIETE INTERNATIONALE DE DEFENSE SOCIALE POUR UNE POLITIQUE CRIMINELLE HUMANISTE - SIDS Organisation dotée de statut consultatif auprès du Conseil économique et social des Nations Unies INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY OF SOCIAL DEFENCE AND HUMANE CRIMINAL POLICY - ISSD Organization in Consultative Status with the Economic and Social Council of the United Nations CONSEIL DE DIRECTION/BOARD Président / President: Simone ROZES, premier président honoraire de la Cour de cassation de France Secrétaire général / Secretary-General: Edmondo BRUTI LIBERATI, substitut du Procureur général près la Cour d'appel de Milan Secrétaire général adjoint / Assistant-Secretary-General: Adolfo CERETTI, professeur associé de criminologie à l'Université de MilanBicocca Vice-présidents / Vice-Presidents: Adedokun A. ADEYEMI, Professor and Dean, Faculty of Law, University of Lagos Tolani ASUNI, Psychiatrist; Former Director, United Nations Social Defence Research Institute Paolo BERNASCONI, professeur de droit pénal de l'économie aux Universités de Saint Gall et de Zürich Pierre-Henri BOLLE, professeur de législations pénales, doyen de l'Université de Neuchâtel Jorge DE FIGUEIREDO DIAS, président du Conseil scientifique de la Faculté de droit de l'Université de Coimbra; ancien président de la Fondation internationale pénale et pénitentiaire Elio GOMEZ GRILLO, directeur de l'Institut de sciences pénales et criminologiques de l'Université Simon Bolivar de Caracas Vladimir KOUDRIAVTSEV, Vice-President, Russian Academy of Sciences Gerhard O.W. MUELLER, Distinguished Professor of Criminal Justice, Rutgers University, Newark, N. J. Reynald OTTENHOF, professeur à l'Université de Nantes; vice-président de l'Association internationale de droit pénal; Vice-président de l'Institut supérieur international de sciences criminelles (ISISC) Mario PISANI, professeur de procédure pénale à l'Université de Milan; directeur des "Cahiers de défense sociale" Constantin VOUYOUCAS, professeur émérite de droit pénal de l'Université Aristote de Thessalonique Secrétaires généraux régionaux/ Regional Secretaries-General: pour l'Afrique / for Africa: A. Aziz SHIDDO, Advocate and Commissioner for Oaths, Karthoum (Sudan) Ayodele Victoria OYAYOBI ATSENUWA, Lecturer in the Department of Public Law, University of Lagos (Nigeria) Maher ABDEL-WAHED, First Assistant to the Minister of Justice; Vice-President, Egyptian Cassation Court (Arab Republic of Egypt) pour l'Amérique Latine / for Latin America: Bernardo BEIDERMAN, ancien professeur de criminologie et de droit pénal de l'Université nationale de Buenos Aires (Argentina) Paulo José DA COSTA, Professor of Penal Law, State University of São Paulo (Brazil) Alì LASSER, ex-juez de menores, Caracas (Venezuela) Louis RODRIGUEZ MANZANERA, Criminológo; Director Academia Nacional de Seguridad Pública (Mexico) pour les Etats-Unis d'Amérique / for the United States of America: Freda ADLER, Distinguished Professor of Criminal Justice, Rutgers University, Newark, N. J. Pedro R. DAVID, Juez de la Cámara Nacional de Casación Penal de la República Argentina y Miembro del Grupo de cinco Expertos, designado por el Secretario General de la ONU para evaluar el funcionamiento y operatividad de los Tribunales Penales Internacionales para la Ex-Yugoslavia y Rwanda pour l'Europe / for Europe: Luis ARROYO ZAPATERO, recteur de l'Université de Castilla -La Mancha (Espagne) Matti JOUTSEN, Director, International Affairs Unit, Ministry of Justice, Helsinki (Finland) pour l'Asie / for Asia: Hira SINGH, Former Consultant, National Human Rights Commission, New Delhi (India) Tadashi MORISHITA, Professor Emeritus of Penal Law, Hiroshima University (Japan) Membres / Members: Ljubo BAVCON, professeur émérite de droit pénal de l'Université de Ljubljana Giacomo CANEPA, professeur émérite de médecine légale et criminologie, Département de médecine légale, du travail, psychologie médicale et criminologie, Université de Gênes; président honoraire de la Société internationale de criminologie Orlando CONTRERAS PULIDO, professeur de droit pénal et de criminologie à l'Université centrale du Venezuela Mireille DELMAS MARTY, professeur à l'Université Paris 1 (PanthéonSorbonne); membre de l'Institut universitaire de France Giuseppe di GENNARO, président adjoint honoraire de la Cour de cassation d'Italie Sergio GARCIA RAMIREZ, professeur de droit pénal à l'Université de Mexique; procureur général de la République (Mexique) Giovanni Battista GRAMATICA, avocat à Gênes Joseph HÄUSSLING, Président honoraire du Sénat de l'Université Witten/Herdecke; professeur de l'Université Lodewik H. C. HULSMAN, Professor Emeritus of Penal Law, Nederlande Economische Hogeschool, Rotterdam Hans-Heinrich JESCHECK, ancien directeur du "Max-Planck-Institut fuer auslaendisches und internationales Strafrecht" de Fribourg e. Br.; président honoraire de l'Association internationale de droit pénal Zoran KANDUC, professeur agrégé de criminologie à l'Université de Ljubljana Alvar NELSON, Professor Emeritus of Penal Law, Uppsala University Raymond SCREVENS, président émérite de la Cour de cassation de Belgique; directeur du Centre national de criminologie, Bruxelles Colette SOMERHAUSEN, ancien chef de travaux de recherche de l'Institut de sociologie de l'Université libre de Bruxelles Denis SZABO, directeur du Centre international de criminologie comparée de l'Université de Montréal; président honoraire de la Société internationale de criminologie Klaus TIEDEMANN, directeur de l'Institut de criminologie et de droit pénal des affaires de la Albert-Ludwigs Universität de Fribourg e. Br. Aglaia TSITSOURA, ancien administrateur principal en charge de la Division des problèmes criminels du Conseil de l'Europe Alexander YAKOVLEV, Senior Researcher, Institute of State and Law, Russian Academy of Sciences Trésorier / Treasurer: Luciana MARSELLI MILNER, du "Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale" Membres honoraires / Honorary Members: Inkeri ANTTILA, Professor Emeritus of Criminal Law; Former Director, Helsinki Institute of Crime Prevention and Control affiliated with the United Nations (HEUNI); Former Minister of Justice of Finland (Vice-President) Shigemitsu DANDO, Former Justice, Supreme Court of Japan; Member of the Academy of Japan; Professor Emeritus of the University of Tokyo; Counsellor to the Crown Prince of Japan Giuliano VA SSALLI, ancien président de la Cour constitutionnelle d'Italie; professeur émérite de droit pénal de l'Université de Rome; ancien ministre de la Justice Jozsef VIGH, Former Head of the Criminological Department, Eötvos Lörand University, Budapest Eduardo Vetere Merci beaucoup, Madame Rozès et chers amis, chers collégues… first of all I have the honour to convey to you, as all participants of the 14th Congress, the best regards and the warmest gratitude of the Secretary General of the Unites Nations , Mister Kofi Annan, for your important contributions to our work, together with his best wishes for a most successful Congress. Secondarily, and before touching on the issues attended, allow me also to join you, Madame, Chair Person, and President of the Society, in stressing the importance of continuing in our work having in mind the heritage of the great founders of our movement: Filippo Grammatica and Mark Hansell, who have transmitted to us one of their most precious gifts. Let me also – as you did, Simone – recall here another of our great friends and personalities, Adolfo Beria d'Argentine, the former Secretary General of the Society, who really, to the United Nations' programme and to me for so many years, has been a tremendous, invaluable presence, not only because he was a fantastic magician – to use your words, Simone – but also because no doubt he was one of the greatest catalysts for the Social Defence Movement and for criminal justice reform. Really there is no time here to recall his role for the organisation of the Congress in Milan, for organising so many of the preparatory meetings related to the topics of the Congresses, together with the other big fours… no doubt such contributions are a demonstration of his commitment to the goals and the objectives enshrined in the United Nations Charter: peace, justice, respect for human rights and development. And it is particularly in connection to this later question of development and also development vis-à-vis human rights that also the Internationa l Society of Social Defence has made important in the work of the United Nations and in all our agendas for a number of years thanks to the contributions of thinkers, of reformers, of scientists like you here today. Now, going to the importance of the issue that you are discussing today, and starting particularly with the question of the problem of sustainable development and the role of criminal law: when we speak of sustainable development we should all recall the Bruntland report of '87 according to which development should meet – and I quote: «…the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs». A process of change in which exploitation of resources, the direction of investments, the orientation of technological development and institutional change are all in harmony and then have both current and future potential to meet human needs and aspirations. The central rationale for sustainable development has been to increase people standards of living, especially the well-being of the least 2 advantaged people in societies thus avoiding indiscriminate future costs. The topics that you are going to treat today, as the previous main issues dealt by the Congresses of the International Society of Social Defence – I just remember: marginalization in Caracas, urbanisation in Thessalonica – are all a demonstration of your global virtue in connection with some of these crucial issues. And of course, when we speak of development, we look at the current process of technology and the role of technology in helping to build prosperity, to make it easier and more comfortable for the life of the people and to ensure better standards of living. However, it is also true that technology has given rise to new risks to the health and the security of individuals, creating also new challenges to domestic, transborder and transnational crime control. In short there are new risks which are deriving from the current advances in technologies, risks which have to be studied, evaluated, interpreted, in order to look at their implications, both in the legal and the social field. This applies also to the other topics that are being discussed today, that are particularly… when, for example, we look at the last topic in connection with the international criminal court and the fact of how many members of the society have been closed to this issue and particularly today, in which just a few weeks ago the Statute of the International Criminal Court has entered into force. No doubt, while these technological problems, while today's life of globalization is creating new problems, the international community is also showing his resolve in order to deal more appropriately at the global level with such problems, as for example the example of the establishment of the International Criminal Court, the fact that its Statute has been ratified and soon should become operational. In our particular field also tremendous progress can be registered. We were six years ago in Lecce discussing about corruption and nobody could think that in very few years the international community would be ready to start negotiating a comprehensive convention against corruption, but we started and the first ad hoc Committee which was established by the General Assembly started to work just last January for the negotiation of a new convention against corruption. A very comprehensive convention touching both public and private corruption, up to the conflict of interests and with so many countries presenting concrete proposals and texts and all this is a good sign that the international community is not only ready to start seriously this work but most likely to succeed in completing this work in the two-year time that was given to the Europe Committee in order to complete the task. Why two years? Because in two years will be also successfully completed another very important convention with three additional protocols. I am speaking of the Convention on Transnational 3 Organised Crime, just negotiated in 1999 and 2000, culminated in the Palermo Conference in December 2000, in which a record number of signatures took place: 121 countries signed the Convention during last year since December 2000, the number of signature has increased to 141 and at the moment 13 countries have ratified the Convention. So we do hope that within the next year, or maximum two, we will have the 40 countries required for the Convention to enter into force as well as the Protocol, so that the Conference of State parties can start its work in looking forward and in looking at the implementation of the Convention. These are just some examples in which the international community, through its intergovernmental machinery has given follow-up to several of the recommendations which have emerged from your meeting, from your conference, from your very important contributions. And I would like now, as I started in giving you the greetings of Kofi Annan, to conclude my short address by also quoting his words during his Nobel lecture when he received the Nobel Prize and I quote, he said: «Today's real borders are not between nations but between powerful and powerless, free and fettered, privileged and humiliated. Today no walls can separate humanitarian or human rights cases on one part and the world from national security crisis in the other. New threats make no distinction between races, nations or regions, a new security has entered every mind, regardless of wealth and status. A deeper awareness of the bond that bind all of us in pain as in prosperity has gripped young and old». The coming generations, those for the benefit of whom the International Society of Social Defence is dedicating this 14th International Congress, have the right to expect a better future, a future with a new, more profound and viable framework for development, where crime prevention and control measures can play their role as a tool of a strengthened, more modern and more human application of the rule of law. Thank you very much. 9 P RESENTATION Le XIVème Congrès international aurait dû avoir lieu à Ponta Delgada, aux Açores, vers la fin du mois de novembre 2001. Les tragiques événements qui ont frappé les Etats-Unis le 11 septembre avaient toutefois imposé un renvoi. Grâce toujours aux soins du Groupe national portugais et tout spécialement à l'inlassable activité de Jorge De Figueiredo Dias, ledit Congrès a pu être reconvoqué à Lisbonne, où il s'est déroulé du 17 au 19 mai 2002. Les Cahiers de défense sociale avaient déjà annoncé dans le numéro de l'année 2001 (p.159 et suiv.) le thème du Congrès et reproduit son Commentaire. Par ce numéro, qui est consacré aux Actes du Congrès, et pour lequel ils expriment leur remerciement pour avoir pu bénéficier d'une partie des ressources financières assurées par le Ministère de la Justice du Portugal, les Cahiers se réjouissent de viser un horizon plus ambitieux, celui notamment des mémoires durables. Ce qui se produit c'est donc un élargissement d'horizons et, en quelque sorte, une transfiguration des Cahiers: les deux conviennent parfaitement non seulement à la dimension du thème du XIVème Congrès, penché vers l'avenir et vers des prévisions du futur, mais également à la personne et à la mémoire de Adolfo Beria di Argentine, auquel le Congrès de Lisbonne a été, et les Actes sont, tout naturellement dédiés. Il en avait été de même pour les Cahiers de l'année 2000 pour lui dire, d'après ses propres paroles: «encore parmi nous et avec nous». (Mario Pisani) 10 PRESENTATION The XIVth International Congress of the Society was originally scheduled to take place towards the end of November 2001, at Ponta Delgada in the Azores. The tragic events of 11th September in the United States, however, compelled it to be postponed, so that - with the Portuguese Group, and most notably Jorge De Figueiredo Dias still acting as hosts − it was finally held in Lisbon on 17th -19th May 2002. The Cahiers − which in its 2001 edition had given an advance review of the matters to be addressed at the Congress (page 159 and foll.) − are now very happy and greatly indebted once more to the financial support from the Ministry of Justice of Portugal − to highlight the enduring memories to which the Congress gave rise, through the publication of its Proceedings. In fact this represents a broadening of the horizons, indeed a sort of transfiguration, for Cahiers, which in each case, apart from the great significance of the theme of the XIVth Congress, looking to the future and its possibilities, stand as memorial to the memory of Adolfo Beria di Argentine, to whom the Lisbon meeting and all the work transacted there serve in a way as an act of dedication. The same is true of the 2000 issue of Cahiers, saying to him, and using words of his own, that he is «encore parmi nous et avec nous». (Mario Pisani) 11 P RESENTACIÓN En su día, se había planeado celebrar el XIVº Congreso Internacional de la Sociedad a finales de noviembre de 2001 en Ponta Delgada (Islas Azores). Sin embargo, los trágicos sucesos del 11 de septiembre en Estados Unidos obligaron a aplazarlo, de modo que, siempre al cuidado del Grupo Nacional Portugués y de Jorge De Figueiredo Dias en particular, el Congreso se trasladó a Lisboa, donde se celebró del 17 al 19 de mayo de 2002. Los Cahiers, que en el número de 2001 (págs. 159 y sigs.) habían adelantado comentarios sobre los temas del Congreso, tienen ahora el placer de apuntar a las más lejanas metas de la memoria duraderas, imprimiendo las actas gracias a una parte de los recursos financieros asignados por el Ministerio de Justicia de Portugal, por los que desean dejar patente su agradecimiento una vez más. De esta forma se ensanchan horizontes y, en cierto modo, se transfiguran los Cahiers, lo que, tanto en un caso como en el otro, corresponde perfectamente a lo grandioso del tema del XIVº Congreso, abierto hacia los confines del futuro y de lo futurible, a la figura y al recuerdo de Adolfo Beria di Argentine, a quien, en cierto modo, tanto los encuentros de Lisboa como las actas correspondientes están dedicados, igual que lo había estado el número de Cahiers de 2000, para decirle, precisamente con sus propias palabras, «encore parmi nous et avec nous». (Mario Pisani) 15 PRÉSIDENCE DU CONGRÈS CHAIRMANSHIP OF THE CONGRESS Simone ROZÈS, Président de la Société internationale de défense sociale pour une politique criminelle humaniste -SIDS Jorge DE FIGUEIREDO DIAS, Vice-président de la Société internationale de défense sociale pour une politique criminelle humaniste- SIDS Edmondo BRUTI LIBERATI, Secrétaire général de la Société internationale de défense sociale pour une politique criminelle humaniste- SIDS Guido BRIGNONE, Vice-président du Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale Les participants au Congrès 19 Luis ARROYO ZAPATERO, Recteur de l'Université de Castilla -La Mancha, Espagne; Secrétaire général régional de la SIDS pour l’Europe – Session Chair Mário Silveiro de BARROS, Advogado en Lisboa, Portugal Rita Brasil de BRITO, Directora-adjunta do Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, Lisboa, Portugal Bernardo BEIDERMAN, Former Penal Law Professor, University of Buenos Aires, Argentina; ISSD Regional Secretary-General for Latin America – Session Chair Camilla BERIA di ARGENTINE, Directeur général du Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale, Milan, Italie Pierre-Henri BOLLE, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit et de procédure pénale de l'Université de Neuchâtel, Suisse; Vice-président de la SIDS – Session Chair Myriam BLUMBERG-MOKRI, Docteur en droit, Avocat à la Cour d'Appel de Paris, France; Cabinet Herbert Smith – Speaker Guido BRIGNONE, Vice-président du Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale, Milan, Italie Edmondo BRUTI LIBERATI, Substitut du Procureur général près la Cour d'Appel de Milan, Italie; Secrétaire général de la SIDS Mota CAMPOS, Secrétaire d'Etat adjoint à la Ministre de la Justice du Portugal Adolfo CERETTI, Professeur associé de criminologie à l’Université de Milano-Bicocca, Italie; Secrétaire général adjoint de la SIDS – Speaker Mariano Alberto CIAFARDINI, Under-Secretary of Criminal Policy and Penitentiary Affairs, Buenos Aires, Argentina – Speaker Paulo José DA COSTA, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit pénal à la Faculté de droit de l'Université de São Paulo, Brésil; Secrétaire général régional de la SIDS pour l’Amérique Latine Manuel DA COSTA ANDRADE, Professeur à la Faculté de droit de l'Université de Coimbra – Speaker Francesco D'ALESSANDRO, Université Catholique du Sacré Coeur, Milan, Italie Jorge DE FIGUEIREDO DIAS, Président du Conseil scientifique de la Faculté de droit de l'Université de Coimbra, Portugal; Vice-président de la SIDS – Speaker António DELICADO, Consultor jurídico, Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, Lisboa, Portugal Pedro Simões DIAS, Advogado en Lisboa, Portugal Hermann FEINER, Chairman, European Police Union – EPU, Vienna, Austria 20 Les participants au Congrès Fernando FRAGOSO, Professeur de droit pénal; Avocat criminel, Rio de Janeiro, Brésil Malgorzata FUSZARA, Dr. Hab., Institute of Applied Social Sciences and Resocialisation, Warsaw University, Poland Gustavo GHIDINI, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit industriel et directeur de l'Observatoire sur la propriété intellectuelle, la concurrence et les télécommunications de l'Université Luiss de Rome, Italie – Speaker Giovanni Battista GRAMATICA, Lawyer in Genova; ISSD Board Member Lodewik H.C. HULSMAN, Professor Emeritus of Penal Law, Nederlande Economische Hogeschool, Rotterdam, The Netherland; ISSD Board Member Ida HYDLE, Associate Professor, Agder University College, Arendal, Norway Giulio ILLUMINATI, Professor of Criminal Procedure, University of Bologna, Italy Gaetano INSOLERA, Professor of Penal Law, University of Macerata, Italy Lazaros KOEMTZOPOULOS, Conseiller de la Cour d'Appel de Thessalonique, Grèce Jacek KURCZEWSKI, Professor, Dr. Hab., Faculty of Applied Social Sciences and Resocialisation, Warsaw University, Poland William S. LAUFER, Associate Professor of Legal Studies and Sociology; Director, The Carol and Lawrence Zicklin Center for Business Ethics Research, The Wharton School; Associate Director, Jerry Lee Center of Criminology, University of Pennsylvania, USA – Speaker Paula Meira LOURENÇO, Advogada en Lisboa, Portugal Paulo Saragoça da MATTA, Consultor jurídico, Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, Lisboa, Portugal Luciana MARSELLI MILNER, Trésorier de la SIDS Rui MOREIRA, Procurador adjunto do Ministerio Publico, Lisboa, Portugal Tadashi MORISHITA, Professeur émérite de l’Université de Hiroshima, Japan; Secrétaire général régional de la SIDS pour l’Asie Rui Manuel MOURA RAMOS, Juge du Tribunal de 1ère instance des Communautés européennes – Speaker Martin NETTESHEIM, Professor, Faculty of Law, University of Tübingen, Germany – Speaker Osamu NIIKURA, Professor, Aoyama Gakuin University; Representative of the Science Council of Japan Alberto NOSENZO, Judge at the Milan Court, Italy – Co-Speaker Les participants au Congrès 21 Fausto POCAR, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit international de l'Université de Milan, Italie; Juge du Tribunal pénal international pour l'ExYougoslavie – Speaker Livia POMODORO, Secrétaire général du Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale, Milan, Italie; Secretary and Standing Coordinator of the Functional and Resource Committees, ISPAC; Président du Tribunal pour Enfants de Milan – Session Chair Domenico PULITANÒ, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit pénal, Université de Milano-Bicocca, Italie Serena QUATTROCOLO, Université de Turin, Italy Miguel ROMÃO, Consultor jurídico, Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, Lisboa, Portugal Simone ROZES, Premier président honoraire de la Cour de Cassation de France; ancien Avocat général de la Cour des Communautés Europénnes; Président de la SIDS Leon SHELEFF, Professor, Tel Aviv University, Faculty of Law, Israel Giuseppe SPAGNOLO, Professor and Holder of the Chair of Penal Law, Department for the Study of Penal Law, University of Bari, Italy Arpad Laszlo SZOCS, Department of Criminology, «Eötvos Lörand» University, Budapest, Hungary João TIAGO SILVEIRA, Director do Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, Lisboa, Portugal Aglaia TSITSOURA, Former Head Division of Crime Problems, Council of Europe; Lecturer at Panteion University, Athens, Greece; ISSD Board Member Antonio VERCHER, Supreme Court Public Prosecutor, Madrid, Spain – Speaker Eduardo VETERE, Director, Centre for International Crime Prevention, United Nations Office for Drug Control and Crime Prevention Joaquim VOGEL, Professor and Holder of the Chair of Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure II, University of Tübingen, Germany; Judge at the High Court of Appeal Criminal Chambers, Stuttgart – Speaker Constantin VOUYOUCAS, Professeur émérite de droit pénal de l'Université Aristote de Thessalonique, Grèce; Vice-président de la SIDS et Président de sa Section hellénique Nobuhito YOSHINAKA, Associate Professor, Hiroshima University, Japan Vassilios ZISSIADIS, Professeur de procédure pénale, Université Aristote de Thessalonique, Grèce; Secrétaire général de la Section hellénique de la SIDS COMMENTAIRE DU THEME DU CONGRES Le Congrès examinera le rôle du droit pénal dans la protection des générations futures contre certains risques nouveaux (risques de santé, nuisances, atteintes au milieu naturel, risques de nature économique, etc...) Plusieurs problèmes se posent: d’une part le problème de la légitimité (et, à quel degré) des délits-obstacles (abstrakte Gefährdungsdelikte), dont la réponse se situe entre prévention et répression, d’autre part le problème de la détermination des intérêts et des biens à protéger (la reconnaissance de biens sociaux distincts de l'individu renforce-t-elle la protection des personnes?), enfin, le droit pénal doit-il se limiter au cas individuel ou peut-on envisager une orientation de type «macro», dans le sens que son intervention apparaît plus limitée que celle du droit administratif qui établit des contrôles et des interdictions de portée générale à l'égard de tous les citoyens (alors que le droit pénal ne vise que les délinquants). Une attention particulière sera portée sur les défis de la mise en jeu de la responsabilité pénale: nouvelles alternatives et limites, nouvelles formes et nouveaux objectifs. Cette conception élargie de la responsabilité pénale classique répond au phénomène souvent décrit par la sociologie moderne de la collectivisation de la vie sociale contemporaine. Pris dans son sens vertical et partant de la division du travail, (et de ses tâches), on constate qu’il n’existe plus de responsable pénal dans l’entreprise dès lors que le travailleur ne remplit pas les conditions légales prévues pour qualifier l’auteur de l’infraction (producteur ou exportateur, etc...) et que les patrons ou dirigeants ne sont pas les auteurs matériels des faits reprochés par la loi. D’où l'idée de ne pas renvoyer seulement les personnes physiques devant les juridictions, mais aussi les entreprises (personne morale). Pris dans son sens horizontal, la globalisation des relations internationales a conduit à considérer que l'infraction n'est pas réalisée dans un seul pays, mais résulte de divers faits commis dans plusieurs états. D’où l'idée classique de coopération et d’entraide judiciaire (qui néanmoins présuppose la réalisation «complète» dans un pays déterminé) et la «création» d’une «entité économique» capable, 24 Commentaire du theme du Congrès au plan juridique, de comprendre la dispersion des activités entre plusieurs pays, le choix étant adopté en fonction de diverses considérations: concurrence, fiscalité, etc... Cette conception des activités économiques ci-dessus décrite pourrait aussi s’appliquer à d’autres domaines tels ceux de l’atteinte à l’environnement, de la biogénétique, et de la responsabilité liée aux produits dangereux ou défectueux, domaine dans lequel la relation entre responsabilité pénale et responsabilité civile pose de délicates questions puisque le plus souvent on est en présence de fautes de négligence qui relèvent de la loi civile. En ce qui concerne la protection des générations futures susceptibles de supporter les risques et les menaces de génocides, de guerres et de toutes sortes de discriminations, le Congrès propose d’analyser les mécanismes propres à apporter des remèdes, notamment au travers des instruments offerts par les Cours Pénales Internationales et les Commissions de Réconciliation. Ces perspectives nouvelles, ouvertes aux droits fondamentaux par la Charte Européenne lancée récemment à Nice, feront l’objet de discussions approfondies. 25 OVERVIEW OF THE THEME OF THE CONGRESS The Congress will focus on the role of Criminal Law in its specific reference to the protection of coming generations against a number of new risks – risks of health, of the environment, of the economy, etc. Several problems arise: on the one hand, the problem of the legitimacy (and to what degree) of crime-obstacles (abstrakte Gefährdungsdelikte ), which occur between prevention and repression; on the other hand, the problem of the determination of the interests and juridical assets to be protected (does the recognition of supra-individual, social assets enhance the protection of the individual?); finally, should criminal law focus exclusively on the intervention in the individual case, or might it have recourse to a «macro» orientation, in this sense that its intervention could be more limited than that of administrative law, which establishes strict controls and prohibitions of general application applicable to all citizens (whereas criminal law only deals with offenders). Particular focus will be given to the new challenges facing criminal liability: new alternatives and limits, new forms and new goals. Such dilution, or broadening of the scope of classic criminal liability, is in response to the phenomenon, often described by modern sociology, of the collectivisation of social life today. Taken in the vertical sense, and starting from the division of labour (and of its tasks), there is no longer a 'central' figure to charge with liability within the company, since the company worker does not meet the legal requirements to qualify as the author of a crime (producer, exporter, etc.) and company directors or executives themselves are not the material authors of the facts contested in law. Hence the idea of not (only) referring natural persons, but (also) corporate entities to a criminal court. Taken in the horizontal sense, globalisation of international relations has meant that a criminal offence is no longer perpetrated in just one country, but rather is made up of diverse facts carried out by different entities in several countries. Hence the classic idea of mutual judicial co-operation (which nevertheless presupposes that a crime has been 'completely' committed in one given country) and the modern 'construction' of an 'economic entity' to encompass, on the juridical plane, the dispersion of activities over several countries, a choice adopted for reasons of competition, taxation etc. Such dilution of criminal liability described above to envisage economic activities would also apply to issues such as destruction of the environment, problems posed by biogenetics and liability for hazardous or defective products, an area where the relation between criminal and civil 26 Overview of the Theme of the Congress liability is a delicate question since, being often a case of negligence, it falls within the scope of civil law. With regard to protecting future generations that will bear the risks and threat of genocide, war and all kinds of discrimination, the Congress proposes to analyse possible remedial mechanisms, namely through the instruments provided by the International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions. The new perspectives opened up to fundamental human rights by the European Charter recently launched in Nice will also be a focus of discussion. PROGRAMME DU CONGRES PROGRAMME OF THE CONGRESS • Friday, 17 May 2002 Opening Session /Séance inaugurale Addresses by/Allocutions: Simone ROZÈS, ISSD President Eduardo VETERE, Director, Centre for International Crime Prevention, United Nations Office for Drug Control and Crime Prevention Mota CAMPOS, Secrétaire d'Etat adjoint à la Ministre de la Justice du Portugal General Introductory Report/Rapport général introductif: Jorge DE FIGUEIREDO DIAS, Vice-président de la SIDS; Président du Conseil scientifique de la Faculté de droit de l'Université de Coimbra, Portugal I. PROBLEMS POSED BY DEVELOPMENT AND THE EVOLVING SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH (DIFFERENT KINDS OF HARMS, GENETIC ENGINEERING AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPM ENT)/LES PROBLEMES POSES PAR LE DEVELOPPEMENT ET PAR L'EVOLUTION DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE (NUISANCES DIVERSES, TECHNOLOGIE GENETIQUE ET DEVELOPPEMENT DURABLE) Chair/Président: Luis ARROYO ZAPATERO, Secrétaire général régional de la SIDS (pour l'Europe); Recteur de l'Université de Castilla-La Mancha, Espagne Speakers/Rapporteurs: Myriam BLUMBERG-MOKRI, Docteur en droit, Avocat à la Cour d'Appel, Paris, France Manuel DA COSTA ANDRADE, Professeur à la Faculté de droit de l'Université de Coimbra, Portugal Gustavo GHIDINI, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit industriel et directeur de l'Observatoire sur la propriété intellectuelle, la concurrence et les télécommunications de l'Université LUISS de Rome, Italie Antonio VERCHER, Supreme Court Public Prosecutor, Madrid, Spain 28 • Programme of the Congress Saturday 18 May 2002 II. THE CHALLENGES OF CRIMINAL LIABILITY: NEW ALTERNATIVES AND LIMITS, NEW FORMS AND NEW GOALS/LES DEFIS DE LA RESPONSABILITE PENALE: NOUVELLES ALTERNATIVES ET LIMITES, NOUVELLES FORMES ET NOUVEAUX OBJECTIFS Chair/Président: Pierre-Henri BOLLE, Vice-président de la SIDS; titulaire de la Chaire de droit et de procédure pénale de l'Université de Neuchâtel, Suisse Speakers/Rapporteurs: Mariano CIAFARDINI, Secretary of Criminal Policy and Penitentiary Affairs, Ministry of Justice, Buenos Aires, Argentina William S. LAUFER, Associate Professor of Legal Studies and Sociology; Director, The Carol and Lawrence Zicklin Center for Business Ethics Research, The Wharton School; Associate Director, Jerry Lee Center of Criminology, University of Pennsylvania, USA Joaquim VOGEL, Professor and Holder of the Chair of Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure II, University of Tübingen; Judge at the High Court of Appeal Criminal Chambers, Stuttgart, Germany III. THE CHARTER OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS OF THE EUROPEAN UNION /LA CHARTE DES DROITS FONDAMENTAUX DE L'UNION EUROPEENNE Chair/Président: Livia POMODORO, Secrétaire général du Centro nazionale di prevenzione e difesa sociale; Président du Tribunal pour Enfants de Milan, Italie Speakers/Rapporteurs: Rui Manuel MOURA RAMOS, Professeur à la Faculté de droit de l'Université de Coimbra, Portugal; Juge du Tribunal de 1ère instance des Communautés européennes Martin NETTESHEIM, Professor at the Faculty of Law, University of Tübingen, Germany General Assembly of ISSD Members/Assemblée plénière des Membres de la SIDS Official Dinner given by the Ministry of Justice of Portugal/Dîner officiel offert par le Ministère de la Justice du Portugal Programme of the Congress • 29 Sunday 19 May 2002 IV. INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL COURTS AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSIONS: SUITABLE RESPONSES TO THREATS OF WARS, GENOCIDES OR DISCRIMINATIONS FACING COMING GENERATIONS/COURS PENALES INTERNATIONALES ET COMMISSIONS DE RECONCILIATION: REPONSES ADAPTEES AUX MENACES DE GUERRES, GENOCIDES OU DISCRIMINATIONS PESANT SUR LES GENERATIONS FUTURES Chair/Président: Bernardo BEIDERMAN, Secrétaire général régional de la SIDS (pour l'Amérique Latine); Former Penal Law Professor, University of Buenos Aires, Argentina Speakers/Rapporteurs: Adolfo CERETTI, Professor of Criminology, Faculty of Law, MilanoBicocca University, Italy; ISSD Assistant-Secretary-General and Alberto NOSENZO, Judge, Milan Court, Italy Fausto POCAR, Professeur titulaire de la Chaire de droit international à l'Université de Milan, Italie; Juge du Tribunal pénal international pour l'Ex-Yougoslavie Closing Session/Session de clôture SIMONE ROZES président de la SIDS Monsieur le Secrétaire d'État à la Justice, Monsieur le Directeur du Centre de Prévention des Crimes des Nations Unies, Mesdames et Messieurs, Mes chers amis, notre tradition nous rassemble aujourd'hui pour notre quatorzième Congrès quinquennal. Les tragiques événements du 11 Septembre nous ont contraint à quelques aménagements de temps et de lieux, mais je tiens à rendre hommage au Gouvernement portugais dont la compréhension et la générosité nous permettent de nous retrouver ici, à Lisbonne, dans ce cadre prestigieux, et de respecter ainsi la coutume observée par les Nations Unies et par chacune des quatre grandes associations qui oeuvrent dans le domaine de la criminologie et qui, vous le savez, se réunissent chaque année à tour de rôle tous les cinq ans. C'est en effet à Lecce, en Italie, voici un peu plus de cinq ans, que s'est tenu notre XIIIème Congrès. C'est le dernier auquel a participé, après l'avoir organisé avec son efficacité habituelle, notre si regretté Secrétaire général Adolfo Beria di Argentine. Permettez-moi de saluer ici sa mémoire et je suis certaine que tous ses amis ici présents conservent avec émotion et gratitude son souvenir. Nous avons promis de ne pas l'oublier et ce soir nous lui dédions ce Congrès. C'est une raison supplémentaire pour adresser de profonds et sincères remerciements aux autorités portugaises, notamment au Ministère de la Justice, à Mme le Ministre de la Justice, qui, dans une période agitée et difficile de constitution d'un gouvernement, ont maintenu leur invitation et leur soutien. J'ai le plaisir aussi de féliciter le Professeur Jorge De Figueiredo Dias, qui est le Président du Conseil scientifique de la Faculté de Droit de Coimbra et l'un des nos vice-présidents. Il lu i revient un immense mérite dans l'organisation de cette journée: il en a été la cheville ouvrière et il a en même temps accepté d'en être le Rapporteur général. Mais je voudrais aussi remercier tous ceux qui ont préparé ce Congrès et en particulier Monsieur Romao, dont le dévouement nous permet d'être ici ce soir. J'éspère que la qualité de nos travaux viendra récompenser les uns et les autres de leurs efforts, ces efforts que nous apprécions à leur valeur. 34 Séance inaugurale – Opening Session En choisissant pour thème «Défense sociale et droit pénal pour la protection des générations futures», notre mouvement affirme son souci constant d'accompagner le monde actuel et de faire preuve de vigilance à un moment où s'affrontent des forces souvent contradictoires, susceptibles de mettre en péril, si on n'y prend pas garde, les valeurs qui ont toujours été difficilement acquises. A chaque instant, la presse, la radio, la télévision, nous présentent de nouvelles découvertes, de nouvelles catastrophes, de nouveaux drames d'origine technologique, dont les conséquences, amplifiées par les techniques de communication, concernent tous les individus dans leurs biens, comme dans leur vie et dans leur santé. Les progrès de la science, qui sont et demeurent incontestables, se révèlent néanmoins porteurs d'angoisse profonde et de périls pour l'homme qui découvre ainsi son propre pouvoir sur la nature elle -même et sur ses tentations: le génie génétique nous donne – n'est-t-il pas vrai – un certain vertige. Par leurs dimensions, par leurs interactions, les activités humaines créent des risques dont l'ampleur n'est pas forcément prévisible et peuvent être porteuses de lourdes conséquences. Dans ce contexte, les mentalités du public évoluent vers une recherche de normes nationales et internationales destinées à sa protection, exigeant ainsi la mise en oeuvre de contrôles sérieux. On assiste alors à l'émergence de nouveaux principes, tel le principe de précaution, par exemple, qui n'est pas limité à l'environnement – contrairement à une idée assez souvent reçue – et face aux incertitudes des scientifiques, il est vrai que des mesures conservatoires doivent intervenir, il est vrai aussi qu'elles doivent être d’un coût acceptable. Toutes ces données traduisent bien de difficultés. Dans l'adaptation de la société à ces changements qui sont inéluctables, nous le savons, je crois que le juriste a un rôle majeur à jouer. Le symbole de la balance qui est si cher à son coeur, y tient toute sa place, car il faut en effet équilibrer les bienfaits du progrès et les risques encourus pour permettre aux générations futures de s'épanouir dans le monde nouveau. Ils paraissent bien simples à enoncer ces propos, mais ils recèlent des dangers considérables pour la liberté et la défense des valeurs essentielles qui fondent notre Mouvement de défense sociale. C'est donc, tout naturellement, en fonction de ces considérations que le thème de ce Congrès a été retenu: il s'inscrit dans une parfaite cohérence avec les précédents, qui ont tous été dévolus, sous une forme ou sous une autre, à la recherche d'une politique criminelle capable de lutter contre la délinquance au sein d'une société en constante mutation depuis le dernier conflit mondial. Aujourd'hui comme hier, il est nécessaire de tenir compte des évolutions existantes pour rechercher, parfois avec audace, toujours avec ténacité, les moyens propres à parvenir à l'équilibre auquel je faisais allusion tout Séance inaugurale – Opening Session 35 à l'heure et, pour atteindre ce but, il faut ne pas craindre d'innover dès lors que les notions classiques se révèlent inadéquates. Le domaine de la responsabilité pénale en offre un bon exemple. Le glissement du fondement sur la faute subjective vers le risque est l'un des aspects les plus signific atifs, avec pour corollaire la responsabilité des personnes morales, naguère inimaginable en raison précisément de la notion de faute, élément indispensable à la poursuite. De même, en dépit de tous les freins et de tous les obstacles, dont elle est jalonnée, la voie qui mène à l'intervention des Cours pénales internationales, chaque jour davantage, encore que bien difficile à mettre en œuvre. On peut encore signaler que la Charte des droits fondamentaux dans l'Union européenne illustre bien les exigences nouvelles de l'opinion publique en ce domaine. Le Mouvement de Défense Sociale, qui a tant inspiré de législations depuis cinquante ans, est en parfaite harmonie avec ces orientations. Les rapports qui vont être présentés et les débats qui vont suivre, j'en suis certaine, vont être riches et passionnants. L'inquiétude éprouvée face à l'héritage à transmettre aux générations futures est l’enjeu stimulant qui doit nous guider et il est bien vrai que nous désirons parvenir à surmonter les dangers réels de l'époque contemporaine et de ses bouleversements pour que les jeunes générations éprouvent le bonheur de vivre dans la paix en êtres humains résponsables. Je vous remercie. Je donne maintenant la parole à Monsieur le Directeur du Centre international pour la Prévention du Crime des Nations Unies, Monsieur Eduardo Vetere. EDUARDO VETERE Director Centre for International Crime Prevention United Nations Office for Drug Control and Crime Prevention UNODCCP Merci beaucoup, Madame Rozès. Chers amis, chers collègues, First of all, I have the honour and the pleasure to convey to all participants in the 14th Congress the best regards and the warmest gratitude of the Secretary-General of the United Nations, Mr. Kofi Annan, for your important contributions to our work, together with his best wishes for a most successful Congress. Secondly, and before touching on the issues at hand, allow me to join you, Madame Chair Person and President of the Society, in stressing the importance of continuing our work having in mind the heritage of the great founders of our movement: Filippo Grammatica and Mark Ancel, who have transmitted to us one of their most precious gifts: their humanism ! Thirdly, let me recall here – as you did, Simone – another of our great friends and unforgettable personalities, Adolfo Beria di Argentine, the former Secretary-General of the Society. To the United Nations' Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice Programme he has been one of its strongest supporters, and to me for so many years he has been a tremendous, invaluable source of inspiration: not only because he was a «fantastic magician» – to use your words, Simone – but also because he was one of the greatest catalysts for the Social Defence Movement and for criminal justice reform. There is no time here to highlight his role in the multiplicity of the activ ities in which he has been involved: from being the most gracious host of the Seventh United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders held in Milan in 1985, to organising so many of the preparatory meetings related to the topics of our quinquennial United Nations Congresses, together with the other «Big Four«, to being the Founder and First President of ISPAC. No doubt such contributions are a demonstration of his commitment to the goals and the objectives enshrined in the United Nations Charter: peace and security, justice, development and respect for human rights. It is particularly in connection with these questions that the International Society of Social Defence has made important inroads to the work of the United Nations, with a profound impact on our agendas for a number of decades, thanks to 38 Séance inaugurale – Opening Session the contributions of thinkers, reformers and scientists, among whom Adolfo Beria di Argentine has been one of the most egregious representatives!. Now, going to the substantive issue of this Congress, let me stress the importance of sustainable development and the role of criminal law. When we speak of sustainable development we all recall the Bruntland Report, according to which development should meet «the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs». A process of change in which the exploitation of resources, the direction of investments, the orientation of technological development and institutional change are all in harmony, having both current and future potential to meet human needs and aspirations. The central rationale for sustainable development has been to increase people standards of living, especially the well-being of the least advantaged people in societies, thus avoiding indiscriminate future costs. While tremendous progress has been made during the last decades, as various United Nations Conferences have noted, still much remains to be done, and the role of criminal law can be crucial – as is the case, for example, of environmental protection. The other topics that you are going to consider today, as the main issues covered by the previous Congresses of the International Society of Social Defence – I just remember «marginalization» in Caracas and «urbanisation» in Thessaloniki – are evidence of your global vision in connection with some of these crucial issues. And of course, when we speak of development, and we look at the current technological progress, we have to acknowledge that technology has marked our times, having a remarkable impact on our life patterns, and thus helping to build prosperity, by making it easier and more comfortable for the people of this world to manage their time, their business, their travel and their work. However, it is also true that technology has given rise to new risks to the health and the security of individuals, creating also new challenges to domestic, transborder and transnational crime control. In short, there are new risks which derive from the current advances in technologies, risks which have to be studied, evaluated and interpreted, in order to look at their legal, economic, psychological and social implications. This applies also to the other issues you are going to discuss: When, for example, we look at the last topic related to the International Criminal Court, we should recall that many members of the Society have been closely associated with this issue. This is particularly rewarding, considering that just a few weeks ago the Statute of the International Criminal Court has entered into force. No doubt, while technological changes may create new risks, and while today's life of globalization is Séance inaugurale – Opening Session 39 creating new problems, the international community is also showing its resolve in order to deal more appropriately at the global level with such problems, as the establishment of the International Criminal Court clearly shows. The fact that its Statute has been ratified by more than 60 countries, and that soon the Court will become operational, is further evidence of both the resolve and the commitment of the international community. This does not constitute an isolated example as in the field of crime prevention and criminal justice other tremendous progresses have been made. We were six years ago in Lecce discussing about corruption and nobody could think that, in very few years, the international community would be ready to start negotiating a comprehensive Convention against corruption. However, this is today's reality! Work has already started in Vienna last January by an Ad Hoc Committee which was established by the General Assembly, to negotiate a new Convention against corruption. A very comprehensive instrument touching both public and private corruption, including conflict of interest is under consideration, with many countries presenting concrete proposals and texts. All this is a good sign that the international community is not only ready to start seriously this work, but most likely to succeed in completing its task in the two-year time that was given to it by the General Assembly. Why two years? Because in two years we were also able to successfully complete the negotiation process of another very important convention, with three additional protocols. I am speaking of the Convention against Transnational Organised Crime, which was negotiated in 1999 and 2000, culminating in the HighLevel Ministerial Conference in Palermo in December 2000, during which a record number of 121 countries signed this new instrument. During the last year, since December 2000, the number of signatures has increased to 141 and, at the moment, 13 countries have also ratified the Convention. Accordingly, we do hope that, within the next year, we will have the 40 ratifications required for the Convention to enter into force, so that the Conference of Parties can start its work of reviewing and monitoring its implementation. These are just the most emblematic examples of how the international community, through its intergovernmental machinery, has given follow-up to several of the recommendations which have emerged from your meetings, from your congresses, from your very important contributions. And I would like now, as I started in conveying to you the greetings of Kofi Annan, to conclude my short address by quoting some of his words from his Nobel lecture, when he received the Nobel Prize. He said: 40 Séance inaugurale – Opening Session «Today's real borders are not between nations but between powerful and powerless, free and fettered, privileged and humiliated. Today no walls can separate humanitarian or human rights cases in one part of the world from national security crisis in the other. New threats make no distinction between races, nations or regions …. a new sense of insecurity has entered every mind, regardless of wealth and status. A deeper awareness of the bond that binds all of us, in pain as in prosperity, has grippled young and old». The coming generations, those for the benefit of whom the International Society of Social Defence is celebrating this 14th International Congress, have the right to expect a better future, a future with a new, more profound and more viable framework for development, where crime prevention measures can play their role as a tool of a strengthened, more modern and more human application of the rule of law. Thank you very much for your attention. MOTA CAMPOS Secrétaire d'Etat adjoint à la Ministre de la Justice du Portugal Madame Simone Rozès, Presidente da Sociedade Internacional de Defesa Social para uma Política Criminal Humanista, permita-me desde já dirigir-lhe uma calorosa saudação e exprimir o prazer e a honra que o Governo português tem em acolher o XIV Congresso da vossa organização. Senhor Vice-Presidente, Senhor Secretário-Geral da Sociedade Internacional de Defesa Social, Senhor Director do Centro de Prevenção Criminal das Nações Unidas, Senhoras e Senhores Procuradores, Ilustres Magistrados, Professores e Advogados, Minhas Senhoras e meus Senhores, é uma honra estar presente nesta sessão de abertura do XIV Congresso de Defesa Social, uma iniciativa da Sociedade Internacional de Defesa Social para uma Política Criminal Humanista em cooperação com o Centro de Prevenção Criminal das Nações Unidas, organizado sob os auspícios do Ministério da Justiça de Portugal. Congratulo-me pelo facto de a SIDS ter tomado a iniciativa de organizar este importante Congresso em Portugal e ainda pela pertinência e actualidade dos temas escolhidos para debate durante os próximos dois dias e meio, nomeadamente os que incidirão sobre os mecanismos destinados à protecção das gerações futuras quanto às ameaças de genocídio, guerras e diferentes formas de discriminação. A recente Carta Europeia dos Direitos Fundamentais e os diferentes Tribunais Penais Internacionais e Comissões de Reconciliação fazem advir avanços significativos nesta área. Com efeito, os chamados Tribunais Penais Internacionais ad hoc colocaram definitivamente na agenda internacional a questão da justiça penal internacional e da necessidade de ser posto fim à impunidade dos responsáveis por violações graves do Direito Internacional Humanitário e dos Direitos Humanos. Contudo, estes tribunais têm competências limitadas e uma natureza reactiva, uma vez que foram constituídos como resposta a crimes praticados depois de ocorridas as tragédias, massacres e violações sistemáticas dos Direitos Humanos e do Direito Humanitário num determinado território ou Estado. Temos de considerar que, neste contexto, a adopção do Estatuto de Roma do Tribunal Penal Internacional constituíu um marco histórico para o Text not revised by the Author 42 Séance inaugurale – Opening Session Direito Penal Internacional. O Tribunal Penal Internacional estabelece pela primeira vez um enquadramento universal destinado a pôr fim à impunidade pela prática de crimes como o genocídio, os cimes contra a Humanidade e os crimes de guerra. Regozijo-me, pois, com a proximidade da entrada em vigor do Estatuto do Tribunal e ainda pelo facto de Portugal se encontrar entre o conjunto de sessenta Estados pioneiros que permitirão esta entrada em vigor no próximo dia 1 de Julho. O Tribunal Penal Internacional é uma inspiração para este novo século e um mecanismo incontornável quando nos referimos à protecção das gerações vindouras, que constitui o motivo inspirador deste congresso. Quanto ao tema da impunidade, o Tribunal contribuirá para impor o respeito pelas regras básicas do Direito Internacional, reforçará o primado do direito e constituirá um contributo, porventura decisivo, para uma melhor e mais sã convivência internacional. Para terminar, parece-me que não podemos esquecer o desafio que a existência deste tribunal coloca a todos os Estados que dele virão a fazer parte. No que diz respeito à sua aplicação efectiva, nomeadamente através da adopção de legislação para a cooperação com o Tribunal e destinada a incorporar os crimes previstos no Estatuto a nível nacional. Desejo, portanto, a este XIV Congresso o melhor sucesso e um trabalho profícuo. Muito obrigado pela vossa atenção. O PAPEL DO DIREITO PENAL NA PROTECÇÃO DAS GERAÇÕES FUTURAS JORGE DE FIGUEIREDO DIAS Vice-Presidente da Société internationale de défense sociale pour une politique criminelle humaniste Professor Catedrático da Faculdade de Direito da Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal I. A questão do papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras constitui um problema novo e controvertido. Ele põe em causa não aspectos parcelares e de pormenor das concepções político-criminais estabelecidas, mas nada menos que os fundamentos e a legitimação da intervenção penal, a idoneidade dos seus instrumentos, os caminhos do labor jurídico-científico que sobre ela se exerce. Se indagarmos da razão por que até há poucos anos atrás a questão não era sequer posta e por que ela se tornou bruscamente numa «questão do destino» do direito penal, a resposta é incontroversa. Assistimos ao advento de uma forma nova de sociedade, que assumiu o significado de uma «ruptura epocal» ( 1) com um passado ainda recente, face à ameaça global causada por novos e grandes riscos, por «riscos globais»( 2), que pesam sobre a humanidade: o risco atómico, a diminuição da camada de ozono e o aquecimento global, a destruição dos ecossistemas, a engenharia e a manipulação genéticas, a produção maciça de produtos perigosos ou defeituosos, a criminalidade organizada dos «senhores do crime», individuais e colectivos – que dominam à escala planetária o tráfico de armas e de droga, de órgãos e dos próprios seres humanos –, o terrorismo nacional, regional e internacional, o genocídio, os crimes contra a paz e a humanidade. Com isto ( 3), é um choque antropológico brutal que estamos a sofrer, devido ao colapso iminente dos (1) A expressão é de STELLA, (2001), Giustizia e modernità, Prefazione. Sobre eles, na esteira do pensamento de BECK, Risikogesellschaft. Auf dem Weg in eine andere Moderne, 1986 e Was ist Globalisierung? Irrtümer des Globalismus − Antworten auf Globalisierung, 1997, v. FIGUEIREDO D IAS , «O direito penal entre a ‘sociedade industrial’ e a sociedade do risco’, in: Estudos em Homenagem ao Prof. Doutor Rogério Soares, 2001, p. 583. A generalidade das considerações aí feitas perpassará por toda a exposição posterior. (3) Acompanho de novo STELLA, (nota 1). (2) 46 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras instrumentos técnico-institucionais de segurança. Choque tornado ainda mais dramático porque talvez descortinemos os remédios radicais que a situação exige, mas não temos a coragem (ou a possibilidade...) nem de os usar, nem de requerer a sua aplicação aos níveis comunitários em que nos inserimos. Com tudo isto é, em definitivo, o valor da solidariedade que sofre inapelavelmente. Perante esta situação, ao pensamento, à ciência, à acção, exige-se que dêem passos radicais: trata-se de ganhar a consciência, porventura dolorosa, de que a crença na razão técnico-instrumental calculadora morreu(4). De uma crença filha da racionalidade que nos iluminou durante três séculos, trouxe um progresso espiritual e material espantoso à humanidade e lhe deixou um legado irrenunciável de razão crítica, de secularização, de direitos humanos; mas que ao mesmo tempo a colocou nos becos sem saída do modelo do homo œconomicus e da crença ingénua no progresso material ilimitado. Não é preciso indicar outros exemplos que o da terrível crise ecológica actual( 5) para oferecer base incontroversa a esta afirmação. Torna-se indispensável pois, neste tempo pós-moderno, uma nova ética, uma nova racionalidade, uma nova política. Porque em causa está a própria subsistência da vida no planeta e é preciso, se quisermos oferecer uma chance razoável às gerações vindouras, que a humanidade se torne em sujeito comum da responsabilidade pela vida ( 6). II. Perguntar se nesta tarefa existencial cabe algum papel ao direito penal e aos seus instrumentos na necessária defesa social perante os megariscos enunciados poderá parecer quase absurdo e sem sentido. É à filosofia que cabe pensar os caminhos necessários de superação dos paradigmas da modernidade. É às políticas, nacionais e internacional, que pertence implementar os paradigmas pós-modernos ( 7). É sobre os líderes das comunidades intermédia s que pesa o dever de promoverem a interiorização individual das novas ideias e dos novos valores. É sobre os agentes (4) Fundamental nesta direcção, STRATENWERTH, «Zukunftssicherung durch die Mitteln des Strafrechts», Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechyswissenschaft (=ZStW) 105, 1993, p.679. E do mesmo Das Strafrecht in der Krise der Industriegeselschaft, Rektoratsrede, 1993. (5) Recorde-se o impressionante livro de RACHEL CARSON, Silent spring. (6) Importante sobre este ponto A NSELMO BORGES , (2000), «O crime ecológico na perspectiva filosófico-teológica», Revista Portuguesa de Ciência Criminal (=RPCC) 10, p. 7. (7) De novo BECK, (1991), Politik in der Risikogesellscaft, p. 23 e s. O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras 47 económicos e sociais que recai a necessidade – para satisfação também dos seus próprios interesses egoístas! – de se auto-organizarem e autolimitarem. É numa palavra, uma vez postas as coisas ao nível da intervenção jurídica, a tese – hoje assaz difundida – da auto-regulação social como forma por excelência, se não a única viável, de oferecer um futuro à humanidade perante os novos e grandes riscos que sobre ela pesam(8). É a predição de que o Direito perderá a palavra na sociedade do futuro; numa sociedade onde tanto no domínio dos princípios, como no dos efeitos ou consequências não haverá mais lugar para um pensamento que, como o mocho, levanta voo só ao anoitecer, que deixa as coisas acontecer para depois tentar remediá -las e cuja intervenção é por isso por essência retrospectiva e não prospectiva, conservadora e não propulsora, aniquiladora e não protectora das vítimas do sistema, que somos todos nós. Não parece todavia que esta ideia da auto-regulação social atinja sequer os limiares da utopia (9), antes é bem possível que nela se trate de um equívoco. Uma verdadeira auto-regulação significaria pedir ao mercado – na verdade, o mais autêntico produtor das dificuldades e desesperanças da sociedade técnica industrial – o remédio para a doença que ele próprio inoculou. Uma verdadeira auto-regulação implicaria pedir a milhões e milhões de pessoas que se decidissem voluntariamente a renunciar a todo um modelo de vida que fez do consumo o seu próprio motor e do aumento da produção o orientador de quase todo o conhecimento. E que para alcançar esse desiderato se serviria da eliminação de toda a heteroregulamentação e do elemento de coacção que inevitavelmente a acompanha, conduzindo deste modo à prescindibilidade já não apenas do direito penal, mas de todo o Direito. III. Não falta porém quem pense que uma protecção efectiva das gerações vindouras não exige ir tão longe e pode ainda conservar a função social do Direito; o que ela impõe, isso sim – diz-se no entanto com cada vez maior insistência –, é que se recuse ao direito penal um papel na tarefa. É a velha tese da «abolição» do direito penal que sob esta capa de novo se perfila. Para além dos meios de política social não jurídica, assim se (8) Sobre esta tese e, em definitivo, mostrando-se a ela favorável no que toca à contenção dos grandes e novos riscos, STELLA, (nota 1), pp. 387 e ss., 414 e ss. (9) Sobre o valor positivo da «utopia» também nos domínios da ciência do direito penal e da política criminal A LBERTO SILVA FRANCO, (2000), «Globalização e criminalidade dos poderosos», RPCC 10, pp. 183 e ss., 227 e s. 48 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras argumenta, haverá que fazer intervir meios jurídicos não penais no esforço de contenção e domínio dos riscos globais, nos quadros daquilo que se vai chamando o «Estado-prevenção». A ideia subjacente a esta tese nutre-se do reconhecimento de que a função do Direito de criador de normas de orientação social e de comportamento individual é indispensável à conservação e desenvolvimento de qualquer sociedade, do presente ou do futuro, e que para ela não existe alternativa. Mas também da convicção de que é impossível ao direito penal desempenhar qualquer papel na contenção de fenómenos globais e de massa. Impossibilidade que derivaria da especificidade dos seus meios de actuação (as penas e as medidas de segurança) e dos seus modelos de aferição da responsabilidade, tendentes à individualização da responsabilidade e zeladores até ao limite de direitos das pessoas que se afirmam perante o Estado e, se necessário, contra o Estado(10). Por isso – diz-se – há que conferir a outros ramos de direito a tarefa de oferecer às gerações vindouras hipóteses acrescidas de subsistência e de progresso. Logo ao direito civil, muito mais indulgente que o direito penal na aferição da responsabilidade e muito menos exigente na sua individualização; e de resto, como direito privado, particularmente adequado ao tratamento de questões que, na sua grande maioria, emergem do «mercado» e têm nele a sua origem. Mas sobretudo ao direito administrativo – porventura intensificado na sua vertente sancionatória, em nome de um Interventionsrecht(11) –, a quem cabe por excelência, dada a sua natureza de braço executivo da própria Administração, a ponderação de milhares e milhares de situações conflituantes entre os interesses mais vitais da soc iedade e os legítimos interesses dos administrados; e que por isso estará em posição inigualável para levar a cabo uma política de prevenção dos riscos globais. Não negarei o papel fundamental – e em certas situações insubstituível – que a estes ramos de direito deve conferir-se na tentativa de resolução do problema. Mas julgo infundado o propósito de com eles esgotar o papel que ao Direito cabe na matéria; e, sobretudo, de com eles (10) Sobre esta tese − cara à que hoje é chamada «Escola de Frankfurt» − HASSEMER, (1992), «Kennzeichen und Krisen des modernen Strafrechts», Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik , p. 10 e «Perspectivas del Derecho penal futuro», Revista Penal 1, 1997, p. 37; e também HERZOG, «Limites del derecho penal para controlar los riesgos sociales», Poder Judicial 32, 1993 e «Algunos riesgos del derecho penal del riesgo», Revista Penal 4, 1999, p. 54. (11) De novo HASSEMER, Revista Penal (nota 8), p. 40. O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras 49 substituir a função diferenciada que ao direito penal deve pertencer. É indiscutível que a força conformadora dos comportamentos do direito civil e do direito administrativo é menor do que a do direito penal; como menor é, por isso, a força estabilizadora das expectativas comunitárias na manutenção da validade da norma violada, neste sentido, a sua força preventiva ou, mais especificamente, de «prevenção geral positiva ou de integração»( 12). Este é o fundamento último da máxima – liberal, mas simultaneamente social – da intervenção jurídico-penal como intervenção de ultima ratio. Ao que acresce que já não na prevenção, mas na repressão das violações ocorridas tanto a intervenção jurídico-civil, como a jurídicoadministrativa surgirão as mais das vezes como desajustadas, se não mesmo inúteis. E se assim é, então esta incapacidade (ou menor capacidade) de sancionamento do direito civil e do direito administrativo reflecte-se prognosticamente, com força potenc iada, sobre o efeito preventivo da norma editada e acaba por aniquilá -lo. Tanto basta, se bem cuido, para que não possa esperar-se que por estas vias viesse a lograr-se uma mais efectiva protecção das gerações vindouras. IV. Assim, pois, ao direito penal não pode negar-se a sua quotaparte de legitimação (e de responsabilidade) na protecção das gerações futuras. Reconhecê-lo, porém, implica que vejamos com a justeza e a modéstia possíveis o que dele pode e deve esperar-se. Desde logo, não faltam os que parece argumentarem baseados num equívoco( 13). Alega-se que o direito penal não constitui qualquer barreira intransponível, qualquer defesa destinada ao sucesso na prevenção e controlo dos riscos globais. Mas com este argumento se esquece que não pode ser propósito da intervenção penal alcançar uma protecção dos riscos globais em si mesmos e como um todo, nem, ainda menos, lograr a «resolução» do problema da subsistência da vida planetária. Não é nada este o problema da intervenção penal, antes sim, muito mais modestamente, um problema de ordenação (e de defesa) social; concretamente, o de oferecer o seu contributo para que os riscos globais se mantenham dentro de limites ainda comunitariamente suportáveis e, em defin itivo, não (12) Conceito, este último, usado pela primeira vez com este significado por ROXIN , (1979), «Zur jüngsten Diskussion über Schuld, Prävention und Verantwortlichkeit», Festschrift für Bockelmann, p. 305 e s. (13) Sobre o ponto que se segue FIGUEIREDO DIAS , (2001), «Sobre a tutela jurídico-penal do ambiente − Um quarto de século depois», Estudos em Homenagem a Cunha Rodrigues, I, p. 376 e ss. 50 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras ponham em causa os fundamentos naturais da vida. O que está em causa é (e é só!) a protecção – fragmentária, lacunosa e subsidiária – de bens jurídico-penais colectivos como tais. Tudo o que vá para além disto ultrapassa o fundamento legitimador da intervenção penal neste domínio. Para uma defesa global da humanidade perante os mega-riscos que a ameaçam – para a tarefa, digamos assim, de protecção global da soc iedade presente e futura – o direito penal constituiria à partida um meio democraticamente ilegítimo e, ademais, inadequado e disfunc ional. Desta consideração logo deriva outra consequência: restringida embora à tutela fragmentária de bens colectivos, a protecção que o direito penal está em medida de oferecer às gerações futuras não pode ser absoluta. Face às condições de complexidade, de massificação e de globalidade da sociedade contemporânea, às quais estão ligadas uma multiplicidade e uma diversidade inumeráveis de condutas potencialmente lesivas de valores fundamentais inerentes à própria existência do Homem, o direito penal tem de distinguir, para delimitação do âmbito de protecção da norma, entre ofensas admissíveis e ofensas inadmissíveis, limitando-se à criminalização destas últimas(14). A distinção entre ofensas admissíveis e inadmissíveis supõe assim – sobretudo nesta nossa era de mercado global – uma dificílima ponderação de interesses complexos e diversificados, quantas vezes de resultado altamente questionável. Esta ponderação, multiplicada por milhões e milhões de casos atinentes aos âmbitos e às actividades mais diversas, não pode ser levada a cabo pelo legislador penal: para tal constituiria ele de novo, sub specie materiæ, entidade incompetente. Aquela ponderação só pode caber ao direito administrativo e aos agentes competentes para a sua aplicação. O que conduz à conclusão de que a – por certos penalistas tão escarmentada – acessoriedade administrativa se apresenta neste domínio como absolutamente necessária e que para ela se não divisa alternativa. Isto dito, falta indagar se eventuais especificidades da tutela no âmbito questionado se verificam a nível do objecto da tutela, do círculo dos sujeitos responsáveis e da construção típica dos delitos dos quais se espera a protecção. Latente ficará a questão de saber se tais especificidades postulam modificações radicais das concepções dogmáticas jurídico-penais que dão corpo ao paradigma próprio das sociedades avançadas do nosso tempo; e se tais modificações, onde e na medida em que porventura se imponham, se revelam ainda compatíveis com o paradigma penal e (14) Tal como o faz, por exemplo, o art. 279º do Código Penal português relativamente ao crime de poluição. O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras 51 juspublicístico de uma sociedade democrática e liberal. A estes temas dedicarei, com a brevidade de que for capaz, as considerações seguintes. V. A questão primordial e decisiva que se suscita é a da definição do bem jurídico tutelado pelos delitos colectivos, em termos tais que consiga preservar a função de padrão crítico da incriminação que o bem jurídico tem de assumir em um direito penal democrático e liberal. A minha convicção profunda e já antiga é a de que o direito penal serve a tutela subsidiária, a par de bens jurídicos individuais, de bens jurídicos colectivos como tais. Que significa isto( 15)? 1. A afirmação feita significa certamente recusar o que por vezes se chama uma concepção administrativa do bem jurídico colectivo. Mas convém evitar equívocos. Com uma manifestação incontestável desta concepção se depararia, segundo alguns, na construção do crime contra bens jurídicos colectivos – p. ex., na do crime ambiental segundo o Código Penal português, art. 279º – como crime de desobediência; já uma tal construção revelaria uma vassalagem tão-só ao valor da fidelidade a prescrições administrativas, um puro (des)valor de acção sob a forma de violação do dever de conformidade com injunções validamente prescritas e recebidas, por conseguinte, uma concepção puramente administrativa do bem jurídico protegido. Esta crítica não tem de ser reputada procedente. Bastará para a elidir compreender que a «desobediência administrativa» pode constituir tão-só um factor limitativo em nome da certeza da proibição ou imposição penal da conduta concreta, face à já sublinhada complexidade e diversidade dos conflitos que em toda esta matéria se deparam; em nome consequentemente da clara percepção, pelos destinatários da norma, da fronteira que separa neste domínio o «admissível» do «inadmissível» de condutas que são, por sua natureza e pelas condições inevitáveis da vida contemporânea, constantes e diuturnas. 2. Face à tese acima enunciada, prejudicada fica igualmente uma concepção exasperadamente antropocêntrica dos bens jurídicos colectivos, ligada a um entendimento «monista-pessoal» do bem jurídico, hoje doutrinalmente muito preconizado (com particular insistência por Hassemer e a chamada (16) «Escola de Frankfurt»). Uma concepção, esta, que de bem (15) Sobre o que se segue, de novo, os meus artigos citados na nota 2, p. 602 e ss. e na nota 13, p. 376 e ss., com indicações bibliográficas. (16) Ao que parece pela primeira vez por SCHÜNEMANN, GA, (1995), p. 203. Cf. já supra, nota 10. 52 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras jurídico só permite em rigor falar quando estejam em causa interesses reais, tangíveis e, por consequência, também actuais do indivíduo. Como prejudicada fica igualmente uma concepção antropocêntrica moderada do bem jurídico colectivo, que conduziria a afirmar a sua existência apenas se e na medida em que a razão da tutela pudesse ainda ser reconduzida à protecção de bens jurídicos individuais; nesta acepção se exigindo que os bens jurídicos colectivos a tutelar se encontrassem de qualquer modo dotados de um «referente pessoal», possuíssem um «núcleo personalizável», fossem unicamente «dedutíveis» a partir de bens jurídicos individuais. O que parece haver de injustificável nesta limitação (e pode vir a afectar a efectividade de uma tutela penal das gerações futuras) é que, com ela, continuam a considerar-se os bens jurídicos colectivos como puros «derivados» de bens jurídicos individuais; e, deste modo, a perspectivar a protecção penal colectiva como tutela antecipada de bens jurídicos individuais, em particular os da vida, da saúde e do património de pessoas singulares e concretas. Com esta formulação uma tal tese parece incompatível com o reconhecimento de verdadeiros bens jur ídicos colectivos. Estes devem ser antes aceites, sem tergiversações, como autênticos bens jurídicos universais, transpessoais ou supra-individuais. Que também esta categoria de bens jurídicos possa reconduzir-se, em último termo, a interesses legítimos da pessoa, eis o que não será lícito contestar. O carácter supra-individual do bem jurídico não exclui decerto a existência de interesses indiv iduais que com ele convergem: se todos os membros da comunidade se vêem prejudic ados por condutas potencialmente destruidoras da vida, cada um deles não deixa individualmente de sê-lo também e de ter um interesse legítimo na preservação das condições vitais. Mas se, por exemplo, uma descarga de petróleo no mar provoca a morte de milhares de aves marinhas e leva inclusivamente à extinção de alguma espécie rara, também aí pode verificar-se a lesão de um bem jur ídico colectivo merecedor e carente de tutela penal, ainda que tais aves sejam absolutamente insusceptíveis de utilização por parte do homem. Não parece possível descortinar aqui, ao menos em via de princípio, ofensa de um qualquer bem jurídico individual, possibilidade de referência a ele ou cadeia dedutiva que a ele conduza. E todavia, as aves referidas, se bem que não «utilizáveis» por quem quer que seja, já nascido ou ainda não nascido, constituem um património de todos. Se as não protegermos as gerações futuras não terão a possibilidade de as apreciar, apesar de que nós tenhamos podido fazê-lo! 3. A verdadeira característica do bem jurídico colectivo ou universal reside pois em que ele deve poder ser gozado por todos e por cada O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras 53 um, sem que ninguém deva ficar excluído desse gozo: nesta possibilidade de gozo reside o legítimo interesse individual na integridade do bem jurídico cole ctivo. Certamente, existe neste uma relação difusa com os usuários, que porém não significa o carácter difuso do bem jurídico universal enquanto tal; como existe – há que reconhecê-lo – uma certa funcionalização da noção de bem jurídico, quando comparada com aquele «monólito jurídico corporizado»( 17) que formou a concepção acirradamente liberal do bem jurídico. Mas não é esta razão bastante para que a categoria seja recusada como jurídico-penalmente relevante. Nesta acepção os bens jurídicos colectivos devem gozar, face aos bens jurídicos individuais, de verdadeira autonomia. Autonomia que não é afectada mesmo que deva concluir-se que não existem bens jurídicos colectivos que não possuam um qualquer suporte em legítimos interesses individuais, por muito simples que eles se afigurem, como o mero prazer de contemplar o voo de uma ave marinha. A relevância dos bens jurídicos colectivos – generosos, em nada egoístas – provirá precisamente da potencial multiplicação indeterminada de interesses de toda e qualquer pessoa, se bem que não individualizáveis em concreto. VI. Assegurada a viabilidade da protecção jurídico-penal de bens jurídicos colectivos como tais, uma segunda ideia de primordial importância deve ser aqui acentuada: a de que ao direito penal não poderá reconhecer-se a mínima capacidade de contenção dos mega-riscos que ameaçam as gerações futuras se, do mesmo passo, se persistir em manter o dogma da individualização da responsabilidade penal. Já antes e independentemente do aparecimento de uma «dogmática do risco» o preconceito do carácter individual de toda a responsabilidade penal (uma vez mais, um preconceito de raiz exasperadamente antropocêntrica) havia sido abalado. E para tanto, peço licença para o afirmar, muito contribuiu a doutrina penal portuguesa, mais do que outras que só muito recentemente ultrapassaram (quando tenham já ultrapassado…) os escolhos da «incapacidade de acção» e da «incapacidade de culpa» jurídico-penais que tradicional e axiomaticamente se considerava atingirem toda a responsabilidade penal de entes não individuais. A uma protecção jurídico-penal das gerações futuras perante os mega-riscos que pesam sobre a humanidade torna-se pois indispensável a aceitação, clara e sem tergiversações, de um princípio de responsabilização (17) Feliz expressão de Verwaltungsrechtslehre, p. 224. RUPP, (1965), Grundfragen der heutigen 54 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras penal dos entes colectivos como tais. Não será, em minha opinião, com doutrinas como a do reconhecimento da validade do princípio apenas no âmbito das infracções ditas «penais-administrativas»; ou mesmo com soluções como a de imputar ao ente colectivo a acção e a culpa dos seus órgãos responsáveis; ou a de aceitar a sua responsabilidade criminal unicamente para efeito da aplicação de medidas de segurança, que não de verdadeiras penas – não será com concepções tais que aquela protecção se logrará. Isso só se torna possível, repito, aceitando que relativamente a certos delitos (e, nomeadamente, os que são próprios da «sociedade do risco») é o ente colectivo como tal que responde também ao nível do direito penal( 18). Já em 1977 defendi( 19) que tal se torna possível segundo um princípio de analogia, quero dizer, atribuindo ao ente colectivo capacidade de acção e de culpa jurídico-penais na medida em que eles são – como muito exactamente notou Max Müller invocando neste contexto o princípio da identidade da liberdade (20) – «obras do homem» e, nesta medida, «obras da sua liberdade». Com o essenc ial desta ideia da analogia depara-se em Portugal num estudo de Faria Costa (21) e na Alemanha numa importante monografia de Heine (22). Mas considere-se ou não procedente uma fundamentação deste teor, deve esperar-se que este filão não seja abandonado e, pelo contrário, seja objecto de progressos de quem consiga ir mais longe e mais fundo. Para que num futuro próximo os códigos penais não só aceitem o princípio, como sucede com o português, como o desenvolvam nas suas implicações normativas, como sucede com o francês; e para que ele passe a constituir uma aquisição consensual da vida judiciária, como de há muito sucede com os direitos penais inglês e norteamericano. Decerto, em perspectiva jurídico-penal dogmática torna-se necessário e urgente saber muito mais sobre ele, sobre as suas implicações prático-normativa, sobre as suas relações com a responsabilidade (18) Sobre cada uma destas posições, com referências bibliográficas, VOGEL, (2001), «La responsabilidad penal por el producto en Alemania: situación actual y perspectivas de futuro», Revista Penal 8 , p. 74 e nota 47. (19) FIGUEIREDO D IAS , (1977), Para uma Dogmática do Direito Penal Secundário, p. 35 e ss. (20) M AX M ÜLLER, (1959), «Freiheit», in: Staatslexikon, III, 6ª ed., p. 53. (21) FARIA COSTA, (1992), «A responsabilidade jurídico-penal da empresa e dos seus órgãos», RPCC 2 , p. 537. (22) HEINE, (1995), Die strafrechtliche Verantwortlichkeit von Unternehmen, p. 271 e ss. O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras 55 individual, sobre o catálogo das penas e medidas aplicáveis. Ver-se-á então porventura que muitos dos problemas postos pela necessidade de tutela jurídico-penal das gerações futuras podem encontrar aqui adequadas soluções, tornando menos instantes alterações, que agora podem afigurar-se urgentes e indispensáveis, na dogmática da imputação objectiva, da comprovação do dolo, da negligência e do erro, da autoria e da cumplicidade. Se por exemplo o fenómeno da chamada «criminalidade organizada», o que quer que por ela deva entender-se em perspectiva dogmática, reentra no direito penal de tutela das gerações futuras, então ele mostra exempla rmente como o progresso da dogmática relativa à responsabilidade penal dos entes colectivos constitui uma exigência instante, para a qual não existe alternativa. VII. Resta encarar a última questão das que atrás ficaram mencionadas, relativa à estrutura típica que, em geral, devem assumir os delitos contra bens jurídicos colectivos. Uma protecção penal de bens jurídicos colectivos legítima e minimamente eficaz supõe que o ilícito material dos crimes respectivos, cometidos por pessoas individuais ou por entes colectivos, seja visto como residindo na verificação de condutas que, em si mesmas consideradas ou em associação a condutas ocorridas em quantidade inumerável e com uma frequência devastadora, lesam ou põem em sério perigo aqueles bens juríd icos. Isto significa, em meu modo de ver, duas coisas(23). 1. A primeira é a de que a multiplicidade de condutas perigosas para as condições fundamentais de vida das gerações futuras, na complexidade que podem chegar a assumir e na constante modificação a que, por força da evolução tecnológica, estão submetidas, conduz efectivamente a que os delitos colectivos, como quer que em definitivo tipicamente se construam, se encontrem submetidos a uma cláusula de acessoriedade administrativa. O que vale por dizer que o conteúdo integral do ilícito só pode revelar-se, em última análise, também em função de normas sem dignidade penal. A acessoriedade administrativa suscita à dogmática jurídico-penal, é verdade, um longo cortejo de problemas, para alguns dos quais ainda mal se divisam hoje soluções consensuais. Mas também neste ponto seria salutar começar por assentar numa tão antiga, como boa verdade: a de que (23) Sobre as questões que se seguem o meu estudo (nota 13), p. 385 e ss.; e também KUHLEN, (1993), «Umweltstrafrecht – auf der Suche nach einer neuen Dogmatik», ZStW 105, p. 720 e ss. 56 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras não são as valorações político-criminais que devem subordinar-se ao labor (e às dificuldades, e às limitações em cada momento histórico) da dogmática e ser por ele condicionadas, antes sim é a dogmática, como puro meio construtivo-instrumental, que tem de servir as proposições políticocriminais e a elas se adequar. Assim postas as coisas, a construção destes delitos como substancialmente delitos contra bens jurídicos colectivos, mas formalmente como delitos de desobediência às prescrições emanadas do direito administrativo e/ou dos seus agentes, parece-me constituir a via talvez mais correcta de corresponder às necessidades de protecção das gerações futuras. De desobediência àquelas prescrições, não (se é preciso reacentuá-lo!) em nome de um mero «dever de fidelidade administrativa», mas sim na medida em que prescrições tais visem evitar a produção – mais próxima ou mais longínqua, mas em todo o caso certa ou altamente provável – de danos e lesões e, por aí, de deteriorações importantes das condições fundamentais da vida em sociedade. Que, a partir daqui, tais delitos devam ser construídos como delitos de perigo abstracto, de perigo concreto ou de perigo abstracto-concreto (de «idoneidade» ou de «aptidão»), ou mesmo como delitos de lesão, constitui já somente um problema de relevo subordinado, uma questão dogmática de segunda ordem. Até porque, seja qual for a arquitectura típica que acabe por ser eleita, não existem artifícios dogmáticos capazes de ofuscar a dificuldade real que aqui se perfila; e cuja magnitude em sede de legitimação as condições da vida social presente (e muito mais as da vida futura) tornam instante e inquestionável. A saber, a de que a «distância» entre condutas em si mesmas insignificantes e lesões certas ou prováveis do bem jurídico colectivo todavia por elas (co)determinadas, a «lonjura» entre os autores de tais condutas e o resultado lesivo – não importa se sob a forma de «resultado de lesão» ou de «resultado de perigo» –, são ou podem ser de tal maneira grandes que, com elas, é a própria referência da conduta ao bem jurídico protegido que se torna questionável; e, por via disso, são princípios democráticos e constitucionais unanimemente aceites como devendo presidir à imputação penal, objectiva e subjectiva, que parecem abeirar o colapso. 2. Essencial me parece neste contexto – e é esta a segunda ideia que me proponho acentuar – não perder nunca de vista que em direito penal colectivo nos deparamos substancialmente (isto é, insisto, segundo o conteúdo material de ilícito em questão) com delitos que possuem uma natureza análoga à da categoria dos delitos de perigo abstracto; delitos nos quais, é bem sabido, a relação entre a acção e o bem jurídico tutelado surgirá as mais das vezes como longínqua, nebulosa e quase sempre O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras 57 particularmente débil. Se apesar disso se aceita a legitimidade jurídicoconstitucional desta espécie de delitos – como creio dever aceitar-se(24), suposto que se encontrem respeitados em espécie os parâmetros mínimos de determinabilidade do tipo de ilícito e a referência ao bem jurídico que em última instância se visa proteger –, a questão que então se coloca é a de saber se o aludido «enfraquecimento», em matéria de direito penal colectivo, da relação entre acção e bem jurídico não tem de ir, para que a tutela dispensada por um tal direito se revele minimamente eficaz, demasiado longe e não obriga, por isso, a aceitar «estruturas novas e atípicas de imputação» particularmente questionáveis (quando não censuráveis) à luz dos princípios jurídico-constitucionais próprios do Estado de Direito. A dificuldade não se desvanecerá, nem sequer se minorará, pela circunstância de que o delito colectivo seja tipicamente estruturado e dogmatic amente construído como crime de dano antes que de perigo, como crime de resultado antes que de mera actividade. O que nesta problemática substancial está em jogo não é a relação naturalística entre acção e objecto da acção, mas a relação normativa entre acção e bem jurídico. Aqui julgo residir mais uma razão em favor da construção do delito colectivo como delito de desobediência a prescrições ou limitações impostas, de acordo com a lei, pelas autoridades administrativas competentes; com a precisão (essencial e imprescindível) de que tais prescrições ou limitações são editadas em nome de uma tutela de bens jurídicos com suficiente relevância para se arvorarem em bens colectivos jurídico-penais. Torna-se de todo o modo instante perguntar se, apesar do que ficou já dito, não persiste como questionável a relação entre a lesão do bem jurídico colectivo e uma multidão inumerável de comportamentos que, quando tomados em si mesmos e na sua singularidade, não são imediatamente perigosos ou sequer mesmo significativos, mas contribuem em todo o caso poderosamente para aquela lesão. Aqui se depara, de modo incontornável, com a necessidade de considerar muitas das ofensas colectivas jurídico-penalmente relevantes dentro dos quadros dos tipos chamados aditivos ou cumulativos. Seguro é que, quanto aos comportamentos susceptíveis de integrarem o fim de protecção da norma penal a sua punição só se revelará legítima se as condutas que venham a somar-se à do agente e que contribuem assim para a lesão forem, mais que (24) E é doutrina do Tribunal Constitucional português : Acórdãos do tribunal Constitucional 30, (1995), p. 985. 58 O papel do direito penal na protecção das gerações futuras possíveis, indubitavelmente previsíveis e muito prováveis, para não dizer certas. Toco, com esta observação, o ponto que se revela certamente mais difícil, mas simultaneamente mais essencial. É ao legislador ordinário e só a ele que, dentro dos referidos parâmetros jurídico-constitucionais, pertence ponderar e decidir a questão político-legislativa de saber se, para uma tutela dos bens jurídicos cole ctivos (ou de certos deles) minimamente eficaz, se torna necessário punir comportamentos em razão da sua provável acumulação e quais deles devem ser puníveis. Esta é a decisão verdadeiramente difícil e que tem de ser cuidadosamente ponderada, nomeadamente em função das aquisições parcelares definitivas que vão sendo feitas pela Ciência. Uma vez, porém, tomada a decisão relativamente a certos (ou a certas espécies de) comportamentos, não tem qualquer sentido agitar a crítica de que uma responsabilização por comportamentos aditivos ou cumulativos significaria sempre uma responsabilização penal por facto de outrem absolutamente incompatível com o princípio da culpa. Como igualmente me parece dispensável excogitar ou acolher estruturas anómalas ou atípicas de imputação, objectiva e subjectiva, da responsabilidade penal: resultados dogmaticamente aceitáveis podem ser conseguidos com estruturas já doutrinalmente consolidadas, desde as da doutrina da adequação às da criação de um risco não permitido, desde as do dolo e do erro às da negligência. Neste sentido acabo por me aproximar, de certo modo, da ideia segundo a qual a tutela jurídico-penal das gerações futuras passa pela assunção de um direito penal do comportamento em que são penalizadas e punidas puras relações da vida como tais ( 25). Dizendo-o, porém, não desejo – como espero ter podido deixar claro – apresentar esta concepção como uma alternativa ao direito penal do bem jurídico. Bem ao contrário, quero significar que a punição imediata de certa espécie de comportamentos como tais é feita em nome da tutela de bens jurídicos colectivos e só nesta medida se encontra legitimada. Deste modo julgando manter-me ainda fiel ao paradigma jurídico-penal iluminista que nos acompanha e que confio que possa continuar a ser fonte de desenvolvimentos e de progressos mesmo no seio da «sociedade do risco»; e que possa por isso continuar a assumir o seu papel na insubstituível (se bem que parcial) função tutelar também dos interesses das gerações futuras. (25) STRATENWERTH, ZStW (nota 4 ), p. 692 e ss. Criticamente STELLA, (nota 1), p. 395 e ss. UN NOUVEAU DEFI: LA PROTECTION DES GENERATIONS FUTURES AU REGARD DES SCIENCES DE LA VIE MYRIAM BLUMBERG-MOKRI Docteur en droit, Avocat à la Cour d'Appel, Paris, France Ce XIVème Congrès international de défense sociale se réunit autour d’une réflexion qui représente un défi d’envergure pour la rencontre du Droit avec les Sciences de la vie puisqu’il s’agit de débattre aujourd’hui de «la protection des générations futures au regard des nouveaux risques». En effet, les progrès en matière de reproduction des générations futures sont le plus souvent présentés comme la promesse d’une amélioration de la santé pour leurs bénéficiaires. Mais le mieux se révèle aussi l’ennemi du bien. En ce sens, les intrusions techno-scientifiques dans le processus de reproduction des hommes génèrent dans le même temps performances thérapeutiques, risques inédits et interrogations innovantes. Cette dynamique est notamment à l’œuvre avec l’émergence d’une thérapie par modification génétique d’un individu à venir. On peut craindre que cette nouvelle forme thérapeutique ne porte en germe le désir consumériste de parfaire génétiquement les individus afin de les rendre conformes aux désirs parentaux et/ou à une norme sociale labellisée. Les prochaines générations auront ainsi la possibilité de choisir pour une large part l’identité de leur progéniture et consécutivement celles des générations à venir( 1). D’autres inquiétudes sont également générées par l’éventualité d’utiliser le clonage humain comme méthode de procréatio n artificielle. En effet, la création d’un individu génétiquement identique à un de ses géniteurs pourrait être considérée comme la traduction d’une atteinte portée à la fois à l’unicité des individus et à la diversité du genre humain. C’est en somme la conjugaison des techniques de procréation artif icielle avec la génétique qui inspire une certaine inquiétude au regard des générations à venir. Dès lors, on conviendra aisément que l’on est passé de la protection des générations futures par le savoir-faire biomédical à la protection des générations futures face à ces nouvelles pratiques. C’est en prenant pour fil conducteur ces deux types d’intrusions techniques dans le champ de la procréation humaine, à savoir la thérapie (1) REICH J., TESTART J., (1997), Pour une éthique planétaire, Paris, Editions Arte, coll. Mille et une nuits, p. 64. 62 Un nouveau défi génique germinale d’une part et le clonage reproductif humain d’autre part, qu’il sera intéressant de s’interroger aujourd’hui sur les réponses que le paysage normatif a apportées jusqu’ici. Pour commencer, on appréciera ce que le Droit entend protéger lorsqu’il se soucie des générations à venir face aux applications biomédicales, c’est-à-dire lorsqu’il met en avant une certaine conception de la notion d’humanité. La complexité vient de ce que l’humanité présente à la fois un caractère ordinaire, que l’on pourrait appeler «l’animalité de l’espèce humaine». Elle partage en effet assez banalement avec d’autres formes de vie sexuée les lois de la transmission de son patrimoine génétique. Mais, l’espèce humaine possède aussi un caractère extraordinaire, que l’on pourrait nommer «l’humanité du genre humain» et qui la distingue des autres espèces. Ce caractère spécifique semble relayé au plan juridique par l’affirmation de la dignité humaine. C’est ainsi que la quête d’un sens jur idique à la notion d’humanité passe par un détour juridique : le principe de dignité humaine (I). Toutefois, on verra que ce principe de dignité humaine − incarné en droit de la santé par l’exigence d’un consentement libre et éclairé aux interventions médicales − lorsqu’on le confronte à la technique de modification du patrimoine génétique humain n’est pas d’une application évidente. Plus grave encore, la question se pose de savoir si la manipulation des gènes humains permettra uniquement de soigner les individus ou débouchera inéluctablement sur la discrimination croissante des individus génétiquement prédisposés à certaines maladies ou certains handicaps voire même sur la création de nouvelles lignées d’individus. Dans ce contexte, et malgré l’écueil de l’exigence du consentement, la mise sous «contrôle génétique»(2) suscitera de nouvelles exigences (II). Quoiqu’il en soit, la rapidité avec laquelle les techniques biomédic ales font leur apparition ne permet pas de se satisfaire de l’idée selon laquelle une technique qui pose problème aujourd’hui mais qui serait dépassée demain, dans le même temps où elle repousse les limites de la faisabilité technique, se trouve autorisée à redessiner au gré de ses prétentions les contours de principes juridiques fondamentaux et universellement déclarés, autrement dit communs à tous les êtres humains. Certes, pour être parfaitement opportune, la détermination du licite et de l’illicite doit tenir compte des données scientifiques. Prenons de façon presque anecdotique l’exemple du Parlement européen qui a été très réactif (2) TESTART J., (1997), «Génétique: puissance et illusions», Transversales Science et Culture, mars/avril No. 44, p. 6. Un nouveau défi 63 à l’actualité scientifique en prenant position après chaque diffusion à grande échelle par la presse d’informations alarmantes sur le thème du clonage humain. Ainsi, l’adoption d’une résolution parlementaire condamnant le clonage de l’embryon humain en 1993( 3) a fait écho aux informations faisant état de ce qui pouvait médiatiquement passer pour le premier clonage d’un «embryon» humain par une université américaine ( 4). Quatre ans plus tard en 1997, en plein retentissement de l’affaire Dolly( 5), le Parlement européen condamne à nouveau le clonage humain à travers une nouvelle résolution. Ce texte a été élaboré à la suite du clonage réussi d’une brebis − après 277 tentatives non concluantes − réalisé par un laboratoire écossais au moyen de la technique de transfert d’un noyau de cellule adulte dans un ovocyte énucléé(6). Enfin, après l’annonce en 1998 par un physicien américain, Richard Seed, de son intention d’ouvrir une clinique consacrée à la procréation assistée par la technique du clonage pour pallier la stérilité (7), le Parlement européen a une fois de plus condamné le clonage humain par une nouvelle résolution( 8). Cette adhésion des législateurs à l’actualité scientif ique a fait dire à un député européen non dépourvu d’humour que «si l’on recommence le même débat chaque fois qu’un chercheur dans le monde raconte aux médias qu’il dépasse ce qui est moralement admissible, il suffira à chaque période de session plénière de cloner une résolution sur la résolution précédente» (9). Au-delà de cette anecdote, on reconnaîtra que le droit ne peut se satisfaire d’être à la remorque de la norme techno-scientifique ni de tenter de répondre au coup par coup aux avancées biomédicales. Son rôle est par définition de rappeler l’existence de limites aux activités humaines, autrement dit d’en réguler les pratiques. Dans le contexte très particulier des applications biomédicales, on observe à ce jour qu’à mi-chemin entre une réponse à portée universelle (3) Résolution sur le clonage de l’embryon humain, 28 octobre 1993, Parlement européen, JOCE, 22.11.1993, C315/224. (4) George Washington University Medical Center (Etats -Unis). (5) Résolution sur le clonage, Parlement européen, 12 mars 1997, JOCE, 14.4.1997, C 115/92. (6) M ILLET A., POSTEL-VINAY O., «Comment va Dolly? Le clonage des mammifères passe à la vitesse supérieure», La Recherche, avril 1997, pp. 50-63. (7) NAU J.Y., «L’Europe se mobilise contre le clonage des êtres humains», Le Monde, 13 janvier 1998. (8) Résolution sur le clonage humain, Parlement européen, 15 janvier 1998, JOCE, 2.2.1998, C 34/164. (9) Parlement européen, C-R débats, 15.1.1998, p. 53. 64 Un nouveau défi quelque peu symbolique concernant spécifiquement la protection du génome humain et des encadrements nationaux desservis par leur variété, une cohérence semble, quoique timidement, se dégager. Cette cohérence est liée à l’effort d’harmonisation au niveau régional opéré par le droit supranational européen. On sait cependant que ni le droit communautaire ni le droit du Conseil de l’Europe n’ont de réelle compétence normative dans le domaine pénal, matière qui relève de la souveraineté nationale. Toutefois, le droit européen supranational entend déterminer un certain nombre d’actes illégaux. Leur inscription normative sera alors relayée par le droit répressif des Etats, ceux-ci conservant également le choix des sanctions appropriées. Dès lors, cette intervention supranationale donne une orientation certaine aux politiques criminelles des Etats européens en ce qui concerne la protection transfrontière des générations futures. La tentative d’harmonisation des politiques criminelles qui se construit très timidement encore sous nos yeux avec le domaine des sciences de la vie prend un intérêt particulier lorsqu’il s’agit du clonage reproductif humain. Reste à savoir si l’option à portée universelle du crime contre l’humanité est parfaitement recevable (III). I − En quête de l’humanité du genre humain: le détour par la dignité humaine Préliminaires Le propre de l’individu vivant est de se perpétuer grâce à l’arrivée d’une nouvelle génération qui se trouve héritière d’un patrimoine génétique transmis des générations antérieures aux générations futures par le biais de la génération parentale. C’est en ce sens que «chacun d’entre nous porte un message de ses ancêtres dans chaque cellule de son corps. C’est l’ADN, le matériau génétique, qui se transmet de génération en génération. Et dans cet ADN sont écrites notre histoire en tant qu’individu, mais aussi toute l’histoire de l’espèce humaine» (10). Si le propre de la vie est bien de se transmettre de génération en génération, le propre de l’individu sexué est de se perpétuer grâce à un autre individu dans le but d’en produire un troisième. Ce troisième individu, et (10) SYKES B., (2001), Les sept filles d’Eve, Génétique et histoire de nos origines: une incroyable découverte qui nous mène jusqu’à nos ancêtres, Paris, Albin Michel, p.9. Un nouveau défi 65 c’est ce qui importe pour nous de retenir aujourd’hui, n’est selon les termes du généticien Albert Jacquard, ni la reproduction d’un parent ou de l’autre, ni même la moyenne des deux; il constitue un ensemble nouveau et unique(11). C’est ce programme de transmission sexuée qui dans le même temps commande la «constance des espèces» et assure «la variabilité des individus» (12). Cette variabilité est rendue possible grâce à la combinaison aléatoire du capital génétique qui s’effectue à chaque fécondation. En effet, les gènes humains sont portés par 23 paires de chromosomes présentes dans toutes les cellules somatiques de l’espèce humaine. En revanche, au sein des cellules germinales, à savoir les spermatozoïdes et ovules, chaque chromosome est présent en un seul exemplaire. Lors de la fécondation, les jeux des chromosomes du père et de la mère se combinent pour former les paires de chromosomes qui seront présentes dans le noyau de chaque cellule du futur individu apportant ainsi la contribution au capital génétique de la génération suivante. L’ADN combiné de chaque personne comporte bien sûr des mutations, qui signent son unicité. Cependant, ces mutations peuvent également être responsables d’une perturbation de l’activité biologique normale, c’està-dire d’une maladie génétique. Toutefois, il faut avoir à l’esprit que tout individu est porteur de gènes de maladies plus ou moins graves, gènes qui se transmettent, mais qui ne permettent pas à la maladie de s’exprimer s’ils sont présents en un seul exemplaire et en l’absence d’un environnement favorable. D’une vision biologiste de la protection des générations futures à la reconnaissance de la dignité humaine Il est bien évident que cette seule dimension génétique ne saurait fonder la complexité humaine du genre humain au regard du Droit. Celle -ci ne se résume en aucun cas à cette simple configuration chromosomique. Mais l’extrême difficulté à circonscrire juridiquement la notion d’humanité du genre humain − difficulté annonciatrice d’un accroc redoutable au principe de légalité qui impose une interprétation stricte des termes de la loi pénale − oblige le juriste épris de définitions ordonnées et précises à se tourner cette fois du côté d’une représentation sémantique moins rigide. (11) JACQUARD A., (1982), «La science face au racisme», in Racisme, science et pseudo-science, Actes -colloque, Athènes 3.3.1981, Paris, Unesco, p. 16. (12) GUERIN-M ARCHAND CL., (1997), Les manipulations génétiques, Paris, Puf, p. 3. 66 Un nouveau défi Plus exactement, cette représentation renverrait − pour emprunter l’expression de Mireille Delmas-Marty – vers l’expression d’un «irréductible humain » (13). Certaines dispositions normatives témoignent de cette difficulté à déterminer positivement la notion juridique d’humanité. Croyant ainsi abolir l’obstacle, elles ont fait prévaloir une vision biologiste de la protection des générations futures. Révélatrice de cette option biologiste, la législation répressive française n’intègre pas les dispositions pénales concernant les atteintes à «la protection de l’espèce humaine» au sein du titre éminemment symbolique intitulé «des crimes contre l’humanité». Le Code pénal n’assimile donc pas l’espèce humaine à la notion d’humanité. Il n’autorise pas l’équation entre l’infraction qui porte atteinte à l’espèce humaine et celle qui relève du crime contre l’humanité. Selon ce découpage, la modification délibérée de l’héritage chromosomique de l’espèce humaine constitutive de la mise en œuvre d’une pratique eugénique tendant à l’organisation de la sélection des personnes et qui porte par là même atteinte à l’espèce humaine (art. 511-1 Code pénal) se différencie de la destruction arbitraire d’un groupe ethnique ou racial particulier à partir de tout critère arbitraire, cette infraction, relevant du crime contre l’humanité (art. 211-1 Code pénal). Les peines sont également différentes: le crime contre l’humanité est punissable d’une peine de réclusion criminelle à perpétuité, le crime d’atteinte à l’espèce humaine est sanctio nné d’une peine de vingt ans de réclusion criminelle. On le voit, le législateur national a préféré confiner les atteintes à l’espèce humaine dans un chapitre contenant des infractions techniques et sectorielles «en matière d’éthique biomédicale» qui relèvent de la santé publique. Ce faisant, le Code pénal français opte pour une vision biologiste de la protection des générations futures au détriment d’une approche plus juridiste qui serait rattachée au droit des droits de l’homme par le biais du respect dû à l’humanité. Cette vision biologiste est également affichée du côté de dispositions à portée universelle. C’est le cas de l’article 1er de la Déclaration universelle sur le génome humain et les droits de l’homme adoptée par l’Unesco le 11 novembre 1997. Cette déclaration pose d’emblée que «le génome humain sous-tend l’unité fondamentale de tous les membres de la famille hu- (13) DELMAS -M ARTY M., (1994), «Le crime contre l’humanité, les droits de l’homme et l’irréductible humain», Revue de Science Criminelle, p. 477. Un nouveau défi 67 maine, ainsi que la reconnaissance de leur dignité et de leur diversité. Dans un sens symbolique, il est le patrimoine de l’humanité ». L’approche quelque peu restrictive de cette Déclaration sectorielle et spécifique de 1997 fait dépendre de son patrimoine génétique non seulement «l’unité fondamentale » de la famille humaine mais, plus préoccupant encore, la «reconnaissance de la dignité intrinsèque» des membres de cette famille humaine (art. 1 er ). Ce fondement laisse un peu rêveur si l’on songe que les scientifiques ont montré que le «code génétique est sensiblement universel» et qu’il est largement commun à toutes les espèces vivantes. Cette démonstration a eu pour conséquence d’amoindrir considérablement «le clivage entre humain/non-humain» et a donc «cessé de déterminer l’avancée de ce type de recherches» (14). Devra-t-elle paradoxalement continuer à déterminer l’«humanité» comprise dans un sens jurid ique? Cette référence à la notion de patrimoine humain, y compris comme le prévoit la Déclaration universelle sur le génome humain dans un sens symbolique, renvoie à la question de savoir si l’humanité peut être considérée comme un sujet de droit international juridiquement titulaire d’un patrimoine ( 15). De plus en plus, cette référence qui se multiplie suppose que l’humanité soit un sujet de droit appelé à gérer un héritage commun dont l’objet n’est autre que … l’humanité elle -même ( 16). Toutefois, ce texte ne renonce pas pour autant à la reconnaissance du principe de dignité humaine. Il est vrai que ce principe est accrédité d’une fonction de rempart juridique face au développement des techno-sciences. C’est ainsi que l’approche biologiste de la Déclaration universelle sur le génome humain se trouve tempérée par les termes de son article 2 qui retrouve ici le fondement de la dignité humaine en précisant que «chaque individu a droit au respect de sa dignité et de ses droits, quelles que soient ses caractéristiques génétiques» et que «cette dignité impose de ne pas réduire les individus à leurs caractéristiques génétiques et de respecter leur caractère unique et leur diversité». (14) HUBER G., (1992), «Vers un anti-destin», in F. GROS , G. HUBER, Vers un anti-destin? Patrimoine génétique et droits de l’humanité, Paris, ODILE JACOB , p. 24. (15) DUPUY R.J., (1984), «La notion de patrimoine commun de l’humanité appliquée aux fonds marins», in Droits et libertés à la fin du XXe siècle. Etudes offertes à A. Colliard, Paris, Pédone, p. 197. (16) Pour la Commission nationale consultative des droits de l'homme, qui s’est exprimée dans un avis du 23 mai 1996 sur l’avant-projet de la déclaration universelle, le terme de «patrimoine commun de l'humanité» est ambigu pour désigner l'héritage génétique. Il paraîtrait préférable dans le contexte d’une Déclaration universelle de retenir le terme d’ «héritage commun de l'humanité». 68 Un nouveau défi Dans ce contexte, l’humanité est assimilée à la famille humaine, renouant dans le même temps avec la terminologie de la Déclaration universelle des droits de l’homme de 1948 qui cimente quant à elle tous les membres de la famille humaine par la dignité qui leur est consubstantielle (1er considérant-Préambule). Que la dignité humaine soit inhérente à l’être humain rend sa protection juridique absolue (17). Le droit des droits de l’homme lui accorde une place tout à fait particulière et plus précieuse encore que celle du droit à la vie qui n’exclut pas que soit porté atteinte à la vie par le biais de la légitime défense ou même de la répression d’une insurrection (art. 2 CESDH). Le droit au respect de la dignité humaine apparaît bien comme un droit absolument indérogeable et qui ne souffre «aucune dérogation, exception ou restriction» (18). Aucune dérogation à la protection contre les traitements inhumains et dégradants n’est admise, y compris en cas de danger public menaçant la nation, ce qu’affirment sole nnellement l’article 4 du Pacte international relatif aux droits civils et polit iques de 1966 et l’article 15 de la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme. Quant à la Charte des droits fondamentaux proclamée par l’Union européenne en décembre 2000(19), elle identifie la dignité humaine à «une valeur indivisible et universelle» inviolable (Préambule et art. 1 er). Un autre texte international mais cette fois à portée plus réduite car régionale, fait prévaloir l’idée d’une responsabilité transgénérationnelle qui pourrait être considérée comme une des caractéristiques fondamentales du concept d’«humanité». La Convention du Conseil de l’Europe pour la protection des droits de l’homme et de la dignité de l’être humain à l’égard des applications de la biologie et de la médecine ouverte à la signature le 4 avril 1997 à Oviedo( 20), affirme solennellement que «les progrès de la biologie et (17) DELMAS -M ARTY M., in DELMAS -M ARTY M., LUCAS DE LEYSSAC C., (2002), Libertés et droits fondamentaux, Paris, Seuil, 2ème éd., p. 23. (18) DELMAS -M ARTY M., in DELMAS -M ARTY M., LUCAS DE LEYSSAC C., Libertés et droits fondamentaux, op. cit, p. 23. (19) Charte des droits fondamentaux de l’Union européenne, JOCE, 18.12.2000, C 364/1. (20) Convention pour la protection des Droits de l’Homme et de la dignité de l’être humain à l’égard des applications de la biologie et de la médecine: Convention sur les Droits de l’Homme et la biomédecine, 4 avril 1997, entrée en vigueur le 1er décembre 1999. A ce jour: 18 Etats membres du Conseil de l’Europe ont signé cette convention, mais sans l’avoir encore ratifiée ou sans y avoir encore adhéré: Bulgarie, Croatie, Finlande, France, Islande, Italie, Lettonie, Lituanie, Luxe mbourg, Moldavie, Pays-Bas, Norvège, Pologne, Suède, Suisse, Ex-République de Yougoslavie de Macédoine, Turquie, Ukraine; 13 Etats l’ont ratifiée ou y ont adhéré: Chypre, Danemark, Un nouveau défi 69 de la médecine doivent être utilisés pour le bénéfice des générations présentes et futures» et qu’un «usage impropre de la biologie et de la médecine» pourrait mettre en danger la dignité humaine. Dans la mesure où la Convention de biomédecine reconnaît l’importance d’assurer cette dignité humaine, elle prévoit également «la nécessité de respecter l’être humain à la fois comme individu et dans son appartenance à l’espèce humaine» (Préambule). Etablissant encore plus fermement la nécessité de s’engager sur la voie de la dépendance à l’égard des générations à venir, la récente Charte des droits fondamentaux de l’Union européenne exprime très clairement que la jouissance des droits fondamentaux de la personne humaine entraîne des responsabilités et des devoirs «tant à l’égard d’autrui qu’à l’égard de la communauté humaine et des générations futures» (Préambule). Le devoir de prise en compte des intérêts futurs du genre humain repose donc sur l’idée d’une forme de «fraternité» universelle qui dépasse les limites de la génération. En ce sens, les hommes et femmes à venir doivent être regardés comme des êtres humains «en dépit de leur existence seulement future et donc de leur anonymat. Malgré leur éloignement temporel, ils entrent dans le cercle des êtres avec lesquels nous estimons devoir établir des rapports définissables en termes de bien et de mal» (21). II − La thérapie génique germinale ou la modification des générations futures Préliminaires Schématiquement, la thérapie génique consiste en l’introduction d’un gène normal dans le génome d’un individu à l’aide d’un vecteur viral et ce dans le but que le gène nouveau prenne en charge les fonctions non assumées par le gène déficient ou anormal( 22). Il existe à ce jour deux types de thérapies géniques. Espagne, Estonie, Géorgie, Grèce, Hongrie, Portugal, Roumanie, Saint-Marin, Slovaquie, Slovénie, République Tchèque. (21) VISSER’T HOOFT H.PH., (1991), «Développement technologique et responsabilité envers les générations futures», Archives de philosophie du droit, Droit et science, Paris, Sirey, T. 36, p. 33. (22) KEVLES D., (1995), Au nom de l’eugénisme, Paris, Puf, p. XII. 70 Un nouveau défi La première thérapie est dite «thérapie génique somatique». Elle consiste à traiter par des modifications génétiques l’organisme d’un malade en ne traitant que ses propres cellules à l’exclusion des cellules de la reproduction. Dès lors, les corrections du patrimoine génétique des cellules n’affectent que l’individu traité. La deuxième correction génétique est dite «thérapie génique germinale». Celle -ci est prévue pour traiter soit les cellules des gamètes c’est-àdire les cellules servant à la reproduction, ovocyte ou spermatozoïde y compris au stade de leur maturation, soit encore les embryons à un stade très précoce de formation de l’œuf fécondé par introduction d’un gène qui au fur et à mesure des divisions cellulaires affectera toutes les cellules du futur individu. De ce fait, cette thérapie a pour but de transmettre aux générations à venir la correction génétique initialement opérée. C’est essentie llement ce dernier type de thérapie qui en affectant les générations futures malgré elles pose problème et génère de nouvelles revendications. Vers de nouvelles exigences Recourir à cette forme de thérapie signifie qu’un individu pourra volontairement vouloir transmettre la mutation génétique qu’il aura initiée aux générations futures(23). De cette possibilité technique peuvent découler de nouvelles exigences dont le non-respect pourrait un jour être sanctionné. Une personne pourra prétendre à ce qui serait considéré comme le droit de modifier sa descendance ou le droit d’en déterminer la qualité génétique en revendiquant une autonomie décisionnelle en matière de santé et une maîtrise des choix qui concernent sa vie (24). Plus insidieux encore, dans un contexte de pratiques thérapeutiques germinales banalisées, il pourra être reproché à une personne d’avoir refusé une thérapie génique qui aurait pu éviter la transmission d’une pathologie héréditaire. Or, la biologie rend effectivement possible ce nouveau confort. Un tel droit à un patrimoine génétique non atteint pourrait devenir un droit à la perfectibilité de son génome. Au droit à l’amélioration de ses gènes et à la revendication de transmettre un patrimoine génétique performant, pour- (23) KNOPPERS B.M., «La génétique humaine: patrimoine et protection», in GROS F. et HUBER G., Vers un anti-destin? Patrimoine génétique et droits de l’humanité, ouvrage précité, p. 165. (24) CORNAVIN T., (1985), «Théorie des droits de l’homme et progrès de la biologie», Revue française de théorie juridique, Droits, vol. 2, p. 100. Un nouveau défi 71 rait donc s’adjoindre la possibilité de faire valoir le droit à naître vierge de toute prédisposition génétique à certaines maladies( 25). Un tel préjudice pourrait trouver son origine dans la coupable négligence ou le refus des ascendants de se prêter à une modification délibérée de leurs gènes. D’ores et déjà, le fondement de ce droit se trouve posé par la doctrine au titre même de la revendication du respect de la dignité humaine sous la forme d’une interrogation essentielle à ce débat. On s’est ainsi interrogé : «entre celui qui refuse le principe eugénique comme attentatoire à la dignité humaine et celui qui place cette dignité dans la maîtrise par l’homme de son destin, dans sa lutte contre les tares et son combat pour l’amélioration de l’espèce, lequel est le plus respectueux de la dignité humaine?» (26). Dans cette perspective, prohiber la thérapie génique germinale précisément au nom de la dignité humaine des générations futures pourrait signifier la privation d’opportunités d’amélioration de la vie mais cette fois … au détriment des générations futures. Cette interrogation est fondamentale et sans aucun doute tout à fait légitime. Elle vient se greffer sur une notion – celle de la dignité humaine − qui bien que chargée, voire surchargée, de sens sans jamais être positivement définie par les textes – n’en est pas moins problématique au regard des bénéfices qu’offrent les nouvelles technologies du vivant lorsqu’il s’agit de respecter l’exigence fondamentale de consentement aux soins. L’impossible consentement des générations futures à leur propre modification Le principe de dignité humaine se traduit dans la sphère médicale par le respect de l’intégrité et de l’inviolabilité du corps humain. Dès lors, toute ingérence dans la sphère personnelle physique ou biologique est a priori considérée comme une violation du respect des droits fondamentaux de la personne humaine. Ce qui suppose que l’intégrité corporelle (et psychique) ne puisse être violée sans le consentement de l’intéressé. Or, pour satisfaire cette exigence, l’obtention du consentement libre et éclairé se révèle inopérante dans le cadre de la thérapie génique germinale. La modification génétique se transmettant aux générations futures, se pose à l’évidence le problème d’une adhésion libre et informée de celles-ci. (25) LEMENNICIER B., (1991), «Le corps humain : propriété de l’Etat ou propriété de soi?», Revue française de théorie juridique – Droits, vol. 13, p. 113. (26) CORNAVIN T., «Théorie des droits de l’homme et progrès de la biologie», article précité, p. 101. 72 Un nouveau défi La difficulté se rencontrera pour celui qui aura subi au stade d’œuf fécondé une recombinaison de son matériel génétique, recombinaison à son tour transmise à ses descendants. Il est bien évident, que son consentement n’aura pas été recueilli. Sa propre descendance n’aura aucun lien immédiat avec ceux qui auront primitivement donné leur accord à l’acte de modific ation du génome. Ces générations feront en quelque sorte figure d’otage de l’acceptation initiale donnée par leur aïeux, sans égard pour leur libre arbitre. Sur ce point, la doctrine n’a pu que constater que le rapport entre les «vivants et ceux qui n’existent pas encore» est forcément vicié puisque par définition «les vivants occupent à l’égard de la postérité, une position de force sans limite aucune» (27). La question de l’ingénierie génétique pose donc un problème crucial et surtout inédit. Il ne s’agit plus d’atteintes aux corps des individus euxmêmes − ou à un de leurs éléments − mais d’ingérences sur les personnes à venir, assimilables à des vic times par ricochet en cas d’échec de la correction génétique. C’est en ce sens qu’aura été porté atteinte à la dignité des êtres humains à venir puisque l’exigence du consentement libre et éclairé trouve ici ses limites. Or, selon la formule de Catherine Labrusse-Riou, la dignité humaine suppose que l’homme ne soit pas traité comme un simple objet, mais «qu’il soit différencié de la chose inerte et vivante, et respecté en sa personne» ce pour quoi «l’éthique et le droit exigent sa participation volo ntaire, son consentement libre et éclairé» (28) à toute intervention dans la sphère de la santé. Ce refus de l’instrumentalisation des êtres humains, y compris pour les individus à venir, s’est d’abord exprimé à travers le Code de Nuremberg. Pour la première fois, la justice avait été confrontée à des médecins qui avaient massivement traité des hommes comme de simples sujets d’expérience. Il a fallu attendre 1966 pour qu’un texte juridique à caractère universel et à force contraignante face du consentement d’une personne à une expérimentation médicale la face immédiatement visible de la dignité humaine. En effet, l’article 7 du Pacte international des droits civils et politiques de 1966 prohibe expressément toute expérience médicale ou scienti(27) VISSER’T HOOFT H.PH., «Développement technologique et responsabilité envers les générations futures», article précité, p. 34. (28) LABRUSSE-RIOU C., (1988), «Les exigences normatives et institutionnelles de protection des droits de l’homme en matière d’expérimentation», in Expérimentation biomédicale et droits de l’homme, Fondation Marangopoulos pour les droits de l’homme, Paris, Puf, p.132. Un nouveau défi 73 fique qui serait réalisée en l’absence du consentement libre du sujet. Ce texte fait même de l’expérimentation médicale et scientifique un traitement cruel, inhumain ou dégradant particulier en posant que «Nul ne sera soumis à la torture, ni à des peines ou traitements cruels, inhumains ou dégradants. En particulier, il est interdit de soumettre une personne sans son libre consentement à une expérience médicale ou scientifique». En 1983, la Commission européenne des droits de l’homme avait affirmé un principe important selon lequel un traitement médical de caractère expérimental mené sans le consentement du sujet peut, dans certaines conditions, être considéré comme une atteinte à l’article 3 de la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme qui prohibe les traitements inhumains ou dégradants. La Commission s’était alors exprimée dans une décision X.c Danemark du 2 mars 1983 à propos d’une affaire de stérilisation volontaire. La requérante avait consenti au principe de l’intervention chirurgicale : une stérilisation utilisant de nouveaux procédés, qui fut cependant suivie d’une grossesse. La requérante s’était considérée comme victime d’une part d’un traitement inhumain et dégradant sous la forme d’une expérience menée sans son consentement et d’autre part à la suite de l’intervention de tortures psychologiques ne sachant pas si elle était enceinte ou non. La Commission écarte en l’espèce la violation de l’article 3 de la Convention mais rappelle d’une part qu’un traitement dit inhumain suppose un minimum de gravité, provoquant de vives souffrances physiques et morales, et d’autre part qu’un traitement dit dégradant suppose une humiliation d’une certaine gravité. Reste à savoir si une fois devenue une pratique médicale banalisée, la thérapie génique germinale pourra toujours s’analyser en une expérience médicale ou scientifique au sens propre, donc comme un cas particulier de pratiques inhumaines ou dégradantes. Il faut reconnaître cependant que les conséquences des investigations sur le génome humain dépassent les seules préoccupations liées à l’adhésion des futures générations aux soins pratiqués en amont. De la même façon, elles retentissent beaucoup plus loin au-delà des simples limites du droit à réparation découlant d’un dommage qui serait directement lié à une intervention sur le génome humain pratiquée sur un ascendant au «profit» d’un de ses descendants. En effet, la modification du génome humain transmissible aux générations futures revêt une gravité particulièrement aiguë si l’on considère la 74 Un nouveau défi question sous l’angle de la mise «sous contrôle génétique» ( 29) des générations futures. La mise sous contrôle génétique L’une des conséquences les plus graves de ce type de soins est la quête de l’enfant idéal qui serait exempt de maladies génétiques voire, comme on l’entend parfois, de prédisposition à la criminalité, à la timidité, à l’aptitude à diriger ou encore à des inclinaisons politiques(30). Corrélativement se dessine le danger d’une norme génétique qui serait constituée de standards adoptés en fonction de critères liés à une prédisposition à certa ines pathologies. Ces critères pourraient parfaitement être dictés par des exigences de polices d’assurance ou de priorités d’embauche et de licenciements dans certaines branches d’activité. Le Tribunal de Première Instance des Communautés européennes est intervenu en 1994 dans un contexte similaire. Les juges ont annulé la décision d’inaptitude à l’embauche fondée sur le risque chiffré par un médecin à partir d’une biopsie du foie réalisée quatre ans plus tôt et qui révélait la présence d’antigène de l’hépatite C. Le spécialiste consulté avait apprécié le risque que le candidat à l’embauche développe une cirrhose du foie à environ 20 à 25 % sur une évolution de 15 à 20 ans. Les juges communautaires ont estimé que «la maladie dont souffre le requérant ne lui cause aucun trouble et ne l’empêche aucunement, à l’heure actuelle, de remplir to utes les obligations qui sont susceptibles de lui incomber dans le cadre de ses fonctions» (§43). Par conséquent, pour le Tribunal, le pronostic médical portant sur l’évolution possible de la maladie ne peut justifier une décision d’inaptitude ( 31). Un tel cas de refus d’embauche pour prédisposition génétique qui s’analyse en une discrimination à l’embauche pourrait être porté devant la Cour européenne des droits de l’homme sur le fondement combiné de l’article 11 de la Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine et de l’article 14 de la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme. Le premier interdit expressément toute forme de discrimination à l’encontre (29) TESTART J., «Génétique: puissance et illusions», Transversales Science et Culture, précité. (30) GUILLEBAUD J.C., (2001), Le principe d’humanité, Paris, Seuil, p. 230. (31) Arrêt, TPI, 9 juin 1994, X. c/ Commission, T94/92 - DE SCHUTTE O., (1995), «Les examens médicaux à l’embauche de la Commission européenne», Revue trimestrielle des droits de l’homme, p. 108. Un nouveau défi 75 d’une personne en raison de son patrimoine génétique, le second dispose que la jouissance des droits et libertés reconnus par la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme doit être assurée sans distinction fondée sur le sexe, la race, la couleur, la naissance ou toute autre discrimination( 32). Une porte est ainsi entrouverte au bénéfice des victimes d’applications biomédicales pour faire valoir leurs droits sur le fondement de la non discrimination inscrite dans la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme. Cependant, il reste regrettable que la condamnation de la modific ation de la lignée germinale n’ait pas été ajoutée aux dispositions de la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme malgré la proposition émise en 1982 par l’Assemblée parlementaire du Conseil de l’Europe. Les parlementaires avaient suggéré d’y inscrire expressément le «droit d’hériter des caractéristiques génétiques n’ayant subi aucune manipulation». Ainsi cla irement énoncé, ce droit additionnel substantiel aurait bénéficié directement de la jurisprudence évolutive et créatrice de la Cour européenne des droits de l’homme. Mais cette proposition n’a pas été suivie d’effet. En outre, cette proposition de l’Assemblée parlementaire présentait le mérite de couvrir non seulement les modifications thérapeutiques du génome humain mais également les manipulations de convenance touchant par exemple à la taille du futur individu, à sa couleur d’yeux ou à une prédisposition à l’éthylisme. De son côté, le Parlement européen se prononçait catégoriquement à travers l’adoption d’une résolution du 16 mars 1989 contre l’utilisation des analyses du génome dans le but de renforcer dans un sens positif le pool génétique de la population ou de procéder à une sélection négative de caractéristiques génétiques considérées comme indésirables ou dans le but de définir des normes génétiques (point 12) (33). (32) Certes, le patrimoine génétique d’une personne n’est pas couvert par les droits garantis par la Convention européenne des droits de l’homme et la jurisprudence européenne a considéré, à l’occasion d’une affaire déjà ancienne dite «Linguistique belge» de 1968, que les termes restrictifs de l’article 14 devaient se lire avec l’un des autres droits ou libertés garantis par la Convention (CEDH, Affaire linguistique belge, 23 juillet 1968, § 9). Toutefois, cette conception évolue sous l’impulsion des juges de Strasbourg eux-mêmes. Trente ans après cette décision, les juges ont favorablement accueilli les moyens de requérants «sans que le lien avec le droit substantiel soit réellement établi» réalisant ainsi une «autonomie grandissante de l’article 14» (PRISOESSAWE S.J., (1998), «Les droits sociaux et l’égalité de traitement dans la jurisprudence de la cour européenne des droits de l’homme – A propos des arrêts Van Raalte c/ PaysBas et Petro vic c/ Autriche (21 février 1997 et 27 mars 1998)», Revue trimestrielle des droits de l’homme, pp. 730-731. (33) Résolution sur les problèmes éthiques et juridiques de la manipulation génétique du 16 mars 1989, Parlement européen, doc. A2-327/88, JOCE, 17.4.1989, C/96. 76 Un nouveau défi Il revient cependant à la Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine adoptée par le Conseil de l’Europe en 1997 de prévoir qu’une intervention ayant pour but de modifier le génome humain ne peut être entreprise que pour des raisons préventives, diagnostiques ou thérapeutiques. Mais surtout cette intervention ne peut être entreprise qu’à condition de ne pas avoir pour finalité d’introduire une modification dans le génome de la descendance (art. 13). Toutefois, cet article n’exclut pas les interventions sur les cellules somatiques qui pourraient avoir pour effet secondaire non voulu d’affecter la lignée germinale ( 34). Il convient de souligner qu’une législation nationale a fait de cette manipulation par imprudence une infraction pénale. Il s’agit du Code pénal espagnol de 1995 qui consacre un titre entier aux «Délits et manipulations génétiques». Une première interdiction condamne ceux qui, dans un objectif autre que l’élimination ou la réduction de malformations ou de maladies graves, manipulent les gènes humains en modifiant le génotype. Suit une deuxième infraction qui vise la modific ation du génotype même lorsqu’elle est imputable à une grave imprudence (art. 159 Code pénal espagnol). Quant à l’Europe du marché unique, sa réponse emprunte la voie de la neutralisation pécuniaire. La Commission européenne refuse en effet de financer au titre de ses programmes-cadres pluriannuels de recherche et de développement une activité de recherche qui modifierait ou destinée à modifier le patrimoine génétique d’êtres humains par altération de cellules germinales ou agissant à tout stade du développement embryonnaire qui puisse rendre cette altération héréditaire(35). Autre réponse économique, la directive 98/44/CE adoptée le 6 juillet 1998 relative à la protection jurid ique des inventions biotechnologiques(36) gèle la possibilité d’obtenir un brevet pour un procédé de modification de l’identité génétique germinale de l’être humain (art. 6). Cette exclusion de la sphère de la brevetabilité repose sur l’idée que l’exploitation commerciale d’un tel procédé – tout comme le procédé de clonage humain − serait contraire à l’ordre public et aux bonnes mœurs. Cette exigence de caractère éthique aura certainement (34) Rapport explicatif à la Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine, Direction des Affaires juridiques, Conseil de l’Europe, janvier 1997, DIR/JUR (97) 1, p. 21. (35) Pour un exemple: Décision, 25 avril 1994, No. 1110/94/CE, JOCE, 18.05.1994, No. L 126; GEE, Avis No. 12, Les aspects éthiques de la recherche impliquant l’utilisation d’embryons humains dans le contexte du 5ème programme-cadre de recherche, 23 novembre 1998. (36) Directive 98/44/CE du Parlement et du Conseil du 6 juillet 1998, JOCE, 30. 07.1998, No. L 213/13. Un nouveau défi 77 des répercussions conséquentes. En effet, les énormes moyens mis en jeu par l’industrie des biotechnologies conduisent légitimement à la volonté de recueillir les fruits des investissements affectés au développement et à la recherche. L’un des moyens de compenser financièrement ces mises de fond, souvent très lourdes, injectées dans les circuits de l’innovation, est l’obtention d’un brevet d’invention qui assure à son titulaire un monopole temporaire sur cette invention. A la lumière de ce contexte économique prometteur, il n’est pas inintéressant de rappeler que les rédacteurs de la directive sur la dissémination volontaire d’organismes génétiquement modifiés adoptée le 12 mars 2001 ont cru devoir préciser que l’être humain n’entrait pas dans la définition d’un organisme génétiquement modifié (OGM) ( 37). On peut donc encore se réjouir qu’une réglementation relative à la dissémination volontaire et à la mise sur le marché d’êtres humains et d’embryons humains génétiquement modifiés ne soit toujours pas d’actualité ! III − Le clonage reproductif humain: l’hypothèse d’un crime contre l’humanité La nécessité d’une harmonisation des législations Eu égard aux conséquences − tant biologiques que sociales et qui pour la plupart restent encore inconnues − de la mise en œuvre du clonage humain à visée reproductive, il est certain qu’une réponse passant par l’harmonisation des interdits au plan universel représente une option tentante et − peut-être − efficace. Une tentative en ce sens est actuellement enclenchée puisque l’ONU envisage l’élaboration d’une «Convention internationale contre le clonage d’êtres humains à des fins de reproduction» contraignante ( 38). (37) BLUMBERG-M OKRI M., «Le régime modifié des organismes réglementairement disséminés − Aperçu de la directive 201/18CE du 12 mars 2001 relative à la dissémination volontaire d’organismes génétiquement modifiés dans l’environnement», Petites Affiches, 11 septembre 2001, p. 4. Directive 2001/18/CE, JOCE,17.4.2001, L 106/1. (38) «La sixième commission recommande la création d’un comité spécial pour étudier l’élaboration éventuelle d’une convention contre le clonage d’êtres humains», 19 novembre 2001, Sixième commission, 27e séance, AG/J/367. 78 Un nouveau défi Pour l’heure, on se trouve en présence d’une production normative internationale tout à fait embryonnaire et non contraignante pour les Etats: la Déclaration universelle sur le génome humain du 11 novembre 1997 déjà évoquée. Or ce texte à prétention universelle qui identifie dans son article 11 le clonage à des fins de reproduction d’êtres humains comme une pratique contraire à la dignité humaine se borne cependant à prévoir qu’une telle pratique ne doit simplement «pas être permise». La faiblesse de cette expression est d’autant plus surprenante que, comme on l’a vu, le respect de la dignité humaine ne souffre en droit aucune dérogation. A l’opposé de la Déclaration universelle sur le génome humain, il existe des réponses nationales coercitives. Or, celles-ci constituent par nature des réponses disparates. Les Etats n’ont en effet pas tous légiféré sur les mêmes aspects de la question. Certains n’ont encore pris aucune pos ition législative que ce soit en faveur ou en défaveur du clonage qu’il soit dit «thérapeutiq ue» ou reproductif. Car il est convenu aujourd’hui de distinguer deux types de clonage en fonction de leur finalité respective. On sait ainsi que le clonage embryonnaire humain peut-être entrepris dans un but thérapeutique. Il permet dans ce cas la production illimitée de cellules et tissus génétiquement et immunologiquement identiques à celles du patient atteint par exemple d’affections neurodégénératives, de cancers ou d’insuffisances hépatocellulaires(39). Mais, il serait également envisageable d’entreprendre une pratique de clonage humain avec pour objectif la naissance d’un enfant. Ce clonage reproductif impliquant la création d’un double peut se faire classiquement par scission au stade des toutes premières cellules d’un œuf fécondé in vitro dans un cas de figure proche de celui de la gémellité naturelle. Mais une technique plus problématique d’un point de vue éthique a été mise au jour et rendue publique avec la conception de la brebis Dolly ( 40). Il s’agit de la méthode de clonage reproductif par transfert du noyau prélevé sur une cellule déjà adulte et intégré dans le cytoplasme d’un ovocyte énuclée après traitement adéquat. L’embryon ainsi produit exclut toute (39) KHAN A., (2002), «Le clonage «thérapeutique» et le statut de l’embryon», Le clonage, coordooné par A. M CLAREN, Editions du Conseil de l’Europe, p. 117. (40) CAMPBELL K. H. S., (2002), «Dolly, la brebis clonée», Le clonage, coordooné par A. M CLAREN, Editions du Conseil de l’Europe, p. pp. 61-71. Un nouveau défi 79 procréation sexuée autrement dit toute recombinaison aléatoire des gènes parentaux(41). Dans sa ferme volonté d’interdire les pratiques de clonage humain quelle qu’en soit leur finalité, le Parlement européen dans une résolution du 7 septembre 2000 a préféré passer outre une telle distinction entérinée par les scientifiques et reprise par les juristes. Les députés ont considéré qu’elle était une distinction technique qui ne faisait que renvoyer à une «stratégie sémantique» susceptible «d’affaiblir la signification morale du clonage» et par là-même d’assouplir les interdictions envisageable s (point G; H). Au niveau des droits nationaux, mis à part le cas de la Constitution irlandaise qui protège l’embryon humain depuis sa conception, et partant devrait rendre illégales les recherches sur les embryons, le clonage reproductif humain, voire même les tentatives de manipulation des cellules souches embryonnaires, il est le plus souvent tenu compte de cette distinction entre clonage reproductif et non reproductif. C’est le cas du gouvernement britannique qui a publiquement annoncé en avril 2001( 42) sa volonté d’être le premier pays au monde à interdire légalement le clonage humain reproductif. Posée par la loi «Human Reproductive Cloning Act 2001» du 4 décembre 2001, une telle interdiction a une valeur juridique déterminante car supérieure à toute interdiction administrative auparavant délivrée par l’Autorité de fécondation humaine et d’embryologie. Est donc passible d’une peine d’emprisonnement de 10 ans et/ou d’une sanction pécuniaire la personne qui aura implanté dans une femme un embryon humain créé autrement que par fertilisation. En revanche, la Grande-Bretagne a donné son feu vert aux médecins afin de pouvoir créer des embryons à des fins thérapeutiques après obtention d’une licence délivrée par l’Autorité compétente. Auparavant, les recherches sur les embryons étaient légales jusqu’au 14ème jour après la fécondation. Avec The Human Fertilisation and Embryology (Research Purposes) Regulations entrés en vigueur le 31 janvier 2001, des cellules souches embryonnaires seront ainsi rendues accessibles aux chercheurs britanniques par création d’embryons ( 43). (41) A TLAN H., «Possibilités biologiques, impossibilités sociales», in A TLAN H., A UGE M., DELMAS -M ARTY M., DROIT R.P., FRESCO N., (1999), Le clonage humain, Paris, Seuil, p. 17 et s. (42) The Guardian Website, 18 avril 2001. (43) FRANRENET S., «Repères internationaux», Biofutur – Le mensuel européen de biotechnologie, No. 223, juin 2002, pp. 38-41. 80 Un nouveau défi Autre exemple législatif, le cas français. En l’état actuel des lois bioéthiques de 1994 il n’y a aucune disposition spécifique concernant le clonage humain. Mais le projet de loi bioéthique du 20 juin 2001 entend intégrer dans le Code pénal l’interdiction du clonage humain comme méthode de procréation en prévoyant une peine de vingt ans de réclusion criminelle pour «une intervention en vue de faire naître un enfant qui ne serait pas directement issu des gamètes d’un homme et d’une femme» (art. 511-12°). Quant au clonage non reproductif, et contrairement à la législation br itannique, les possibilités actuelles de constituer des clones d’embryons humains comme source de matériel biologique thérapeutique sont exclues par l’interdiction pénale de concevoir in vitro des embryons humains à des fins de recherche ou d’expérimentation (art. 511-18 Code pénal) dont la violation est punie de sept ans d’emprisonnement et de 100 000 Euros d’amende. Le récent projet de loi bioéthique autoriserait en revanche l’obtention de cellules souches embryonnaires prélevées sur des embryons surnuméraires obtenus in vitro et qui ne feraient plus l’objet d’un projet parental. Mais l’idée d’une répression adéquate contre la création d’un être humain par la technique du clonage reproductif implique de s’éloigner du cadre limité des frontières étatiques. Car, il est clair que l’interdiction du clonage humain comme pratique de procréation assistée à un endroit du monde ne prohibe ni la recherche ni les pratiques à un autre endroit ( 44). Cette hypothèse n’est pas de pure école. Richard Seed, un chercheur américain qui a récolté assez de fonds privés pour envisager la création d’une clinique spécialisée dans la procréation humaine par clonage à Chicago a prévu qu’en cas d’interdiction du clonage humain sur le territoire américain, il irait à l’étranger. On connaît déjà des pratiques de recours à des mères de substitution par des couples français hors du territoire national, cette pratique étant considérée comme contraire à l’ordre public français (art. 167 et 16-9 Code civil; Cour de cassation, Ass. Plén. 31 mai 1991). Ces couples s’en remettent alors à des associations américaines susceptibles de faire le lien entre l’offre d’une mère porteuse et leur demande. Une telle mise en relation relèverait en France du droit répressif qui condamne l’entremise entre une personne ou un couple désireux d’accueillir un enfant et une femme acceptant de porter en elle cet enfant en vue de leur remettre (art. 227-12, al. 2 Code pénal). (44) Assemblée Parlementaire, Compte-rendu, Session 1997, 26ème séance, BIRRAUX M., AS (1997), CR 26, p. 3. Un nouveau défi 81 Cette modulation géographique de la licéité présente un éclairage tout particulier dans l’Europe des quinze. Car l’adéquation entre un espace spécifique de liberté de circulation des personnes, des services et des marchandises et les degrés variables des permissivités légales nationales n’est pas évidente (45). L’affaire Blood (46) en témoigne. En l’espèce, une veuve britannique avait, après prélèvement au Royaume-Uni des gamètes de son époux victime d’un coma profond, recouru sur le sol belge à une insémination post-mortem qui lui avait été − administrativement − refusée dans son pays. Cette pratique a pu être entérinée par les juges britanniques sur le fondement de la libre prestation de services au sein de l’Union européenne, les gamètes de son époux défunt étant considérés comme des accessoires d’un service librement délivré sur le territoire communautaire(47). Cette mosaïque législative, on s’en doute, ne peut que favoriser ce qu’il est convenu d’appeler aujourd’hui le «tourisme procréatif». D’où un souci d’harmonisation au niveau européen de l’interdiction du clonage humain à but reproductif. Le Conseil de l’Europe s’est prononcé à travers un protocole additionnel à la Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine adopté le 12 janvier 1998 ( 48). Ironie de l’histoire, ce protocole additionnel portant interdiction du clonage d’êtres humains est entré en vigueur en mars 2001 au moment même où un médecin italien et un médecin américain avaient déclaré être en mesure d’ici deux ans de pallier la stérilité de leurs patients en recourant à la technique du clonage ( 49). (45) BERNARDI A., (2002), «Europe sans frontières et droit pénal», Revue de Science Criminelle p. 4 et s. (46) R. v. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, Court of Appeal, (1997). (47) BERGÉ J-S, (2000), «Le droit communautaire dévoyé – Le cas Blood», La Semaine Juridique - JCP, pp. 289-293. (48) Protocole additionnel à la Convention pour la protection des Droits de l’homme et la dignité de l’être humain à l’égard des applications de la biologie et de la médecine, portant interdiction du clonage d’êtres humains, adopté le 12 janvier 1998, entré en vigueur le 1er mars 2001. A ce jour: 18 Etats membres du Conseil de l’Europe ont signé cette Convention, mais sans l’avoir encore ratifiée ou sans y avoir encore adhéré: Croatie, Danemark, Finlande, France, Islande, Italie, Lettonie, Lituanie, Luxe mbourg, Moldavie, Pays-Bas, Norvège, Pologne, Saint-Marin, Suède, Suisse, ExRépublique de Yougoslavie de Macédoine, Turquie; 11 Etats l’ont ratifiée ou y ont adhéré: Chypre, Espagne, Estonie, Géorgie, Grèce, Hongrie, Portugal, Roumanie, Slovaquie, Slovénie, République Tchèque. (49) Agence France Presse, 9 mars 2001. 82 Un nouveau défi Ce texte européen interdit cependant expressément toute intervention ayant pour but de créer un être humain génétiquement identique à un autre être humain, qu’il soit vivant ou qu’il soit mort. Il s’agit d’interdire la création de deux individus ayant en commun l’ensemble des gènes nucléaires (art. 1er). Cette prohibition vise donc à garantir l’identité de l’être humain contre les moyens d’en prédéterminer la constitution génétique (Rapport, § 3)(50). Cette prédétermination médicalement assistée serait une sorte de «bombe à retardement» pour les générations futures. Dans l’hypothèse d’une utilisation banalisée de ce mode de reproduction des êtres humains, le risque est en effet à terme de mettre en échec la diversité de l’espèce humaine par la remise en cause de la recombinaison naturelle et aléatoire des gènes issue de la reproduction sexuée (Rapport § 3 ). En dépit du caractère contraignant pour les Etats ayant ratifié ce protocole additionnel portant interdiction du clonage, le choix est laissé aux législateurs nationaux de prévoir des sanctions dites appropriées pour la violation d’une telle interdiction (art. 25 Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine). Ces sanctions appropriées pourront donc être, selon les politiques législatives des Etats, des sanctions professionnelles, disciplinaires ou ordinales contre les médecins par exemple, des sanctions pécuniaires visant à la réparation d’un dommage causé par l’intervention médicale, ou encore des sanctions administratives de fermeture d’établissements. Mais eu égard à la gravité des atteintes, il est prévisible que les Etats Parties envisageront de les incriminer pénalement. Toutefois, le risque d’amoindrir l’effectivité d’un tel interdit posé par le texte européen est accentué par le fait qu’il revient aux Parties, dans le cadre de la Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine, d’assurer la protection juridictionnelle appropr iée afin de faire cesser une atteinte illicite aux droits et principes reconnus par ce texte et ses protocoles additionnels (art. 23). Sont ainsi posées les limites d’un texte international dont l’application des clauses dépend in fine de la bonne volonté des Etats signataires. D’où un risque d’ineffectivité de ce texte, risque accru puisque ce texte international est chargé de limiter les divergences nationales dans un domaine d’activité – la biomédecine – qui représente un secteur économiquement très prometteur et déjà hautement concurrentiel. (50) Projet de Rapport explicatif au projet de protocole additionnel à la Convention sur les droits de l’homme et la biomédecine portant interdiction du clonage d’êtres humains, Direction des Affaires juridiques, juillet 1997, DIR/JUR (97) 9. Un nouveau défi 83 La prohibition du clonage reproductif humain au titre du crime contre l’humanité L’interdiction du clonage reproductif reposerait essentiellement sur le risque d’instrumentalisation des êtres humains. On songe à l’hypothèse de la création par clonage d’embryons in vitro à des fins de constitution de pièces de rechange. Des scientifiques ont déjà émis le projet de la conservation par congélation des embryons humains qui permettrait après fraction de l’amas cellulaire embryonnaire d’en implanter immédiatement la moitié dans un utérus maternel pour donner naissance à un enfant et de différer l’utilisation de l’autre moitié afin de donner artificiellement à cet individu un jumeau, une réplique génétique qui constituerait une réserve de cellules, tissus ou organes immunocompatibles( 51). L’instrumentalisation des êtres humains se trouve amplifiée par l’aspect encore expérimental du clonage humain. En effet, les faibles taux de réussite de cette technique entraîneraient une mise en danger de l’intégrité physique, voire de la vie, des personnes ainsi produites (vieillissement précoce des cellules; risque de malformation et de stérilité etc.) (52). Ce solde négatif est encore aggravé par la mise en danger de l’intégrité psychique des individus clonés. En effet, les clones vivront selon toute vraisemblance en sachant que leur constitution génétique a déjà vécu dans un autre individu. On peut encore supposer qu’ils subiront les décalages dus au bouleversement de la filiation ma is également de graves conflits d’identification selon la place assumée dans la famille par la personne sur laquelle aura été prélevée la cellule initiale. Ainsi, le père génétique pourra aussi bien être considéré comme le frère du clone que son grand-père. Enfin, ils vivront en partageant la même apparence physique que le donneur de noyau cellulaire, voire que des personnes reproduites en nombre illimité dans l’hypothèse (pour l’heure futuriste) de multiplication massive de clones. (51) A LEXANDRE H., (1990), «L’expérimentation sur les embryons de mammifères», in C. SUSANNE, Les manipulations génétiques – Jusqu’où aller?, Bruxelles, De Boeck Université, p. 82.; KHAN A., PAPILLON F., (1998), Copies conformes – Le clonage en question, Paris, Nil éditions, p. 196-197. (52) En dépit de ces inconnues et de ces risques, le gynécologue italien S. Antinori a annoncé que trois femmes dans le monde, «deux en Russie et une dans un autre pays», étaient enceintes «après implantation in utero d’embryons humains obtenus à partir de la technique du transfert nucléaire, et que les naissances devraient survenir en décembre 2002 ou en janvier 2003», J.Y. NAU, «La naissance annoncée des premiers clones humains», Le Monde, 25 mai 2002, p. 23. 84 Un nouveau défi A fortiori dans cette dernière hypothèse, mais plus simplement dans le cas du recours à la procréation scientifiquement assistée par la méthode du clonage, cette technique de reproduction porterait atteinte à la singularité de chacun emportant ainsi violation du fondement de «l’humanité comme pluralité d’êtres uniques» (53). D’où l’éventualité de qualifier la pratique du clonage reproductif comme un crime contre l’humanité. Cette éventualité repose sur l’idée que le clonage reproductif humain est clairement répertorié comme une violation grave des droits fondamentaux de la personne humaine. Outre qu’il exige une expérimentation sur l’homme contraire à la dignité humaine (expérimentation menée sans le consentement de l’intéressé et non dépourvu de dangers pour celui-ci), le clonage humain reproductif est un comportement violant le principe d’égalité en droit des êtres humains. Il induit la possibilité technique et normative d’une sélection eugénique et raciste de l’espèce humaine. Précisément, la stigmatisation des pratiques eugénistes en vue de la sélection des êtres humains est l’une des indications du crime contre l’humanité. Elle renvoie à l’atteinte à la singularité des individus tout en se fondant sur une volonté de sélectionner les hommes. Or, c’est bien «la pratique délibérée, politique, juridique, […] médicale ou scientifique, comportant soit la violation du principe de singularité, soit celle du principe d’égale appartenance à la communauté» (54) humaine qui justifie la notion de crime contre l’humanité. Cependant, le problème du sens d’une telle répression reste posé et notamment au regard de l’auteur d’une telle infraction. En effet, «le crime contre l’humanité est toujours la conséquence d’un plan concerté, c’est-àdire de la volonté proclamée plus ou moins ouvertement, généralement par les plus hautes autorités de l’Etat de détruire ou pour le moins asservir, de façon systématique et rationnelle un groupe» (55) humain. Caractérisé à la fois par l’effet massif de la destruction et par son organisation systématique, ce crime ne peut se départir d’une politique étati- (53) DELMAS -M ARTY M., (1996), Vers un droit commun de l’humanité, Paris, éditions Textuel, p. 87. (54) DELMAS -M ARTY M., Vers un droit commun de l’humanité, ouvrage précité, p. 87. (55) CLERGERIE J.L., (1988), «La notion de crime contre l’humanité», Revue du droit public, p. 1259. Un nouveau défi 85 que, ou quasi-étatique ( 56). Dès lors, dans le cadre précis du clonage humain, la désignation de l’auteur prend un éclairage particulier. Techniquement, il serait possible à un biologiste ou à un médecin de s’adonner en solitaire à la fabrication de clones humains. A l’opposé, il lui serait difficile, en agissant seul, de mettre en œuvre une politique concertée de sélection eugénique de l’espèce humaine. Or dans le cadre du crime contre l’humanité, cette séle ction est menée au nom d’un «intérêt général» déterminé par un «groupe-auteur», par exemple un gouvernement, qui seul a les moyens d’imposer et de mettre en œuvre une telle politique de séle ction eugénique. La spécificité du crime contre l’humanité, vu par exemple depuis le droit pénal français, impose de «subordonner l’incrimination à l’existence d’une entreprise collective de domination de l’homme concrétisée par un ensemble de pratiques accomplies de manière systématique» (57). Dès lors, comment envisager d’impliquer un individu isolé en tant qu’auteur d’un tel plan concerté qui suppose par définition une entente? Complice certes. Mais l’agent clonant un embryon humain de façon isolée serait en réalité poursuivi sous l’empire de la législation pénale française existante pour avoir pratiqué des recherches et expérimentations illégales sur un embryon humain. Par ailleurs, un individu œuvrant de manière isolée pourra difficilement se prévaloir d’un agissement involontaire. Pour reprendre les termes de Mireille Delmas-Marty, il est évident que l’on ne réduit pas en esclavage une population de clones produite dans un but prédéterminé, que l’on ne commet pas un génocide, que l’on ne procède pas à des pratiques eugénistes à grande échelle, bref que l’on ne commet pas un crime contre l’humanité par imprudence ou simple négligence(58). Du point de vue des poursuites judiciaires, il est possible d’envisager au plan international l’assistance d’une cour répressive internationale sur le fondement par exemple de la Convention sur le génocide adoptée par les Nations-Unies en 1948. Au plan régional, et à condition de rattacher cette infraction à la violation d’un des droits garantis par la Convention euro(56) A SCENSIO H., MAISON R., (1997), «L’activité des tribunaux pénaux internationaux pour l’ex-Yougoslavie (1995-1997) et pour le Rwanda (1994-1997)», Annuaire français de droit international, p. 392-393. (57) FRANCILLON J., Commentaires sous les articles 211-1 à 213-5 du Code pénal français :«Des crimes contre l’humanité», Code pénal commenté –ROUJOU DE BOUBEE G., BOULOC B., FRANCILLON J., M AYAUD Y., P ARIS , DALLOZ , (1996), p. 119. (58) DELMAS -M ARTY M., «Certitudes et incertitudes du droit», in ATLAN H., A UGÉ M., DELMAS -M ARTY M., DROIT R.P., FRESCO N., Le clonage humain, ouvrage précité, p. 92. 86 Un nouveau défi péenne des droits de l’homme, il serait possible de recourir à la Cour eur opéenne de Strasbourg sur le fondement de l’article 33 de la convention. Cet article prévoit en effet le recours d’un Etat contre un autre sans lien de nationalité entre l’Etat requérant et les victimes individuelles de la violation des droits conventionnels ( 59). Reste que les victimes sont ici individuelles sans être encore aujourd’hui un groupe humain caractérisé par leur qualité de «clones». Quoiqu’il en soit, puisqu’en matière de clonage nous naviguons sur du long terme, la qualification de crime contre l’humanité présenterait le mérite de rendre imprescriptible la violation de l’interdiction de dupliquer des personnes dans les Etats ayant consacré cette imprescriptibilité. Le droit pénal de la bioéthique, un «droit pénal magique» (60)? En guise de conclusion, je m’interroge sur la portée de l’interdiction pénale portant sur des actes encore rares et qui de ce fait appartiennent encore aujourd’hui à la science du futur. En revanche, et en dépit de cette appartenance encore avérée à la sphère de la science-fiction, la prohibition de tels actes figure d’ores et déjà dans le droit positif. Cette particularité, voire ce paradoxe, donne une dimension éminemment symbolique à cette incrimination. Ainsi, très clairement, l’interdiction pénale de création de clones ou de modification du génome de la descendance, actes qui relèvent encore exclusivement à ce jour du domaine expérimental, est inscrite dans nombre de textes normatifs dont on a pu apprécier dans cet exposé la variété. Dès lors, plutôt que préventif ou dissuasif, ce type d’incriminations pourrait jouer le rôle d’interdit de «pur affichage» (61) au service d’une volonté visant à rassurer une opinion publique (62) fort peu consultée sur des questions aussi graves. (59) LABAYLE H., «Article 24», in DECAUX E., IMBERT P.H., PETTITI L.-E., (sous la dir.) (1995),, La convention européenne des droits de l’homme – Commentaire article par article, Paris, Economica, p. 572. (60) L’expression est une fois de plus empruntée à DELMAS -M ARTY M., (1985), «L’enjeu d’un Code pénal: réflexions à propos de l’inflation des lois pénales en France», Mélanges Legros, Bruxelles, p. 165 et s. (61) RASSAT M.L., (1994), «Les nouvelles mœurs législatives à la lumière du nouveau Code pénal français», Revue Droits. (62) PROTHAIS A LAIN, (1997), «Les paradoxes de la pénalisation – enquête en matière d’assistance médicale à la procréation et d’adoption», La Semaine juridique − JCP, Doctrine, 4055, p. 430. Un nouveau défi 87 Cette tendance générale à légiférer avait déjà été décrite il y a une vingtaine d’années par le Conseil de l’Europe dans un Rapport du Comité européen pour les problèmes criminels consacrés à la décriminalisation: «Le législateur peut avoir recours à la criminalisation en tant que solution apparente d’un problème social. Il subit souvent la pression de «l’opinion publique» ou de groupes qui l’incitent à maîtriser certains phénomènes indésirables alors qu’il ne dispose d’aucun moyen efficace pour le faire ou qu’il ne veut pas subvenir aux frais ainsi engendrés. Dans ces conditions, il peut criminaliser l’action afin d’apaiser l’opinion. L’opération réussit souvent en raison des croyances peu réalistes largement répandues dans la société au sujet du fonctionnement du système pénal»(63). Ce mode de régulation juridique appliqué aux activités biomédicales de fabrication de la vie humaine ne risque-t-il pas de traduire une «sorte d’exorcisme législatif où le texte de loi n’aura plus qu’une valeur incantatoire» (64), une tendance à légiférer au nom d’un «droit pénal magique» ? Il est vrai que la matière elle -même, autrement dit la transmission de la vie humaine et les moyens techniques que les hommes ont acquis d’en modifier le parcours, ayant une forte charge symbolique, s’y prête aisément. Dans ce cas, la décision d’incriminer joue un rôle d’apaisement social certainement aussi important, voire plus important, que la mise en application qui pourra être faite de la norme pénale elle-même. (63) Conseil de l’Europe, Rapport sur la décriminalisation, Strasbourg, 1980. DELMAS -M ARTY M., L’enjeu d’un Code pénal: réflexions à propos de l’inflation des lois pénales en France, article précité, p. 165 et s. (64) DIREITO PENAL MÉDICO EM MUDANÇA MANUEL DA COSTA ANDRADE Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal I. Introduçao 1. Há mais de um século lançou o penalista alemão Merkel a sua alegoria sobre o direito penal. Que comparava a uma árvore, que perde as folhas no Outono, mas que na Primavera aparece sempre vestida de folhas novas. Pelo menos do lado do Direito penal médico estaremos seguramente a viver o Outono de um paradigma e a Primavera de um outro. Não è ainda possível referenciar com segurança, na plenitude das suas singularidades, o paradigma emergente. Além do mais porque o mocho das ciências normativas − morais, éticas ou jurídicas − voa sempre ao entardecer. Sobre o crepúsculo das novas «construções sociais da realidade» (Berger/Luckmann) e, particularmente, das realizações das ciências e técnicas médicas. Se è assim, em geral, por maioria de razão terá de sê-lo para o direito penal, instrumento de protecção subsidiária de bens jurídicos e de reafirmação contrafáctica da validade das normas. Que só está legitimado a intervir face a manifestações reais e intoleráveis de danosidade social e não para esconjurar os fantasmas da futurologia. 2. Tudo permite antecipar que no futuro − pelo menos no futuro ao alcance do nosso olhar − sobrará sempre um espaço para a intervenção legítima do direito penal para proteger os bens jurídicos mais «expostos às intempéries» (Binding) das intervenções e agressões abusivas feitas à sombra da Medicina. De qualquer forma e à vista das transformações a que assistimos, tudo leva a crer que a sobrevivência do direito penal médico será acompanhada pela crise − irreversível ao que parece − do paradigma que chegou aos nossos dias. E que conheceu o seu triunfo e estabilização generalizada a partir sobretudo dos meados do século passado. Text not revised by the Author. 90 Direito penal médico em mudança II. Tópicos do (Velho) Paradigma Herdado 3. Na sua expressão eidéctica e canónica aquele paradigma analisa-se em dois enunciados basilares e complementares: a) A intervenção médico-cirúrgica − medicamente indicada, realizada por médico, segundo as leges artis e com animus curandi − não preenche, qualquer que seja o seu resultado, a factualidade típica das Ofensas corporais ou do Homicídio. b) A intervenção médico-cirúrgica realizada sem o consentimento livre e esclarecido do paciente, é incriminada e punida como um crime autónomo contra a liberdade. O crime de Intervenções ou tratamentos médico-cirúrgicos arbitrários (a eigenmächtige Heilbehandlung na linguagem germânica). Devido, no essencial, à elaboração doutrinal alemã, este modelo dogmático e normativo generalizou-se no plano comparatístico. E conheceu mesmo a expressão positivada em ordenamentos jurídicos como o português (artigos 150°, 156° e 157° do Código Penal) e austríaco (§ 110 do ÖStGB). 4. Numa caracterização sumária, este paradigma polariza-se em torno de duas constelações de bens jurídicos diferentes, com exigências, em princípio, antinómicas e conflituantes. De um lado a vida e a integridade física; do outro lado, a «liberdade de dispor do corpo e da própria vida« (Figueiredo Dias), ou, na expressiva formulação do tribunal Federal Alemão, o «livre direito de autodeterminação da pessoa sobre o seu corpo (freien Selbstbestimmungsrecht des Menschen über sein Körper«). A par do hipocrático salus aegroti suprema lex esto , o médico tem também de respeitar o imperativo voluntas aegroti suprema lex esto . Este último um axioma que significa a prevalência de princípio da autodeterminação sobre a saúde e a vida. E reversamente a denegação à sociedade, ao Estado e ao médico de qualquer Vernunfthoheit sobre a «irracionalidade« da escolha do paciente. A recusa do paciente tem de ser respeitada qualquer que sejam as suas consequências. Por vias disso, não é punível a chamada eutanásia passiva. Não é, noutros termos, punível o médico que, correspondendo á vontade livre, esclarecida e inequívoca do paciente, omite ou interrompe o tratamento indispensável para lhe salvar a vida. 5. Este compreensão doutrinal e normativa tinha subjacente uma representação estabilizada e quase «natural« da realidade, em geral, e do Direito penal médico em mudança 91 acto médico, em particular. Numa redução arquetípica: uma relação de comunicabilidade e confiança entre um médico e um paciente. Numa aproximação mais analítica: a) De um lado estava um − um só − médico. Livremente escolhido pelo paciente, que nele depositava a sua confiança e que tornava em confidente exclusivo das suas angústias e sofrimento. Por vias disso, um médico que obedecia a uma única lealdade. Na síntese de Fletcher: «o compromisso é com os pacientes…não com aqueles à espera, nem com a sociedade no seu conjunto». b) Do outro lado, um – e um só – paciente. Um paciente representado com mónada isolada ou como sistema autorreferente e autopoiético, em cujo horizonte se inscrevem as decisões e as acções médicas. Que esgotam a sua relevância e significado na direcção da vida, da saúde e da autonomia do paciente. c) Em terceiro lugar, um médico e um paciente ligados por uma relação contínua de díalogo e comunicação. No sentido de que é sempre possível comunicar com o paciente, informá-lo e obter a expressão actualizada da sua decisão esclarecida e livre. III. Nova Realidade. Novo Direito Penal? 6. Tal como o conhecemos, o Direito Penal Médico continua a ter como referente esta «construção social da realidade». Uma realidade hipostasiada, que pouco terá de comun com o quotidiano dos médicos e dos doentes que protagonizam a medicina nos nossos dias. Onde o quadro tende a ser outro. a) Em primeiro lugar, é cada vez mais rara a experiência de um médico livremente escolhido, como depositário exclusivo da confiança e do segredo do paciente. Cada vez mais, o doente interage com organizações burocráticas: hospitais, clínicas e serviços de saúde, em geral. Os seus médicos são em boa medida ditados pela álea da organização dos serviços. Por seu turno, o tratamento decompõe-se numa sequência de actos atomizados, a cargo dos diferentes especialistas. Por vias disso, não sobra lugar para a confiança. Alarga-se incontroladamente o universo dos profissionais − a Kreis der Wissenden de que falam os alemães − a ter legitimamente acesso ao segredo e à privacidade. E estreita- 92 Direito penal médico em mudança se drasticamente o âmbito de uma eficaz autodeterminação informacional (informationelle Selbsbestimmungsrecht). b) Em segundo lugar, o acto médico é joje, em grande medida empreendido à margem do diálogo e da comunicação. São de todos os dias as situações em que, no contexto de uma cirurgia, e já com o paciente anestesiado, é urgente alargar a intervenção a domínios que não foram abrangidos pelo esclarecimento e pelo consentimento. Por outro lado e com uma frequência cada vez maior, a sociedade do risco (Risikogesellschaft) faz chegar aos hospitais caudais massificados de sinistrados, anónimos, inconscientes e sós, a necessitarem de intervenções que não é possível legitimar em nome do consentimento expresso ou, ao menos, concludente do paciente. Recordem-se ainda os progressos realizados ao nível do prolongamento da «vida«. Que vêm multiplicando as situações marginais, de fronteira entre a vida e a morte. E onde as exigências da vida, da dignidade e da indizibilidade da dor reclamam a decisão do médico à margem de qualquer comunicação com o paciente. O médico poderá saber − nomeadamente através do chamado Patiententestament − o que ele terá querido em momento anterior; antes, mas não è possível saber o que ele quererá agora, depois de «vividos« os instantes densificados «entre a vida e a morte«. Acolhendo-nos à lição do Ivan Illich de Tolstoi, que no leito da agonia se interrogava: «onde é que eu estarei, quando já aqui não estiver?». É o que pode ilustrar-se com a decisão de recusa ou interrupção de tratamento destinado a prolongar a «vida» do paciente que perdeu irreversivelmente a consciência, mas a propósito do qual não pode ainda falar-se de auxílio médico à morte (Sterbehilfe). Como acontece com os casos do que na Alemanha se designa por appalischer Syndrom ou, em linguagem anglossaxónica, o chamado persistent vegetative state (PVS). c) Em terceiro lugar, as novas realizações da ciência médica abriram a porta a intervenções cujas consequências, os custos e as vantagens se projectam para além dos limites do autorreferente sistema pessoal. Tenham-se em vista as intervenções médicas em benefício de um feto em gestação, que só é possível levar a cabo à custa do sacrifício de autonomia e da integridade física da mulher grávida. Pense-se no teste do HIV, realizado sobre uma pessoa, mas cujo resultado pode ditar a sorte de outros: nascituros, parceiros sexuais, médicos, etc. Uma Direito penal médico em mudança 93 consideração das coisas à vista da qual pode já pertinentemente falar-se de um dever de saber (duty to disclosure), contraposto ao emergente direito a não saber (right not to know ou Recht auf Nichtwissen). Por seu turno, os avanços da medicina predictiva ou predizente (sprechende Medizin) permitem antecipar «situações de risco« que lançam a sua sombra sobre o destino de muitas pessoas. Na expressão mais simples e óbvia: a descoberta de que A se mostra geneticamente propenso a contrair cancro, pode, se tempestivamente comunicada a B, seu parente, permitir levar a cabo oportunas medidas de profilaxia e prevenção. Tudo permite assim antecipar que o acto médico venha a ganhar uma cada vez mais exposta e ponderosa mais decisiva valência sistémico-social. E será seguramente assim mesmo postos entre parênteses os movimentos com maior conotação ideológica, que à sombra de um communitarian thinking − como o que vem sendo protagonizado por Amitai Etzioni − reivindicam uma ética e um direito da medicina voltados para a consideração privilegiada da public safety e do common good. 7. Esta nova experiência da medicina faz naturalmente adivinhar um novo − ou ao menos renovado − Direito Penal Médico. Um direito penal em decantação mas de que é possível desvelar sinais ou mostrações. A título de ilustração. a) A emergência de novos bens jurídicos, a elevar à constelação dos bens jurídico-criminais. Muitos deles bens de índole supraindividual, como a tantas vezes referenciado direito à identidade genética. Nesta linha não será arriscado questionar a elevação do já citado direito a não saber à categoria de autónomo bem jurídic o-criminal. Um direito que presta homenagem ao interesse legítimo do Homem em conduzir os trabalhos e os dias sem ter de sofrer em cada dia a dor e a morte que se antecipa. Desvelado e reconhecido a partir do «espanto» das realizações da medicina predictiva, não pode, em rigor, afirmar-se que ele seja, em toda a linha, uma criação recente. Como Gadamer recorda, na tragédia de Ésquilo (Prometeu agrilhoado), Prometeu, o amigo dos homens, declara que o grande benefício que lhes legou não foi tanto o fogo que abriu a porta de todas as artes. Mais importante do que isso, foi ter privado os homens de saber quando chegaria a hora da morte. Na interpretação do filósofo da hermenêutica: «é a motivação ligada à morte que dá à tragédia de Ésquilo a sua 94 Direito penal médico em mudança profundidade. O dom consiste em que vislumbre, do futuro que o Homen tem, o futuro que lhe confere o carácter de um presente tão apreensível que o fim se torna inconcebível. Alguém tem futuro enquanto não sabe que o não tem». Ou, dando a palavra ao próprio Ésquilo: «mais vale morrer de uma só vez do que ser infeliz todos os dias« (v.750). b) A re-conformação de bens jurídicos, ou, ao menos, a problematização da sua dimensão e recorte. Mesmo de bens jurídicos que pareciam gozar da estabilidade e definitividade das coisa cosmogonizadas. Como o próprio conceito de corpo humano, bem jurídico protegido pelo crime de Ofensas corporais. Recorda-se que à vista das descobertas das ciências genéticas sobra cada vez mais problemática a ideia consensualizada de tratamento partes separadas do corpo (tecidos, órgãos, matérias de extirpações, etc) como meras e vulgares coisas: E isto porquanto elas são portadores de um acervo incalculável de informação de óbvia dimensão pessoal. Por seu turno, a importância e a frequência crescentes dos transplantes na medicina dos nossos dias, obrigam a repensar o significado da danificação ou destruição dos órgãos e tecidos destinados a reimplante ou transplante. E que dizer da destruição de óvulos ou esperma crioconservados, que representavam a única possib ilidade de procriação de uma pessoa, em casos como o que foi recentemente (9.11.1993) decidido pelo Tribunal Federal alemão? c) Invenção ou redescoberta de novas figuras de legitimação do acto médico. Com destaque para o consentimento presumido, a ocupar cada vez mais o espaço do consentimento espresso ou concludente. Na certeza de que se trata de um «normatives Konstrukt» (Roxin) que legitima a intromissão na esfera jurídica de outrem em nome da sua vontade hipotética, aceitando-se o risco de ex post se concluir que a acção não correspondia à vontade do paciente. O que naturalmente obriga à definição exigente do regime jurídico da figura. Em que sobressai, por um lado, a subsidiaridade face ao consentimento espresso ou concludente, E, por outro lado, a vontade hipotética do paciente come matriz de legitimação axiológica e político-criminal. Vontade qe prevalence sobre a solução alternativa que, em concreto, possa considerar-se mais racional, segundo padrões de normalidade. Direito penal médico em mudança 95 IV. Conclusão 8. O registo das transformações assinaladas e a convicção de que outras, de maior amplitude e profundidadade, se deixam adivinhar, não levam consigo qualquer juízo de apoucamento da eminência e dignidade dos valores ao serviço dos quais se ergueu o Direito Penal Médico que chegou até aqui. Nomeadamente da vida, da integridade física e da autonomia do paciente. Eles continuam, pelo contrário, a cintilar como estrelas de primeira grandeza na constelação dos bens jurídico-criminais. Só que agora uma constelação densificada pela emergência de novos valores e bens jurídicos. O que significa que os bens jurídicos originários têm agora de realizar-se no contexto de novas e mais complexas relações de conflitualidade. De qualquer forma, mais do que de um novo Direito Penal Médico, talvez deva falar-se de un Direito renovado. É que, revertendo à alegoria de MERKEL, por detrás da nova folhagem com que a Primavera vai vestindo o Direito Penal Médico, persiste a mesma árvore. Ontem como hoje alimentada pela seiva dos mesmos e últimos valores: a preservação da vida e a libertação da dor no respeito pela autonomia e pela intangível dignidade da pessoa. «EQUITABLE SHARING» OF BENEFITS OF BIODIVERSITY-RELATED INNOVATION GUSTAVO GHIDINI Professor of Intellectual Property and Competition Law Luiss Guido Carli University, Rome, Italy 1. It is well known that much innovation in the pharmaceutical sector, as well as in the agricultural field (concerning seeds, in particular) is based on germplasm provided by plant and animal genetic resources: a «wealth» often referred to as «biodiversity», and which − while rarely and exceptionally surviving in Western in dustrialized countries (IC), has been fundamentally preserved by farmers of Developing Countries (DC) − «for cultural reasons which may escape those of us who equate wisdom to economic calculus»1 . Now, the innovation I am referring to stems typically from a «collaboration» between industrial countries and developing countries (DC). The former possess the technology which enables to develop new products for mass consumption (more advanced and efficient drugs and healthier and more resistant and/or abundant food) from the germplasm preserved, and provided, by the latter. And, of course, such innovation can be patented by its developers. In particular, it is well known the patenting of «an invention based on biological material of plant or animal origin» is expressly granted by European Directive No. 98/44. Thus, even thanks to patent protection, the biodiversity-related innovation can yeld potentially very high benefits both in strictly economic terms (return from sales and/or royalties in exclusive règime) as well as in techno-scientific progress (further impulse to R&D activities) and industrial and commercial advancement. 2. I will here examine, under a legal viewpoint, the problem of the «equitable sharing» of benefits accrued by biodiversity related innovation − chiefly in the pharmaceutical and food industry. This problem, as you know, is addressed by the Rio de Janeiro 1992 Convention on Biodiversity. Said Convention aims, on one hand, to grant the States sovereign rights to exploit their biological and genetic resources (1) RICOLFI, (2001), Biotechnology, Patents and Epistemic Approaches 98 «Equitable sharing» of benefits of biodiversity- related innovation (see Artt. 3 and 2), and therefore dictates that said States shall have the «authority to determine access to their genetic resources» (Art.15). On the other hand, the Convention sets as another fundamental goal of its «the fair and equitable sharing of the benefits arising out the utilization of genetic resources» (Art. 1). And to this end, it furtherly provides, i.a., that «Each Contracting Party (emphasis added) shall take legislative, administrative or policy measures, as appropriate, and in accordance with Articles 16 and 19, with the aim of sharing in a fair and equitable way the results of research and development and the benefits arising from the commercial and other utilization of genetic resources with the Contracting party providing such resources. Such sharing shall be upon mutually agreed terms.» 3. Accordingly, the «cooperation» between industrial and developing countries has been based on contractual relationships − directly with local rural communities, sometimes with the Governments, usually in form of a licence for exploitation of biological material granted by a rural community of a DC to a firm of an IC. Some, maybe most of such agreements usually attribute to the provider country a simple financial return, be it a lump sum and/or a royalty, from commercial exploitation of the new biodiversity based drug or food produce. Other agreements are more generous, in that they place a duty on the «industrial party», license of the biodiversity material and developer and owner of the patent on the new drug or seed, to «grant back» to the «provider» licensor (DC) a non-exclusive license «for research use» (see e.g. Art. 6.03 of the Agreement between the Peruvian Aguaruna and Huambisa Communities and G. D. Searle & Company (Monsanto) − text provided by Professor Charles McManis of Washington University, Mo., USA, and published in ATRIP's 1999 Annual Papers, 71). But please note: a) such license is «not for any commercial use» (ibidem) − and thus it could not be conferred to, and shared with, a locally operating industry; b) it is expressly foreseen that, whereas the indigenous people are free to continue to make and sell their traditional products, by no means the new drugs developed and patented by the industrial licensor can be deemed as an expression of «indigenous knowledge», and thus, obviously; c) there is no provision of co-ownership of the patents and/or know-how developed. «Equitable sharing» of benefits of biodiversity-related innovation 99 As a result, the biodiversity-related innovation, be it patented or not, will not pertain, even in part, to the indigenous people provider of the biodiversity (see. Art. 6.05). 4. In my opinion, such kind of agreements reflect and consolidate a substantial disproportion of contractual and economic power in that they do not grant a really «fair and equitable sharing» of «the results of research and development and the benefits arising from the commercial and other utilization of genetic resources», and thus also do not comply with the Rio Convention principles. I expressly leave aside the question of the intrinsic «fairness» of the entity of financial return usually granted to DC. What I assume here is that the concept of «fair and equitable sharing» should embrace the provider country's chance to participate in the industrial and commercial exploitation of biodiversity-related innovation (and thus, particularly, of related patents and know-how). Indeed, the Rio Convention's concept (as well as the commonsense concept) of «the results of research and development and the benefits arising from the commercial and other utilization of genetic resources», to which the principle of «fair and equitable sharing» applies, seems to me wide enough as to embrace that «spread» of scientific knowledge and (applied) know-how, and that development of new industrial and commercial activities, which embody the main social benefits related with actual exploitation of the achieved innovation. (Benefits which, always in my opinion, cannot be substituted by simple «abstract» knowledge, and thus simply by the grant of a sort of «fair use» right, such as the one foreseen in the Searle -Aguarunas Agreement I referred to above). Thus, I assume that a fully equitable sharing of benefits stemming from biodiversity − related innovation would be achieved only if the provider country could be given also the chance to «host» a direct exploitation − directly by the patent owner or, at its choice, through local licensees (even direct production in situ by the foreign − based firm does help the growth of a local, domestic «industrial know-how acquisition» (let aside employment-related benefits) of the innovation developed thanks also to its essential contribution. Thus the biodiversity providing country would be put in condition to progressively «grow» to R&D own capacity and develop (even in view of the time when the patent will be elapsed) a domestic industry and a domestic trade of new goods which it has helped to create. 100 «Equitable sharing» of benefits of biodiversity- related innovation Should the patent owner refuse either to produce or to appoint a license of its choice, an ad hoc measure of the provider country could foresee a compulsory license, which, according to TRIPs rules should be non-exclusive, non-discriminatory, based on fair terms (here taking into consideration the provider country's essential contribution to the developed innovation), and fundamentally focused to the supply of that very domestic market − thus not, if not marginally, to export (see TRIPs rules). This proposal seems consistent, even as far as IP is concerned, with Rio Convention. As recalled, same Convention empowers «Each Contracting Party» (emphasis added) to adopt legislative, administrative or policy measures aimed to achieve the fair sharing of results of R&D and the benefits arising from the commercial and other utilization of genetic resources (Art.1). Such adoption must be (see same Art.1) «in accordance» with Articles 16 and 19 of the Convention. Now, the former engages the parties to the Convention − thus including provider (DC) and recipient (IC) countries − to cooperate, subject to national legislation and international law, in order to ensure that patents and other IPRs «are supportive and do not run counter to its objectives. The latter, Art.19, provides that all parties to the Convention «shall take all practical measures to promote and advance priority access on a fair and equitable basis by Contracting parties, especially developing countries, to the results and benefits arising from biotechnologies based upon genetic resources provided by those Contracting parties» (emphasis added). 5. Nevertheless, the aforesaid proposal may seem unviable in legally positive terms − and thus, merely utopian − in view of the fact that the «universal IP law» of the WTO countries, i.e. the TRIPs agreement, 1996 (thence followed by national patent laws) has rejected (doesn't matter, here, under whose pressures) the long-time widely established principle of the so called «working requirements» of patent protection at national level, that is the duty to produce the patented goods in the country where patent protection is sought (see Art.27.1 ). This rejection, one might well argue, empowers the companies belonging to IC, recipient of the biodiversity, to sell exclusively everywhere − including the biodiversity providing country − the patented biodiversity − originated products, while retaining manufacture, hence actual capability to implement the relevant know-how, in their own homeland or in any other country where they find most convenient to set up production − thus, if they so wish, excluding the biodiversity providing country. In other words, TRIPs would allow that the provider country be «Equitable sharing» of benefits of biodiversity-related innovation 101 «reduced» to a mere import country, thus just be enabled to receive a monetary compensation (royalty), without any participation to the industrial development of the innovative products realized thanks − and first of all − to the biodiversity it preserved and provided. Should such interpretation be confirmed, the practical result would be bitter indeed. It would validate a commercial format that strongly reminds the good old typical colonial trade − off: the developing country «exporting» its «raw materials», and the industrialized countries «returning» their finished goods. A trade-off, of course, that − aside any other considerations, such as the ones referring to the traditionally strong price imbalance between DC «raw materials» and IC «finished products» − substantially delays the spreading and acquisition of industrial know-how amongst developing countries, and thus keeps same in a long term condition of economic and technical dependence. 6. Dura lex, sed lex? Shall we give up that proposal, at least under positive law? I don't think so. I do not share the view that Art. 27.1 of TRIPs constitutes an absolute bar to that proposal. Indeed, TRIPs' rejection of the «working requirements» expresses a general principle, whereas same Agreement allows, although exceptionally, and for reasons of public interest, the very imposition of compulsory licences on IPR's holders. See in particular Art. 31, providing for exceptional imposition of compulsory licenses («Other Use Without Authorization of the Right Holder») in connection with Art. 8.1, which states that «Members may, in formulating or amending their laws and regulations, adopt measures necessary to promote the public interest in sectors of vital importance to their socio − economic and technological development». (Please note that the compulsory license would be issued, as recalled, «predominantly for the supply of the domestic market», therefore basically not for export: see TRIPs Art. 31, f). Thus, should the biodiversity providing countries «take profit», so to say, of aforesaid rules (in connection with the powers they are granted under afore quoted norms of Rio Convention), the rejection of the working requirements would be respected in principle, i.e. in general perspective − vis-à-vis all other countries. The exception would accrue to the sole benefit of the biodiversity providing country, thus enabled to participate to the industrial and commercial utilization of the biodiversity − related innovation it has decisively helped to realize. 102 «Equitable sharing» of benefits of biodiversity- related innovation Thus, the proposal I outlined can be accepted, I believe, under existing legal regime. Its accomplishment, and no less, will achieve a truly «fair and equitable» sharing of the benefits − of all kinds − arising from the innovation the DC contributed to create. SOME REFLECTIONS ON THE USE OF CRIMINAL LAW FOR THE PROTECTION OF THE ENVIRONMENT(1) ANTONIO VERCHER Supreme Court Public Prosecutor, Madrid, Spain «We must sincerely pity our economists who doggedly debate the costs of the furniture of a house that has already burnt down» Anatole France (The Opinion of Jerome Coignard) I. Some Historical Considerations There are two historical periods which could be considered as real milestones in the evolution of the legal protection of the environment. These two periods are the so called Industrial Revolution, which took place in the first half of the 19th century, and the period of economic recovery that followed World War II. That second period lasted until the 70's in the 20th century. The clear connection that exists between economic development and the use of natural resources is well known. It is a truism that the more we develop industry, commerce, and other economic sectors, the more natural resources are needed. Human beings have been exploiting natural resources for centuries without nature having been seriously affected(2). Minerals, raw materials, water, air, etc., have been used in all sort of industrial activities (1) I would like to thank to my friend Mr. LIAM CASHMAN , Principal Administrator of the European Commission, for reading a draft of this paper. However, all errors and omissions remain my responsibility. (2) There were exceptional cases, however, of environmental problems and the subsequent social or political reaction. According to KISS and SHELTON, even in Fifth Century Rome, there were complaints that the Tiber river was seriously polluted by the filth of the city, as well as protests against odours emanating from various homes. One of the earliest known environmental measures is an ordinance adopted by Edward I in 1306 to prohibit the use of coal in open furnaces in London. Also in the Fourteenth Century, Charles VI forbade in Paris bad smelling and nauseating smoke. Vide KISS A. and SHELTON D., (1993), Manual of European Environmental Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, page 9. 104 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law throughout history without having seriously impinged on nature or natural resources. Traditionally, nature could easily recover without too many negative effects. Serious problems began when, as a result of the Industrial Revolution, natural resources began to be exploited, not lightly or occasionally as before, but in a systematic and significant manner. That situation provoked a sort of initial environmental protectionist approach and drove some European countries to enact environmental laws(3). Accordingly, it could be said, roughly speaking, that the Industrial Revolution was the starting point for the system of legal protection of the environment as it is known today. The laws enacted were basically civil and administrative, and were aimed at providing proper compensation when cases of pollution occurred, as well as at introducing an initial regulatory scheme to avoid damage and safeguard public health. It was generally not considered necessary to resort to criminal law, since instances of serious environmental disruptions were still not too widespread (although it is worth noting that early industrial towns suffered serious pollution), technology was still not advanced and the value attached to a clean environment was still limited. The situation changed radically with the reconstruction following World War II and the Marshall Plan, and the subsequent increase in exploitation of the natural resources. For the first time international public opinion began to demonstrate concern over the general state of the environment. It was a widespread movement developed in response to a visible envir onmental deterioration. Not coincidentally the concept of «ecological pessimism» also emerged. Not coincidentally either some literary works began to be published questioning the human behaviour affecting an important number of environmental aspects, such as Bertrand Russell's Has a Man Future? (4). The catalyst for many individuals and groups was the Torre Canyon accident in 1967, the first of a series of major oil tanker spills ( 5). This led to the search for new measures to combat environmental destruction. One of these measures was to resort to criminal environmental law and soon an increasing number of countries resorted to criminal law as a way of assuring environmental protection. The Japanese Diet was the first to come up with a truly criminal law for the punishment of environmental (3) The British Waterwork Clauses Act of 1845, the German General Industrial Code of 1845, etc. (4) I have been using the Spanish translation of the book. RUSSELL B., (1982), ¿Tiene el Hombre Futuro ? (Barcelona, Editorial Bruguera). (5) KISS A. and SHELTON D., Op. cit. pags. 9 and 10. Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 105 pollution offences, by its pioneering law, the Law for the Punishment of Pollution Offences, 1970. Several countries, following the Japanese example, enacted criminal environmental provisions in the form of special provisions or as a special part of their penal codes(6). Accordingly, serious environmental infractions or behaviour presumed to be hazardous to the environment have become criminal offences. This is an understandable reaction to a behaviour considered highly intolerable to society( 7). However, this criminalisation of actions which were not previously criminal offences, poses an important number of problems. It is, to a certain extent, understandable since there is a lack of precedents in relation to environmental crimes within criminal legal systems. This entails the need to face the whole subject-matter with a pioneer's perspective, since part of it is still an unexplored field. Let us see where the aforementioned problems lie, focusing on the more relevant. Some problems are of a general or abstract kind; others, however, are of a more practical character and are specifically connected to the day-to-day application of the law. The approach taken in this article is firstly, to describe and examine these problems, and secondly, to analyse the future perspectives of the use of criminal law for the protection of environment. II. General Aspects Regarding Problems of an Abstract Nature It could be said, first of all, that there is a key difference between what could be called the traditional or classical criminal law and the new area of criminal law aimed at avoiding environmental degradation. (6) PRABHU M., (1994), «General Report. Crimes against the Environment. Preparatory Colloquium», in International Review of Penal Law, vol. 65. Nos. 3-4, page 700. (7) «…there is a widespread concern that available regulatory instruments are not adequate to attack the ongoing threat posed by pollution to environment. The view has been expressed by the Law Reform Commission of Canada in Working Paper 44, that the pollution control armoury needs to be augmented by providing in the Criminal Code a separated new offence entitled crimes against the environment» in Pollution Control in Canada: the Regulatory Approach in the 1980s, Law Reform Commission of Canada, Administrative Law Series. Study Paper, 1988, page 69. 106 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law Roughly speaking, the traditional or classical criminal law tries to obtain «a certain degree of social stability ( 8)», using for that purpose methods of social control and, occasionally, prevention( 9). The expression «a certain degree of social stability» is used since it is commonly assumed that delinquency has never, and probably will never be completely eradicated from the social context. This is probably due to the fact that delinquency is inherent to society itself. Accordingly, wherever any social structure emerges, criminal actions cannot be ruled out. Environmental crimes, however, introduce a completely different perspective into the criminal legal system. While traditional criminality poses a menace to social stability, environmental crimes do not so much threaten social stability as pose a threat to the survival of human beings themselves. As a result, it is not the maintenance of social stability but the survival of society itself which is at stake. In this regard Commoner has noted that «The survival of all living things – including man – depends on the integrity of the complex web of biological processes which comprise the earth's ecosystem. However, what man is doing on the earth violates this fundamental requisite of human existence. For modern technologies act on the ecosystem which supports us in ways that threaten its stability; with tragic perversity we have linked much of our productive economy to precisely those features of technology which are ecologically destructive. These powerful, deeply entrenched relationships have locked us into a selfdestructive course(10)». This is the reason why Commoner describes this (8) This is why criminal law is, generally speaking, concerned with acts or omissions which are contrary to public order an society as a whole and which render the guilty person liable to punishment. Vide FARRAR J., (1977), Introduction to Legal Method, London, Sweet and Maxwell, page 16. Denham asserts that «Social deviance in general may be viewed as a failure to change society in a particular way, and criminal behaviour in particular is an acute form of deviance» DENHAM. P., (1983), A Modern Introduction to Law (London, Edward Arnold) page 150. (9) As SMITH and HOGAN indicated «While the definition of offences can adequately forbid unjustifiable and inexcusable conduct, it can rarely prevent it. The Children and Young Persons (Harmful Publications ) Act 1955 was said to have been completely successful at a time when no prosecution has been brought under it. But this is unusual». Vide SMITH J.C. and HOGAN B., (1983), Criminal Law, London, Butterworths page 5. (10) COMMONER B., (1975), The Ecological Facts of Life. in SHAW , B., Enviro nmental Law. People, Pollution and Land Use (St. Paul, Minn) West Publishing CO) pages 11-12. Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 107 process by resorting to the very strong expression, «suicidal track(11)». It is, nonetheless, an evolutionary and quite complex suicidal track(12). Secondly, it is also important to make clear that environmental crimes are «real» crimes. As has been stated before, there is at present considerable concern about the criminal nature of some serious environmental degradation. This concern reflects a new and widespread public ethic that demands a strong response to environmental abuse(13). This is why an important list of countries have criminalized serious environmental infractions, creating in that way a new specialised area within the criminal law system as a way of confronting serious environmental degradation. However, states initially resorted to criminal law as an alternative to solve social problems when other legal mechanisms had previously failed. In fact, some legal systems began to make use of criminal law as an alternative to protect the environment when no other options were left. In France, for instance, the crime of poaching, regulated by the Law of 15 April 1829 on «river fishing» was applied by the courts after 1859 to manufacturers who discharged any pollutant into the water, since there was not any other effective legislation to repress this type of behaviour. In the United States the potential significance of the Refuse Act of 1899, which made it a crime to discharge any refuse matter into the navigable waters of the United States without the permission of the Army Corp. of Engineers, was recognised by the Waters and Wetlands Report in 1970. In fact, it was the starting point for the use of Criminal Law for the protection of the environment in the United States. After the rediscovery of the Act there was a spate of criminal prosecutions aimed at avoiding environmental pollution( 14). More recently, it has been argued that the new crime related to (11) COMMONER B., Op. cit. page.12. «When the first cannons were fired, in the early fourteenth century, they affected ecology by sending workers scrambling to the forest and mountains for more potash, sulfur, iron, ore and charcoal, with some resulting erosion and defo restation. Hydrogen bombs are of a different order: a war fought with them might alter the genetics of all life on this planet». Vide W HITE LYNN Jr., The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis, in edit. by LORI GRUEN and DALE JAMIESON (Oxford, New York, Oxford University Press 1994) page 6. (13) «The (United States) Government's Memorandum» in Aid of Sentencing cited in the case United States v. Holley Electric Corp, Case No. 83-119-CR-J-6. (14) «After the 1970 Waters and Wetlands Report (...) prosecutors across the country began to wield the sword of strict criminal liability in the battle against water pollution.» Vide Mc NOLD D., UNKOVIC J.C. and LEVIN J.L., «Thoughts on the Role of (12) 108 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law land planning introduced in the recent 1995 Spanish Criminal Code enacted in 1995( 15) was an alternative to the lack of efficiency of the administrative sanctions which were normally being applied to serious land planning abuses. This is why environmental crimes have occasionally been defined as a sort of utilitarian solution( 16) to remedy the lack of efficient administrative measures to protect the environment. The fact is that criminal offences, especially environmental criminal offences, should not only be considered in terms of efficiency or utilitarian cost-benefit analysis. Whether efficient or inefficient, criminal provisions express society's moral condemnation of pollution. As Heine has very accurately indicated, circumstances such as the greenhouse effect, changes in climate, acid rain, etc., have all become part of a new scenario which ultimately involves the course of developments on which the future of human beings may depend. Accordingly, «it may appear as a necessity, even a duty for government to provide the criminal law with adequate instruments for the protection of the environment( 17)». However, this is not the only problem. It has been generally accepted that a «crime» means a serious breach of the criminal law. Nonetheless, when it comes to analysis of environmental crimes, there is a certain tendency to downgrade this specific type of criminality. Walker, for instances, asserts that «Nowadays there is a tendency to use «crime» to stigmatise almost any intentional behaviour of which the speaker disapproves. Calling a rubbish-dump a crime is a conservationist's way of stimulating public protest against something which is deplorable ( 18)...». Penalties in the Enforcement of the Clean Air and the Clean Water Acts». in Duquese Law Review, volume 17, No. 1, 1977-1978, page 4 . (15) Article 319 of the Spanish criminal code. (16) The classical utilitarian theories took the fundamental basis of morality to be a requirement that happiness should be maximised: the basic principle of utility required as to weight up the consequences , in terms of happiness or unhappiness, of various alternative actions, and choose that action which would, on balance, have the best consequences, in the sense of producing the largest net balance of happiness. Utilitarianism holds that, in deciding what we should do, we should consider only the consequences our actions: an action cannot be justified purely by its relationship to past facts. Vide SIMMONDS N.E., (1987), Central Issues in Jurisprudence. Justice, Law and Rights, London, Sweet and Maxwell, pages 15 and 17. (17) HEINE G., «Environmental Protection and Criminal Law», in Frontiers of Environmental Law, edit. By OWEN LOMAS , (1991), London, Chancery Law Publishingpages, 76-77. (18) W ALKER N., (1987), Crime and Criminology. A Critical Introduction, Oxford, New York, Oxford University Press, page 1. Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 109 Environmental crimes represent a new type of criminality, but nevertheless environmental crimes are real crimes. Judge Charles M. Allen expressed at the time of sentencing in the United States v. Donald Distler, that «It was and is the opinion of this court that business and industries who pollute our environment are guilty of grave crimes against man and nature themselves. Such crimes, if allowed to continue, will soon reach the point where their effects are irreversible by any known technology…( 19)». III. Some Practical Problems Posed by the Penal Protection of the Environment The penal protection of the environment raises some very interesting questions, some of which will be outlined in the following paragraphs. As has already been indicated, it is necessary to select those questions which appear to be more relevant. Otherwise, one runs the risk of getting involved in endless discussions, mainly taking into consideration the understandable limited character and nature of the Congress in which this paper will be submitted. III.1. Conceptual Problems Raised by the Criminal Protection of the Environment and the Need of Special Courts It has been previously asserted that the penal protection of the environment is relatively new. This is completely logical since environmental law itself is basically «virgin law», unprecedented in history. In fact, as has been observed, most environmental legislation has emerged in these last decades(20). Besides, environmental matters constitute a specialised area of science which has its own terminology, its own technical concepts, etc.. This means that the judiciary will have to deal with some special aspects with which it will not be familiar. Examples include pollution of the atmosphere, discharges to water, noise, waste, land planning, protected areas and release of poisonous substances. The emergence of certain fundamental principles underpinning environmental protection policy (such as the principle of preventing damage and the precautionary and polluter pays principles) also deserved recognition. (19) United States v. Donald F. Distler. Cr. No. 77-00108 (W.D. Ky. 1979). KRAMER L., (1989), «The Open Society, its Lawyers and its Environment», in Journal of Environmental Law, vol. 1, No. 1, page 9. (20) 110 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law For instance, the concept of environment itself was subject to strong discussion by the Spanish judiciary when it came to apply the first environmental offence introduced in the Spanish criminal code ( 21). This type of difficulty led the British Labour Party Policy Commission to recommend in 1994 in the United Kingdom an environmental division of the High Court ( 22). As De Prez asserted, such a court with a specialist bench would be better equipped to deal with the technical matters often raised in environmental disputes, and would perhaps have a better idea of what is reasonable or feasible to expect of industry in terms of pollution abatement(23). This explains as well why in the European context the Council of Europe Resolution (77) 28, on the Contribution of Criminal Law to the Protection of the Environment, recommended the establishment of specialist branches of courts and offices of public prosecution to be able to deal properly with environmental cases(24). From what has been said, it is evident that special courts will be better equipped to face technical matters. However special environmental courts will also be better prepared to avoid situations were environmental crimes could be treated as a sort of privileged crime. These situations may appear in cases were the courts lack the appropriate guidance or knowledge (21) The issue was finally resolved by the Spanish Supreme Court in a decision of November 30, 1990, which interpreted the term «environment» in a limited sense. According to the Supreme Court, criminal law protects the «ecological balance» from a human perspective and not in a general way. It is an anthropocentric view of environment and not an ecocentric one. (22) In Trust for Tomorrow. Labour Party Commission Report on the Environment. 1994, page. 50. This was previously recommended by Sir HARRY W OLF , Vide W OLF , Sir HARRY, Are the Judiciary Environmentally Myopic? in "Journal of Environmental Law, volume 4, No.1, 1992, page 13. (23) DE PREZ P., (2000), «Excuses, Excuses: The Ritual Trivialisation of Environmental Prosecutions», in Journal of Environmental Law, volume 12, No.1, page 76. (24) The Committee of Ministers made the following recommendations: «4. Re-examination of criminal procedure in matters of environmental protection and in particular: a) creation of specialist branches of courts and offices of public prosecution to deal with environmental cases; b) means of providing persons or gro ups the right to become associated with criminal proceedings for the defence of the interests of the community; c) creation of a special criminal register of persons convicted for pollution, independently of the general criminal register; d) exclusion from amnesty of serious criminal offences…». Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 111 on environmental matters. In this regard, the words of Michel Brown, the American EPA's (25) enforcement counsel, are expressive: «You have got judges out there who will put a man behind bars for shooting someone, but if the same guy dumps three buckets of stuff in a town's water supply that will destroy the guts of all of the people of that town for generations, he will draw a suspended sentence(26)». III.2. The Coexistence between Administrative and Criminal Environmental Law This is probably one of the most important obstacles when it comes to applying most criminal environmental provisions in countries with civil law jurisdictions. This is so because, as it will be seen, administrative law plays an essential role in the definition of environmental criminal offences. The situation varies in the United Kingdom − which is part of the common law legal system −, since its administrative justice approach is completely different from any civil law jurisdiction. Grottanelli de Santi, when comparing the systems of administrative justice in England and Italy, observes that «In Italy indeed, we speak of administrative justice, as in France, whereas the English speak of justice without attributes, and become suspicious and perplexed when faced with any special sort of justice such as military or ecclesiastical justice(27)». As a result, in the United Kingdom, the distinction between regulatory or administrative infractions and «real» crimes is not as clear as in countries like Germany or Spain 28 . Due to the fact that administrative law is not consistently defined in the different civil law countries(29) it is difficult to apply to them a common (25) Environmental Protection Agency, United States. The ORLANDO S ENTINEL . Sunday, October 9, 1983, page A-7. (27) GROTTANELLI goes saying, however, that despite the apparent differences between both systems (civil and common law), the real differences «lie less in the institutions or statutory texts than in the approach and way of thinking of judges». Vide GROTTANELLI DE SANTI G., (1986), «An Italian Looks at English Administrative Law», in Public Law, Spring, page.115. (28) Editor's note in Heine's article on Environmental Protection and Criminal Law. Vide HEINE G., Op. cit., page. 76. There are other differences, though. For instances, in the United Kingdom environmental criminal law is dominated by strict liability offences with prosecution generally undertaken by the Environmental Agency in front of a local lay magistrate. (29) HEINE G., Op. cit., pags. 82-86. Heine refers to four basic models in the relationship between criminal law and administrative law in the field of environmental protection. Those are as follows: criminal offences which are absolute independent of (26) 112 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law description. However, as a general rule, in these countries behaviour presumed hazardous to the environment may be subject to administrative legal rules as well as to repressive criminal law. This is so since «Most of the measures for environmental protection form part of the administrative law in order to submit harmful behaviour to prior control. These administrative devices are usually completed by repressive means which enable administrative agencies to ban unlawful activities (…) Whereas criminal prosecution is intended as reaction highly intolerable to society, these administrative offences are designed to suppressing mere unlawfulness not requiring an express moral verdict( 30)». Besides, administrative law uses concepts which have traditionally been outside the criminal legal system. Logically, a criminal law court may have problems to interpret them. Moreover, since the terms of administrative law serve different purposes in different contexts to those of criminal law, they lead to inappropriate results if adopted uncritically by criminal law. This coexistence, which frequently becomes an overlapping tension, between both sets of legal norms (administrative and criminal), is basically due to the fact that before it became common practice to draft criminal environmental legislation there were only administrative violations. Accordingly, what was a purely administrative field, is now a mixed administrative-criminal one. Previously, it was left to the administrative agency to lay down the permissible level of pollution through administrative regulations. Now, the criminal judicial authorities also intervene to decide whether the pollution caused is acceptable under the criminal law standards. Another very important problem that arises from that relationship is the incapability of the Public Administration to cope with the enormous control programme related to environment in the wider sense(31). However, very often, in order to determine the scope of criminal liability, penal law has, therefore, generally deferred to the definition of socially acceptable/unacceptable behaviour, made by the administrative law. administrative law (Model 1), criminal provisions absolutely dependent of administrative law (model 2), criminal law relatively dependent on administrative law (model 3) and environmental offences separated from the real crimes of the penal code (model 4). (30) PAEFFGEN H.U., «Overlapping Tensions between Criminal and Administrative Law: The Experience of West German Environmental Law», in Journal of Environmental Law, vol. 3, No.2, pages 247-248. (31) W INTER G., (1989), «Perspectives for Environmental Law – Entering the Fourth Phase», in Journal of Environmental Law, vol. 1, No.1, page 45. Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 113 Legal commentators have referred to a set of different questions which appears as a result of the coexistence of both set of legal norms. For instance, and according to the undeniable influence of administrative decisions on criminal liability, under certain circumstances an administrative decision, or even a lack of decision, may leave unapplied a criminal law provision. This is, for example, the case of what has been called «active tole ration» of pollution by administrative authorities. Paeffegen defines active toleration «when the applicant, relying on the permissibility of his purpose begins to pollute a river, etc., before actually receiving a formal consent, and when the administrative authority knowingly fails to take against him( 32)». Using other words, toleration is when administration, in the general pursuit of economic growth, declines to discipline one who breaches pollution regulations. Toleration is thus postulated to legitimise such offences and to avoid sanctions (33). It may also happen that in the discussion between the administrative authority and the public prosecutor, regarding the criminal character of the environmental infraction, if they do not reach an agreement there is always a risk of passivity on both sides, which is not so rare, for instances, in Holland, as Fangman pointed out( 34). In other cases, if the administrative authority intervenes with an administrative act that entirely covers the relevant criminal activity, then the author has committed no offence, since one of the definitional elements of the crime is missing( 35) or the administrative act is considered a defence justifying the author's action( 36). There are some other examples of this type of abuse and all them prove that in that sort of cases modern states − and their administrations − very often do not take a too «active» position in the protection of environment( 37). Moreover, they are occasionally capable of breaking the rules and of subverting the institutional order(38). Occasionally, as it is the case, in Germany the competent public authorities, following a purely (32) PAEFFGEN H.U., Op. cit., page 260. W INTER G., Op. cit., page 45. (34) FANGMAN N., (1990), Criminal Enforcement on Environmental Legislation. Environmental Enforcement Workshop. May 8-10, Utrecht, The Netherlands, page 131. (35) Since it is not an illegal act from the administrative point of view. (36) PAEFFGEN H.U., Op. cit., page 231. (37) LEPAGE JESSUA, C., «L'Etat ennemi ou protecteur de l'environnement», in La Vie Judiciaire, Du 19 au 25 Septembre 1988, page 9. (38) VERCHER A., (1990), «The Use of Criminal Law for the Protection of the Environment in Europe», Council of Europe Resolution (77) 28, in Northwestern Journal of International Law and Business,. Winter, vol. 10. No. 3, page 457. (33) 114 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law utilitarian strategy and even knowing the existence of a serious infraction, may enter into «futile and endless negotiations with the polluter (…) intervening for years. The motive of this strategy is to achieve better compliance with environmental provisions by imposing mutually agreed conditions than by the threat of punishment – the results often are poor nonetheless(39)». This type of negotiations has been equally problematic in Spain ( 40) and in Holland, although in the last case judicial authorities may participate in the negotiations themselves(41). Under these circumstances, can we make use of criminal prosecution against members of public administration for this kind of abuse? It is certainly possible, although it has to be admitted that it is extremely difficult to obtain a conviction. Up to the present, there is a limited number of convictions in Germany and none in Spain, although in the Spanish legal system new legal criminal provisions have recently been created to confront the possible criminal responsibility of administrative authorities in this sort of case(42). The reasons are obvious: very often the public administrative authorities carry on investigations, or even negotiations, without providing the proper information to the police or to the judicial authority. Moreover, a recent Spanish constitutional case(43) left open the possibility for administrative authorities to infringe the well known principle of «double jeopardy», also known in civil law jurisdiction as the «non bis in idem» principle. According to the Spanish Constitutional Court, the administrative authorities are allowed to sanction an environmental infraction from the administrative point of view and, after punishing it, to refer the case to the judicial authorities «in case there were any criminal responsibilities for the commission of a possible environmental penal offence(44)». In fact, the judicial authorities convicted the accused of (39) PAEFFEGEN H.U., Op.cit., page 261. That type of initiatives, as described in PAEFFGEN's quotation, are known in the Spanish legal system as «Programas de descontaminación gradual». (41) «There is an enormous investment in time for talks, often without matching results». FANGMAN N., Op. cit., page 134. (42) Articles 319, 321 and 329 of the 1995 Spanish penal law. (43) Court decisión 177/1999, of October 11th. (44) Vide TORRES FERNÁNDEZ M.E., «El Principio non bis in idem en la Jurisprudencia Constitucional», La Ley, 7 de junio de 2000. page 1 et seq.; DE VICENTE M ARTÍNEZ R., Teoría y Práctica o el Dr. Jekyll y Mr. Hyde (a Propósito de la Sentencia del Tribunal Constitucional 177/1999, de 11 de Octubre, sobre el Principio ne bis in idem. In: Actualidad Penal. No. 22. Semana de 29 de mayo al 4 de junio de 2000. También CORCOY BIDASOLO M. y GALLEGO SOLER J.I., «Infracción Administrativa e Infracción Penal en el Ambito del Delito Ambiental: ne bis in idem Material y Procesal», in (40) Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 115 releasing serious polluting substances into a river, an action that had been already sanctioned by the administrative authorities. III.3. Corporations and the Protection of the Environment The question could be put in the following way: A Corporation or a legal person, is an organised group of persons. If a person individually considered can be criminally and civilly liable for any kind of action, why when that person combines with some other persons, should that capacity disappear? Certainly there are not too many countries which adhered to the principle «Societas delinquere non potest(45)». For instance, France eliminated the aforementioned principle in its last penal code, as did Portugal. However, some other countries, and Spain is a good example, kept adhering to it. There are some important arguments to take into consideration when analysing the need to admit or to reject the adherence to the principle «Societas delinquere non potest», at least in cases of environmental crimes. First of all, as Hazlitt argued, «Corporate bodies are more corrupt and profligate than individuals, because they have more power to do mischief and are less amenable to disgrace or punishment. They feel neither shame, remorse, gratitude or good will… »( 46). Accordingly, the corporations' capacity to commit environmental offences must not be underestimated. Secondly, we must keep in mind that an environmental crime is a crime like any other, albeith a new crime born as a consequence of social, economical and industrial development. To consider it as a crime we must expand the stereotypical traditional definition of crime and the traditionally portrayed criminal, to embrace those who break this new form of socioeconomic and industrial wrong against society. Thirdly, reflecting the early and crucial role of corporations in anglosaxon economic development (now exported worldwide), the American Supreme Court long ago held that «It is true that there are some crimes which in their nature can be committed by corporations but there is a large Actualidad Penal,. No. 8. Semana de 21 al 27 de febrero de 2000. Also, VERCHER NOGUERA A., «La Incorporación del Principio "el que no corre vuela" en Derecho Constitucional», in Derecho y Medio Ambiente. Revista Jurídica para el Desarrollo Sostenible. vol. 1. No. 2. Abril-junio 2000, p age 67 et seq. (45) Civil law jurisdictions are based on Roman law and Roman law traditionally established the principle «societas delinquere non potest», that is, societies are unable to commit a criminal action and so only physical individuals have the capacity to infringe criminal law. (46) HAZLITT W., (1952), Table Talk , London, Everyman Editions, page 254. 116 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law class of offences (…) where in the crime consists in purposely doing the things prohibited by statutes. In that class of crimes we see not good reason why corporations may not be held responsible for and charged with the knowledge and purposes of their agents, acting within the authority conferred upon them(47)». Fourthly, perhaps the type of punishment applicable to corporations is the most complex point. The fact that a fine is the only type of punishment applicable to corporations is totally unfair. That is not only because managers and executives can go to jail for the commission of the same kind of crimes when their culpability is individual, but also because a fine does not have a properly deterrent effect on a corporation, considering that the amount of the fine can, like any other cost, be included in the cost/benefit balance. Judge Donald W. Van Artsdalen stated as follows: «As to the defendant there are two types of effective deterrents. One of course is imprisonment of the responsible official. The other is that the law provides for either or both, in cases of this sort. If the only punishment is a fine, the person might be inclined to violate the law and tend to look at it as being a bad business investment and they must pay a fine and thereafter can forget about any other type of restrain upon them48 ». Considering those facts, the research for new types of punishment applicable to corporations is not merely a theoretical problem but also a practical concern for schola rs and legal practitioners. Likely effective types of punishment that have been proposed include management intervention, community service order and adverse publicity. Management intervention may take the form of internal discipline and organizational reform orders. A community service order consists of requiring a corporate offender to undertake socially useful work projects tailored to the corporate offender capacity and resources. Finally, regarding adverse publicity it consists of publishing in the current press the court decision against the corporation. Of all them, adverse publicity (name and shame) could perhaps be the most effective, considering the nature and characteristics of corporations. In fact, according to Fisse, adverse publicity is «the quintessentially stigmatic corporate sanction( 49)». It is the type of sanction (47) New York Cent. H. R.R. Co. v. United States 212 U.S. 489, 494-495 (1909). United States v. Lanigen, Cr. No. 81-297 (E.D. PA. 1982). The owner and operator of a sanitary landfill was convicted for negligent violations of the American Clean Water Act and violations of the Refuse Act. (49) FISSE BRENT , (1982), «Reconstructing Corporate Criminal Law: Deterrence, Retribution, Fault and Sanctions», in Southern California Law Review, vol. 36, No. 4, page 1229. (48) Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 117 that has enjoyed the most considerable support because it affects the corporation's prestige as well as its financial success. In that regard, Fisse added: «…to attach the marke of Cain to a corporation is to strike at an organizational mantle which shields individual persons from being subjected to the stigma ( 50)». Corporate criminal law is, nonetheless, surrounded by complexities. It is important to point out that in some countries, such as the United States, China or Japan, where corporations can be prosecuted, to prosecute a corporation does not exonerate individuals implicated in the offence from criminal liability. However, it is often expedient to prosecute only the corporation because it spares the investigating and prosecuting officials the trouble of going behind the corporate veil and identifying the actual director, manager or other employee responsible for the crime. Such a task is particularly difficult in large and complex organisations ( 51). However, this is not the most important problem. The greatest lies in the fact that, as Laufer points out, referring to United States, corporate criminal law has moved through different phases, the last one being characterised by a novel sort of partnership of corporations with the government. This means a worrying Government-corporate cooperation where command and control strategies of corporate regulation has been replaced by negotiated compliance, coerced cooperation and regulatory persuasion( 52). IV. Recent Evolution of the System of Criminal Law for the Protection of the Environment in the European Context As is widely known, national and international environmental law have taken giant steps in the last decades. During this period of time, many countries, inspired by Principle I of the 1972 Stockholm Declaration, amended their Constitutions, thereby providing their citizens a guaranteed right to a safe and healthy environment or imposing on the state an obligation or duty to protect the environment, or in some cases imposing a similar obligation or duty on citizens. (50) FISSE BRENT , Op. cit., page. 1230. PRABHU M., Op. cit., page. 717. (52) LAUFER W. and GEIS G., (2001), «Corporate Criminal Law, Cooperative Regulation and the Parting of Paths», in Cahiers de Defense Sociale. Bulletin de la Société Internationale de Defense Sociale, pag. 103 et seq. (51) 118 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law The European continent has witnessed some important developments not only in the protection of the environment in general, but also in the use of criminal law for the protection of the environment. The legal developments which have taken place within the European Union on the protection of the environment are well known. It is a process that has been defined as «The emergence of the Community as an environmental actor (53)». The same could be said of the Council of Europe, especially taking into consideration its efforts to transform the right to a decent environment into a «real» human right( 54). It is not surprising, therefore, that both the Council of Europe and the European Union, have resorted, at a certain stage, to the criminal law for the protection of the environment. Let us analyze the use of criminal law for the protection of the environment separately in both organizations. We will begin, following a chronological order, with the Council of Europe. IV.1. The Council of Europe The penal protection of the environment became a matter of real concern in the Council of Europe in 1978, when the Committee of Ministers adopted Resolution (77)88 on the contribution of criminal law to the protection of the environment. The Committee of Ministers first considered the need to protect the health of human beings, animals and plants, and the beauty of landscapes. Second, the Committee considered that various aspects of present-day life, especially industrial development, entail a degree of pollution which is especially dangerous to the community. Finally, the Committee concluded that a need to resort to criminal law as an «ultima ratio» existed when other measures are ignored, ineffective or inappropr iate. Based on these conclusions, the Ministers made a number of recommendations to member state governments(55). (53) SCOTT J., (1998), EC Environmental Law, London and New York, Longman, page 4. (54) VERCHER NOGUERA A., «Derechos Humanos y Medio Ambiente», in Claves de Razón Práctica No.84. Julio/Agosto 1998. Page 14 and seq. (55) «1. Examination of criminal penalties for damage to the environment and whilst maintaining the traditional penalties of fine and imprisonment (possibly conditional) in the most serious cases: a) introduction in this field of particular forms of pecuniary penalty, such as daily fines (astreintes), day fines, s uspended fines and conditional fines; b) allocation of proceeds from pecuniary penalties for pollution to environmental uses; Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 119 Later on, the Council of Europe Justice Ministers' Resolution No 1 (1990) reaffirming Resolution (77)28, called upon Member States «…to examine the advisability of (i) drawing up a list of offences the purpose of which would be to provide adequate criminal law protection for water, soil, the air, and another components of the environment meriting protection, and also for man and in its environment; (ii) applying the concept of endangerment offences irrespective of the damage actually done, and (iii) making environmental impairment a criminal offence liable to prosecution not only in the country where the offence is committed but also in all countries where the offence had consequences, subject to the principle of avoiding double jeopardy». Following the adoption of the Resolution No.1 (1990), the Committee of Ministers of the Council of Europe established a new select committee of experts in 1991 under the name of the Group of Specialists on the protection of the environment through criminal law(56). On 4 November 1998 the Convention on the Protection of the Environment through Criminal Law opened for signature(57). The most outstanding points could be described as follows: 1) Article 2 of the Convention requires signatory countries to criminalise various serious offences(58). c) introduction in this field of measures such as restoration of the former state possibly ordered in connection with a suspended custodial penalty, work for the benefit of the community (as principal penalties) and publication of convictions: 2. Re-examination of the principles of criminal liability, with a view, in particular, to the possible introduction in certain cases of the liability of corporate bodies, public or private. 3. Examination of the advisability of criminalizing acts and omissions which culpably (intentionally or negligently) expose the life or health of human beings or property of substantial value to potential danger…». Vide as well note 19 supra, on the recommendation to introduce environmentally specialized courts and prosecutors. (56) In October 1991 it started to work and completed the new Convention for the protection of environment through criminal law in December 1995, after holding seven plenary and ten working group meetings. 57 For an analysis and discussion of the Convention vide CHAMOT C., «La Convention du Conseil de l'Europe sur la protection de l'environnement par le droit penal» (Strasbourg, 4 novembre 1998), in L'effectivité de Droit européen de l'environnement, edited by SANDRINE M ALJEAN-DUBOIS , (2000), Paris, La Documentation Francaise, page 199 et seq. (58) Release of substances or ionising radiation into air, soil, or water which causes death or serious injury to any person or creates a significant risk of causing death or serious injury. 120 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 2) Article 4 extends the scope of the Convention to a wide range of environment-related illegal conduct by a reference to «infringement of the law, an administrative regulation or a decision taken by a competent authority». Signatories can choose to impose criminal sanctions and/or measures, or administrative sanctions and/or measures. Other measures of a punitive nature may be the withdrawal of a permit, the prohibition to continue environmentally dangerous processes, etc., etc. 3) Article 9 requires signatories to impose corporate liability, without excluding criminal proceedings against natural persons. Through those, and other non-referred provisions, the Convention's basic aim is to approach the signatories' penal legislations on the protection of the environment, contributing in that way to increase its practical effectiveness(59). IV.2. The European Union International conventions constitute an important step towards the establishment of a real «system» of international penal law for the protection of the environment, rather than mere «principles(60)» the European Union has also open up new possibilities. These have been expressed throughout two different initiatives. On the one hand, Denmark presented an initiative for a framework Decision on combating serious environmental crime ( 61) in March 2000. The framework Decision is aimed at introducing minimum standards on prosecution and sanctions for major offences, looking as well an enhanced - Unlawful release of substances or ionising radiation into air, soil, or water which causes or is likely to cause their lasting deterioration or death or serious injury to any person or substantial damage to protected monuments, other protected objects, property, animals or plants. - Unlawful disposal, treatment, storage, transport, export, or import of hazardous waste, which causes or is likely to cause death or serious injury to any person or substantial damage to the quality of air, soil, water, animals or plants and unlawful operation of a in which a dangerous activity is carried out presenting the same risk, and - Unlawful manufacture, treatment, storage, use, transport, export or import of nuclear materials or other hazardous radioactive substances which causes or is likely to cause death or serious injury to any person or substantial damage to the quality of air, soil, water, animals or plants. (59) CHAMOT C., Op. cit., page 200. (60) BYUNG-SUN CHO, «¿El Surgimiento de un Derecho Penal Internacional del Medio Ambiente?», in Revista Penal, No.8, July 2001, page 22. (61) OJ C 39/4 of February 2000. Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 121 cooperation between Member States for detention and apprehension of offenders. Besides the Danish initiative, the European Commission presented a proposal for a Directive of the Parliament and of the Council on the Protection of the Environment through Criminal Law(62), which was published on 13 March 2001. IV.2.1 The Proposed Directive on the Protection of the Environment through Criminal Law The Explanatory Memorandum of the proposed Directive is quite clear when establishing the aims of the proposal and the reasons according to which the Commission decided to prepare it. The Explanatory Memorandum points out that «Experience has shown that the sanctions currently established by the Member States are nor always sufficient to achieve full compliance with Community law (…) In many cases, only criminal penalties will provide a sufficient dissuasive effect. First, the imposition of criminal sanctions demonstrates a social disapproval of a qualitatively different nature compared to administrative sanctions or a compensation mechanism under civil law. It sends a strong signal, with a much greater dissuasive effect, to offenders. For instance, administrative or other financial sanctions may not be dissuasive in cases where the offenders are impecunious or, on the contrary, financially very strong. Second, the means of criminal prosecution and investigation (and assistance between Member States) are more powerful than tools of administrative or civil law and can enhance effectiveness of investigation. Furthermore, there is an additional guarantee of impartiality of investigating authorities, because other author ities than those administrative authorities that have granted exploitation licences or authorizations to pollute will be involved in a criminal investigation». Let us to analyse the most outstanding points of the proposed directive. IV.2.1.a. A Minimum Standard in Criminal Offences The Explanatory Memorandum continues «Therefore, a minimum standard on constituent elements of criminal offences in breach of Community law protecting the environment needs to be established». Accordingly, the proposal does not cover all activities regulated by Community law, but only important types of pollution which can be (62) 2001. Commission proposal COM (2001)139 final., OJ C 180/238 E, of 26 June 122 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law attributed to individuals or legal persons. These are breaches of Community environmental law which constitute «serious impairments of the environment» and are listed in article 3( 63). It is evident that in the case of the proposed directive the role of administrative law, as a base for environmental offences, will be played by the Community's own environmental law. That is the reason why the Explanatory Memorandum states that «For reasons of legal certainty, the Annex to the proposed directive sets out exhaustively the relevant Community provisions, which prohibit the activities described in Article 3». However, this minimum standard may vary according to the development of environmental law. So, «For the purposes of this directive, any future modifications of the directive listed in the Annex will automatically apply to this directive. As regards future Community legislation each text will regulate itself to which extent criminal sanctions shall have to be provided for». This has the advantage that any criminal offence will be treated more thoroughly in each environmental directive and according to the different circumstances at any specific time. There are other important advantages. For instances, we said before that, occasionally, in the discussion between the administrative authority and the public prosecutor, regarding the criminal character of the environmental infraction, if they do not reach an agreement there is always a risk of passivity on both sides. It will be possible to avoid cases of administrative toleration. It is evident that the possibility to refer points of interpretation to the European Community Court, outside the administrative (63) According to article 3: «Member States shall ensure that the following activities are criminal offences, when committed intentionally or with serious negligence, as far as they breach the rules of Community law protecting the environment as set out in the Annex and/or rules adopted by Member States in order to comply with such Community law: a) the discharge of hydrocarbons, waste oil or sewage into water; b) the discharge, emission or introduction of a quantity of materials into air, soil or water and the treatment, disposal, storage, transport, export or import of hazardous waste; c) the discharge of waste on or into land or into water, including the operation of a landfill; d) the possession, taking, damaging, killing or trading of or in protected wild fauna and flora species or parts thereof; e) the significant deterioration of a protected habitat; f) trade in ozone-depleting substances; g) the operation of a plant in which a dangerous activity is carried out or in which dangerous substances or preparations are stored or used". Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 123 legal system of each Member State, and the fact that there will be an European directive at stake, may bring interesting new perspectives. Moreover, the Explanatory Memorandum also refers to new possibilities of judicial cooperation, which certainly may well improve the whole system itself ( 64). IV.2.1.b Corporations The proposed directive also refers to corporations, or legal persons (65), and the problem posed by the principle societas delinquere non potest, is still admitted by some Member States. Looking for a solution, the Explanatory Memorandum seeks for an intermediate way: «As concerns legal persons, it is essential for effective enforcement of Community law protecting the environment that legal persons can be held liable and that sanctions against legal persons are taken throughout the Community. However, for some Member States it might be difficult to provide for criminal sanctions against legal persons without changing fundamental principles of their national legal systems. Therefore, Member States would be able to foresee sanctions other than of criminal nature, as long as they are effective, proportionate and dissuasive. For instance, they could impose non-criminal fines, judicial supervision, judicial winding-up orders or exclusion from entitlement to public benefits or aid». Accordingly, article 4 provides, regarding natural persons, that «Member States shall provide for criminal penalties, involving in serious cases deprivation of liberty». However, when it comes to provide sanctions for legal persons (although it is applicable to natural persons as well), article 4 b) indicates that «Member States shall provide for fines, exclusion from entitlement to public benefits or aid, temporary or permanent disqualification from the practice of commercial activities, placing under judicial supervision winding up orders». In that way, the European proposal avoids corporations escaping environmental sanctions simply because they are not natural persons. It is easy to observe that the proposed directive has adopted an extremely pragmatic attitude, trying to obtain solutions to the problems (64) «Beyond the rules of this directive, further steps might have to be taken under the EU-Treaty, with regard to improved judicial cooperation. On the basis of the current discussion in the Council following the initiative of the Kingdom of Denmark, it may be envisaged to set up in addition a framework decision according to article 32 (2) b EU. It could concern criminal jurisdiction, measures guaranteeing mutual extradition and/or coordination of prosecutions and investigations» (65) Article 2 a) defines «legal persons» as «any legal entity having such status under the applicable national law, except for States or other public bodies acting in the exercise of their sovereign rights and for public international organizations». 124 Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law which have been posed by different legislations. In fact, the various legal systems of the European Union Member States probably cover the majority of the abovementioned problems. To provide a minimum standard for environmental crimes; to base criminal offences on environmental directives, listed in the Annex, which may increase in number with the different amendments of the directives; the introduction of a flexible system of sanctions for legal persons or corporations: all this implies a high level of flexibility and a powerful instrument towards harmonising the environmental penal system in Europe. The possibility to refer to the European Community Court of Justice is another positive aspect to take into consideration in the future development of this legal area. IV.2.2. The Present Situation At the time of writing, there seems to be certain conflict between the European Parliament and the European Commission, on the one hand, who support the proposed Directive and some Member States and the European Council, on the other, who support the Danish initiative. The reason for this different attitude on the use of criminal law for the protection of environment is rather obvious: whereas the proposed Directive is subject to full co-decision under the European Union's «first pillar», Denmark's «third pillar plan would be adopted by Governments alone, nor would the European Court of Justice have jurisdiction over its implementation. There are similarities, nonetheless, between both initiatives. Both would harmonise the definition of crimes against the environment and require Member States to put in place «effective and dissuasive» penalties against them. Neither would stipulate the precise punishment that offenders should receive. However, though the effects of the initiatives would be similar in practice, Member States fear the Commission proposal would set a precedent for further proposals in other areas of criminal law. This is perhaps be biggest obstacle. Accordingly, the conflict remains unsolved at present. V. Conclusions It is evident that environmental criminal law is undergoing an unstoppable evolution. In fact, although it practically did not exist at the beginning of the 70's, right now it is even proposed to be introduced in the European Union, something which was almost inconceivable just a few years ago. However, its unavoidable evolution is completely logical since it is an essential instrument to achieve effective protection of the Some Reflections on the Use of Criminal Law 125 environment. The newly created environmental criminal law had to face an important number of problems, due to its characteristics and nature. Recent developments, especially the proposed directive on the protection of the environment through criminal law and the Danish proposal on the same matter, have introduced new and interesting perspectives. In fact, both initiatives within the European Union had to search for new solutions as a way to harmonise the different penal legal systems existing within the European Union. This may represent – whatever be the solution adopted within the European Union – a force for innovation in this new legal area. THE CHALLENGES OF CRIMINAL LIABILITY. NEW ALTERNATIVES, LIMITS, FORMS AND GOALS MARIANO CIAFARDINI Secretary of Criminal Policy and Penitentiary Affairs, Ministry of Justice, Buenos Aires, Argentina Modern society imposes upon the actors of the criminal system of justice (jurists, legislators and judges, in that order) the adoption of measures oriented toward the achievement of the ends that characterize criminal law. It is essential that today's dogmatics of the illicit act aim at normatizing categories within the theory of punishable acts with a view to providing an answer to new social phenomena, without relaxing any individual rights guaranteed in the law. The proposed normatization is the basis for the full operation and respect for a democratic state and the rule of law. It is not unusual among us to hear arguments against the normatization of criminal law as a guiding instrument of state punishment. Those who oppose the normatization of criminal law maintain that the introduction of normative criteria in the various categories of the theory of the offence carries with it lesser guaranties for the individual. This idea, equally widespread and wrong, fails to take into account the social configuration of the end of the XXth century and the beginning of the XXI st . It seems that a new era has begun: that of special prevention; the end of criminal law is no longer the protection of legal interests but the validity of the norm. With respect to the definition of the offence, it is necessary to abandon the old causal-naturalistic doctrine to ascribe results to conduct. The analysis should not be one of a casuistic but of a regulatory nature. As to culpability, individuals must begin to be seen not as flesh-and-blood beings − as beings who are part of the natural world −, but as citizens with a social role to play. By this, I intend to provide grounds for a functional concept of culpability, forsaking all naturalist notions in this area as well. This functionalist criterion of culpability allows the introduction of the imposition of sanctions to collective legal entities into the criminal system; these legal persons, being entitled to rights and constrained by obligations, have a social role to play and actual capacity to threaten property or interests protected by the state (or, as I maintain here, to challenge the validity of the norm). 130 The Challenges of Criminal Liability a) The Protection of the Validity of the Norm and Special Prevention The new dogmatic conception has evolved around two axes: (1) a different notion regarding the ends of state punishment and (2) a focus on the question of whether the main purpose of criminal law is the protection of legal interests or the validity of the norm. Thus, those who see the mission of criminal law as the protection of legal interests and define these as «every desirable social state which the law wants to shield from harm(1)», adhere either to a retributive theory of the sanction or – and they constitute a vast majority today – to a relative theory of the sanction (and usually, general prevention). I cannot − and not only because of the importance that Professor Roxin has had in the Spanish-speaking academic world and especially in my country, but also because this will probably become the prevalent view in a few decades −, I cannot, then, not draw attention to this respected German professor's opinion in that it is primarily special prevention what is to prevail as the grounds for the imposition of sanctions by the state. «My conclusion is that, when it comes to fair sanctions, that is, those that do not go beyond the limits to fair punishment that arise from the principle of culpability, special and general prevention certainly still dominate the theory of the ends of the sanction, although these ends have found today a much richer content and a much more detailed scope for application than in the past. Also, and contrary to the current trend, special prevention has shown to play, as always, a central role in the theory of the ends of the sanction, while general prevention, which has been brought to the forefront these days, though certainly still deemed equally important, has been considered of relative importance with regard to the ends of the sanction, since its methods and scope are for the most part outside criminal law( 2)» . I hope I am not mistaken (and this is probably a wishful thinking) in asserting that special prevention will become the foundation on which the modern conception of the ends of the sanction shall develop. However, I think the view that advocates replacing the protection of legal interests as the mission of criminal law for the protection of the validity of the norm is regaining momentum today. With this I am trying to introduce a much- (1) W ELZEL HANS , (1987), Derecho penal aleman, Trad. Juan Bustos y Sergio Yánez Pérez, Santiago de Chile, pág.15. (2) ROXIN CLAUS , (2001), «Transformación de la teoría de los fines de la pena», publicado en Nuevas formulaciones en las ciencias penales, Córdoba, págs. 225 y sig. The Challenges of Criminal Liability 131 debated issue on the ends of criminal law and whether these lie in the protection of legal interests or rather, the validity of the norm. The social order cannot be exclusively defined in terms of goods but it also has to be defined in terms of the roles of legal persons. It is clear that criminal law has never restored a legal interest that has been harmed. Also, whenever a legal interest is irremediably lost (for example, in the case of a patient who, it has been established, will die in a few minutes due to poor medical assistance) the conduct that constitutes an attack on the patient's life, such as the firing of a gun still must be punished; but then (say functionalists) it is not a matter of legal interest but of guaranteeing those who are members of a society the expectancy that the norm banning homicide is valid, even when the legal interest it aims at protecting has been irremediably lost. It is not a question of protecting the legal interests of individual persons (who may, in fact, consent to the destruction of a legal interest, thus turning a conduct licit, for example, by consenting to somebody else's trespassing their property) but of guaranteeing society's expectancy as regards the validity of the norm. In this last example, we cannot say the legal interest has not been hurt, but rather, that the action carried out by the social agent does not challenge the validity of the norm and that, therefore, it cannot be sanctioned although the legal interest has actually been affected. «Society maintains norms and refuses to think of itself in any different way. According to this conception, the sanction is not just a means to maintain social identity but it constitutes that maintenance itself (…) The answer to a social problem through the application of criminal law is given through the application of the legal system as a partial social system, and this means that the answer is given within society. Thus, it is impossible to separate the criminal law from society ( 3)». The usual objection to this theory, i.e. that the theory could offer protection to any legal order is, in my view, invalid. Advocates of the theory of the legal interest maintain it would be impossible to turn state protection per se, the existence of a given political party or even, the purity of the human race, into a legal interest. These objections may seem sound enough, but from the perspective of the theory of the legal interest one can also choose norms to regulate people's lives. The theory of the legal interest (3) JACOBS GÜNTER, (1996), Sociedad, norma y persona en una teoría de un derecho penal funcional, Bogotá, pág. 14. 132 The Challenges of Criminal Liability shares with the functionalist theory the same critical starting point. The objection is a political, not a scientif ic one (4). The advocates of the theory of legal interests also reject functionalism on the basis that this theory, in its conviction about the value of legal norms, has raised them to the concept of legal interest and it is the legal interest − «respect for the validity of the norm» −, what criminal law protects. Time will show whether any of these conceptions (special prevention – protection of the validity of the norm) prevails over the other, since the protection of the validity of the norm is not compatible with special prevention and viceversa. The debate about the ends and meaning of state punishment is not over. And it will never be, since it is practically impossible to find the right answer. I have only attempted here to highlight the new trends that have developed over the past years (special prevention and protection of the validity of the norm). To sum up: «The discourse on the meaning and ends of the sanction is not an affair to which an end could have been put if we had found once and for all th e «right» answer to it, but one of those tasks for which there shall never be a final answer (5)». b) The Acceptance of Normative Limits to Causality The old theory of causality laid down naturalistic parameters for the imputation of a result to a given conduct. Thus, according to the traditional theory of equivalence every conduct is a cause providing that the result does not disappear if the cause is mentally suppressed. The simplicity of this theory, advocated by Julius Glaser in 1858 and by one of the members of the Reich's Supreme Tribunal in Germany, Justice von Buri, caused it to be rapidly accepted by jurisprudence and books of authority, a situation which lasted into the 1960's. The extent to which this theory could be stretched was (from its inception) clearly disproportionate to its intended aim. For example, if there was a road accident, the cause of the result (in the sense given it by the theory of the condition) was not only the driver's imprudence but also the car maker, the building company responsible for the construction of the freeway, the driver's parents, etc. (4) JAKOBS GÜNTER, (2000), ¿Qué protege el derecho penal: bienes jurídicos o la vigencia de la norma ?, Mendoza, pág. 54. (5) STRATENWERTH GÜNTER, (1996), ¿Qué aporta la teoría de los fines de la pena?, Bogotá, pág. 38. The Challenges of Criminal Liability 133 An attempt (naturalistic, of course) to limit causality was made by the theory of social adequacy. According to this theory (put forward by v. Kries) a cause will only be legally relevant if it is not improbable. This theory qualifies causal processes according to statistical criteria (was the result likely to happen?) and to criteria based on general perceptibility (did it happen in the usual way?); however, there are cases when certain causes can be normatively relevant even if the events in question did not occur in the usual way. The main shortcoming of the theory of equivalence (and of its corrective theory, the theory of social adequacy) is that it relies, erroneously, on statistics, experience and models that can be perceived through the senses instead of being based on the aim of criminal laws(6). Welzel's final − conduct doctrine brought about dramatic changes for several aspects of the theory of the offence and the resulting crisis of the concept of conduct is no other than a crisis revolving around the concept of subject that had served as a model. Up to then, the model of subject of criminal law was an individual whose behavior was determined by the influence of the method of analysis of natural sciences. In this sense, all human behavior was studied in the light of the law of causation, which gave way to a notion of conduct in which human beings were nothing more than a causal factor mediating between conduct and result. Welzel not only changed the concept of conduct and, consequently, that of culpability, but he also changed the notion of subject as such and the notion of society(7). From here, Honig took a critical step forward and denied that the ontological category of causality reflected the relationship between conduct and result correctly. In his view and bearing in mind the general ideas set forth by Larenz about imputation, what really counted for the law and for the definitions of the offence was something completely different: whether the result could be seen as the workings of a person and, consequently, whether it could be attributed to them(8). It is the modern theory of objective imputation that laid the foundations for the attribution of human conduct to legal subjects − and for the ascription of results to conduct − by acknowledging that individuals live today in a complex society, where everyone has a social role to play and (6) JAKOBS GÜNTER, (1995), Derecho Penal. Parte general. Fundamentos y teoría de la imputación, Madrid, pág. 243. (7) W ELZEL HANS , (1975), (Kausalität und Handlung), in «Abhandlungen zum System des Strafrechts und zur Rechtsphilosophie», Berlin/New York. (8) KHÖLER M ICHAEL, (2000), La imputación subjetiva: estado de la cuestión, Sobre el estado de la teoría del delito, Madrid, pág. 23 y ss. 134 The Challenges of Criminal Liability expects others to behave according to their own social role. Criminal laws do not govern human behavior arbitrarily but they do so in order to make social life possible, which cannot exist without the safety of expectations. In a highly industralized society, characterized by modern sociology as the collectivization of social life, we are faced with a situation in which it is necessary, on the one hand, to set limits to the liability of social actors, and, on the other, − if we accept a functionalist notion of culpability − to admit that not only physical persons can be criminally liable but collective legal entities as well. As regards the limits modern criminal law must set for the imputation of results to conduct, there are cases when, although the perpetrator creates a risk that may endanger other people's property (for example, the car maker's) such behavior falls outside the protective scope of criminal law since the benefits of societies having a car industry outweigh the drawbacks. Today life without the automobile has become inconceivable and since a society without risks is equally inconceivable and nobody is seriously thinking of living outside society, a normative guarantee entailing no risks has also become impossible: on the contrary, risks inherent to social life have to be irremediably tolerated, as an allowed risk(9). It goes without saying that a free society can only tolerate certain risks if the activity that creates the risk is justifiable to whoever will bear the costs: in a free society, freedom of behavior cannot be accepted to the detriment of others. Social cohabitation has to be built upon a consensus between coassociates, a consensus that certain parameters of behavior need to be followed since, otherwise, their existence would hinder rather than allow a harmonious social life. As a consequence of this consensus, whic h, at least at the theoretical level, must underlie norms of social behavior, it becomes essential that each individual be able to organize their activities on the assumption that others will also act in conformity with the law(10). I have said that there are some risks it is necessary for individuals to bear if they are to live in society. I would like to add that social life is impossible without division of labor. No individual can be in charge of everything. Think of complex medical equipment or aircraft maintenance, cases in which if each of the participants had to supervise everybody else's (9) JAKOBS GÜNTER, (1996), La imputación objetiva en derecho penal, Madrid, pág. 118 y sig. (10) A LVARADO YESID REYES , (1994), La imputación objetiva, Bogotá, pág. 141 y ss. The Challenges of Criminal Liability 135 work, they would not be able to perform their own tasks. Modern society cannot be conceived without the division of labor: if each social actor were answerable for everything, then there would be no benefits in the allotment of tasks − to say the least − since citizens would constantly be under the threat of criminal sanctions. No modern criminal law is possible without a principle of trust. c) Liability for the Event Based on a Functional Theory of Culpability. Criminal Liability of Collective Legal Entities As it has already been explained, modern dogmatic trends tend to maintain that the aim of criminal law is not the defense of property or other values protected by the law but the reaffirmation of the validity of the norm. Thus, Jakobs explains his position by means of the following example: a driver who is aware he is drunk when he drives his car and does not take into account the prejudicial consequences his conduct may have on the lives of others is expressing through his behavior complete disregard for the life of others. What this kind of behavior confirms is just the opposite of what is specifically provided in the criminal law for negligence cases. This contradiction of norm through conduct is a breach of the norm. This disregard for the norm – Jakobs goes on to explain – gives way to a social conflict in that it challenges the norm as an orientation model. The sanction is not an outside event, it is meaningful, i.e. the meaning of the deviant behavior is not determinant, what continues to be determinant is the norm(11). To sum up: the end of punishment is to help maintain the norm as an orientation model for social relationships. The content of the sanction is a response, imposed on whoever has challenged the norm(12). This view has substantially modified the concept of culpability. The paradigm of free will as an inescapable prerequisite of culpability based on the assumption that human beings are totally free to decide how to behave cannot be demonstrated empirically (13). The flaw in the old criterion has been to regard human beings and their freedom as they exist in the natural (11) JAKOBS GÜNTER, (1995), Derecho Penal. Parte general. Fundamentos y teoría de la imputación, Madrid, pág. 13. (12) JAKOBS GÜNTER, (1995), Derecho Penal. Parte general. Fundamentos y teoría de la imputación, Madrid, pág.14. (13) For details see FERNANDO CÓRDOBA, (2001), La capacidad de motivación y la imputación de responsabilidad, pág. 175 y ss., in "Nuevas formulaciones en las ciencias penales", Córdoba. 136 The Challenges of Criminal Liability world and to have been completely oblivious of the dimension of their social meaning(14). What is taken into consideration today to measure the existence or lack of culpability is the more comprehensive social role of the individual: its role as a law-abiding citizen(15). Instead of the objective value relationship jurists now resort to society's function (the system's). The presuppositions underlying culpability end up being determined according to teleological derivations of positive general prevention, thus losing their significance vis à vis legal subjects. The notion of culpability has to be functional, i.e., it has to be in line with certain normative principles. The evolution of the notion of subject – from subject in the natural world to subject in society − has paved the way for the discussion of criminal liability of collective legal entities and organizations. Modern theoreticians have found justification for the criminalization of organizations in ideas such as the need to protect legal values or the validity of the norm, without forsaking the principle of culpability as the sole source of legitimacy for sanctions or punishment. There is no doubt that an organization as such can challenge the validity of the norm, regardless of whether physical persons are criminally liable or not. In order to hold a legal entity criminally responsible it is necessary to verify whether a physical person has committed a crime while conducting transactions within the scope of the entity's business − from which the business should benefit − and also whether surveillance measures have been lacking or been inadequate to avoid the commission of the illegal act. It should also be mentioned that even those not personally involved would be criminally liable, according to the current theories on authorship and participation(16). There is also a need, from a political-criminal perspective, for the introduction of criminal liability of organizations. Several authors understand that criminal responsibility should only fall on those individuals whose conduct may be attributed to the organization on whose behalf they (14) CÓRDOBA FERNANDO, (2001), «La capacidad de motivación y la imputación de responsabilidad», Pág. 175 y ss in Nuevas formulaciones en las ciencias penales, Córdoba. (15) KHÖLER M ICHAEL, (2000), La imputación subjetiva: estado de la cuestión. Sobre el estado de la teoría del delito, Madrid, pág. 79 y ss. (16) SCHÜNEMAN B., (1979), Unternehmenskriminalität und Strafrecht – Eine Untersuchung der Verantwortlichkeit der Unternehmen und ihre Führungskräfte nach geltendem und geplanten Straf − und Ordnungswidrigkeitenrecht, Köln/Berlin/Bonn/ München. The Challenges of Criminal Liability 137 act, namely actions carried out by its organs, through its legal representatives or managers. Another condition is that the act in question should yield benefits for the organization (either actual or potential): the socalled 'functional relationship' between the act and the organization's scope of business, a normative relationship that does away with any remains of objective liability. The criminal system has reacted so far by resorting to parameters of individual authorship to address systematically organized crime. These parameters have to be supplemented with a doctrine based on social systems arising from the relationship between society and wrongdoing. By system I mean a set of organized relationships which may adopt legal form through the issuance of a charter. Just as there is personal liability and there are individual sanctions through which an individual's character may be improved, a sanction may also perform a social function and serve the purpose of improving the ends and organization of the social system. Criminal liability may be attributed to any unit taking part in social life, a physical person or an organization made up of physical persons. In other words, even if an organization is fictional as a phenomenon, it is not fictional as social system. It is for this reason that either individuals or social systems may be blamed from a social and ethical perspective, since a social system, as human institution, must produce, accept and fulfill ethical obligations (17). A functional concept of culpability must necessarily acknowledge criminal liability for organizations, as subjects with a role to play in the social system. At this point I would like to make it clear that what has been suggested here is, in my view, the paradigm of a liberal de jure State of the XXIst century. It should also be pointed out that the modern social configuration cannot relax in any way any of the individual rights guaranteed by international instruments and conventions, which have been incorporated into positive law by most states. In sum, I think this is a criminal law that has adjusted itself to today's world, a citizen's criminal law, as opposed to an enemy's criminal law. An enemy's criminal law optimizes the protection of legal values; a citizen's criminal law optimizes spheres of freedom(18). Criminal law is not so much about protecting legal values anymore, but about reestablishing the validity of the norm. Individuals are not regarded as flesh-and-blood beings but as legal subjects (17) LAMPE E.J., (1994), «Systemunrecht und Unrechtsysteme», Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, pág. 106. (18) JAKOBS GÜNTER, Estudios de Derecho Penal, en el artículo Criminalización en el estado previo a la lesión de un bien jurídico, pág. 298 y ss. 138 The Challenges of Criminal Liability fulfilling a social function. It is not possible to set naturalistic parameters to attribute conduct to results: the criterion has to be a normative one. CORPORATE CRIME AND A NEW BRAND OF COOPERATIVE REGULATION∗ WILLIAM S. LAUFER Associate Professor of Legal Studies and Sociology The Wharton School University of Pennsylvania, USA GILBERT GEIS Professor Emeritus Department of Criminology Law and Society, University of California, Irvine, USA I. Introduction It cannot be denied that the rapid development of the United States, which has astounded the world, has been largely due to combinations of individual wealth collected in large corporations for the purposes of enterprise. We owe much as a new country to them, but it is also true that as a country develops more fully, becomes more thickly settled and the individuals accumulate more wealth, the corporations seek to overstep the bounds of their charters and the laws of the country, and commit crimes( 1). Over a hundred years ago, Judge Cicero J. Lindley admonished members of the States Attorney's Association of Illinois to consider an emerging threat that will only increase as commercial life in the United States matures. Concentrated private wealth, large corporate conglomerates, and the prospect of intense commercial activity in interstate commerce, combine to pose a distinct challenge to law and law enforcement. Add to this the appearance of large trusts, powerful monopolies, and widespread corruption in certain industries. It is no wonder that courts and le gislatures regularly debated how best to control abuses of corporate power. (∗) An earlier version of this paper appeared in: Cahiers de défense sociale, 2001. That paper was an expanded version of «Corporate Prosecution, Cooperation, and the Trading of Favors », 87, Iowa L. Rev. (2002). (1) CICERO J. LINDLEY, (1899), «Criminal Acts of Corporations and Their Punishment», 7 Am. Lawyer, 564. 140 Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation Lindley's words came at a distinct turning point in the history of the criminal law. By the beginning of the Twentieth Century courts were frequently hearing cases of corporate nuisance and corporate misfeasance with a common law heritage that, for reasons having much to do with conceptions of corporate personhood, did not contemplate a role for the criminal law(2). It soon became clear, however, that the metaphysics of personhood was an insufficient obstacle. Logic and the absence of biology gave way to the necessity of criminal regulation, or at least the perception of its necessity(3). As Justice Day reasoned in the 1909 watershed case of New York Central Railroad, corporations make up much of the activity in interstate commerce. Restricting the criminal law in the regulation of interstate commerce would essentia lly immunize corporations and «virtually take away the only means of effectually controlling the subject matter and correcting the abuses aimed at it»( 4). With New York Central Railroad, the corporate criminal law was elevated above failed regulatory polic ies and practices. In the ensuing years, however, the divergence between the literal requirements of New York Central Railroad and actual regulatory practice grew dramatically. How and why this divergence took place will be briefly discussed in Part I of this paper. It would be a misstatement to conclude, however, that the corporate criminal law and, thus, corporate criminal liability, became something of a relic. Resort to the criminal law moved in an out of favor over the past Century. In recent years, the conventional wisdom endorses the coexistence of cooperative models of regulation and corporate criminal liability where (2) See, e.g., KATHLEEN F. BRICKEY, (1984), Corporate Criminal Liability. See, STEVEN D. WALT & W ILLIAM S. LAUFER, (1991), «Why Personhood Doesn't Matter: Corporate Criminal Liability and Sanctions », 18, Am. J. Crim. L., 263; STEVEN D. WALT and W ILLIAM S. LAUFER, (1992), «Corporate Criminal Liability and the Comparative Mix of Sanctions, in White Collar Crime Reconsidered, ed. Kip Schlegel and David Weisburd. For a lively debate on corporate personhood, see DONALD R. CRESSEY, (1988), «The Poverty of Theory in Corporate Crime Research», in 1 Advances in Criminological Theory» 31; JOHN BRAITHWAITE and BRENT FISSE, (1990), «On the Plausibility of Corporate Crime Control», in 2 Advances in Criminological Theory, 15; and GILBERT GEIS , (1994), «A Review, Rebuttal, and Reconciliation of Cressey and Braithwaite & Fisse on Criminological Theory and Corporate Crime », in 5 Advances in Criminological Theory, 321. (4) New York Central & Hudson River Railroad Company v. United States, 212 U.S., 481 (1909). (3) Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation 141 resort to the criminal law is literally the last resort(5). In Part II of this paper, we raise one of a number of limitations that plague this coexistence. Scholars have recognized the theoretical risks and limitations of complete reliance on the criminal law. Others have documented the distinct weaknesses of cooperative regulation. We restrict our discussion to the difficulties of protecting «blended» regulatory regimes from corporate abuses or «gaming.» Finally, we conclude that the evolution away from reliance on criminal law and command and control regulatory strategies in recent years requires either abiding faith in the character of compliance or, alternatively, a disinterested vigilance to ensure its integrity. We deny having the former and question, albeit optimistically, how this vigilance might be achieved when the interests of regulators and the regulated are so much aligned. I. Phases of Corporate Criminal Law The corporate criminal law has moved through five distinct phases (Figure 1). In the first phase, courts obsessed over the importance and meaning of corporate personhood. The individ ualistic bias of common law crimes made the attribution of liability seem both strange and wrong. Courts could only go so far. Without a soul, judges concluded that the idea of corporate mens rea was too much of a fiction. Between 1850 and 1910, however, rising concerns over new forms of market power and rapid market integration captured the public's attention. Corporate criminal liability, no matter how illusory or seemingly illogical, became increasingly appealing as a hedge against this power. In the second phase, initiated by the decision of New York Central Railroad, courts abandoned the nonfeasance-misfeasance distinction for reasons of practicality( 6). Corporate regulation in this new world of (5) See JOHN BRAITHWAITE, (1990), « Convergence in Models of Regulatory Strategy », 2 Current Issue Crim. Just., 59; see also IAN A YRES & JOHN BRAITHWAITE, (1992), Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate (articulating a new paradigm for regulatory cooperation); JOHN BRAITHWAITE, (1985), To Punish or Persuade: Enforcement of Coal Mine Safety (extending theories of self-regulation to the coal industry); JOHN BRAITHWAITE, (1982), « Enforced Self-Regulation: A New Strategy for Corporate Crime Control», 80 Mich. L. Rev. 1466 (proposing a new concept of regulatory cooperation). (6) W ILLIAM S. LAUFER, (1994), «Corporate Bodies and Guilty Minds », 43, EMORY L.J., 647, 651 − 58 (discussing origins of corporate criminal liability). 142 Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation interstate commerce necessitated a powerful and more formal social control. This was all the more true as the first merger wave ended and large corporations became increasingly decentralized. Centralized functions were now specialized and complex. In the years leading up to New York Central Railroad unease over loss of control across the managerial hierarchy invited the formality of criminal law(7). Vicarious corporate criminal liability soon became the rule of law in all federal courts. The phase that began with a set of clearly defined liability rules, derived from the tort law doctrine of respondeat superior, evolved into a protracted period of strategic risk shifting by employers and employees. Perceptions that vicarious fault was unduly strict and harsh prompted pleas by firms for a better understanding of the complexity of the corporate form and the diligence of management in promoting law abidance(8). No fewer than four years after New York Central Railroad, corporations were raising due diligence defenses. One cannot imagine a greater slight to the substantive law. How can corporations assume risks for the acts of their agents and, yet, avoid liability if they did their best to ensure compliance. A host of other risk shifting mechanisms, from fidelity bonds and a variety of other insurance products, characterized the liability posturing of both employers and employees. This posturing continued into the third phase distinct phase of the corporate criminal law, where there was a marked rise in regulatory power and regulatory law. Compliance replaced punishment as the preferred sanction in a regulatory era where the locus of enforcement was found in sweeping legislation, codified in a host of federal and state regulatory statutes. Labeled the Environmental-Consumerist Period by legal scholars, Congress and state legislatures turned their attention to «social costs of a successful industrial economy»( 9). By the end of this period, and the beginning of a subsequent phase of deregulation, literally thousands of criminal provisions were found in a wide range of federal statutory law(10). Marshall Clinard and his colleagues captured a glimpse of the effects of (7) See generally RICHARD S. GRUNER, (1994), Corporate Crime and Sentencing. W ILLIAM S. LAUFER, (1999), «Corporate Liability, Risk Shifting, and the Paradox of Compliance», 52, VAND. L. REV., 1343. (9) HARRY FIRST , (1990), Business Crimes, 4. (10) W ILLIAM S. LAUFER, Culpability and the Sentencing of Corporations, 71, «Neb. L. Rev. », 1049 (1992) (8) Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation 143 this new regulatory state on large corporations in their much-heralded work Illegal Corporate Behavior(11). In the fourth phase, spurred by the passage of the Sentencing Guidelines for Organizations, corporations were seduced into a novel partnership with government (see Figure 2). Following significant lobbying from bus iness associations, a congressionally appointed body − the United States Sentencing Commission − announced guidelines that govern the sentencing of corporations in federal courts. The timing of the release of the Sentencing Guidelines could not have been better. Congress approved the Sentencing Guidelines when dissatisfaction with the remaining command and control strategies of corporate regulation was paramount. Drafters of the Se ntencing Guidelines wanted corporations to face the threat of signif icant punishment and, at the same time, the possibility of mitigation, leniency, and amnesty. Theories of cooperative regulation and negotiated compliance, blended theories, could easily accommodate. The Sentencing Guidelines require judges to consider a base fine multiplied by a mitigation score. A corporation's willingness to accept responsibility, cooperate with author ities, and implement a compliance plan reveal due diligence. Of course, knowing the Sentencing Guidelines prescription for organizational due diligence in advance gives corporations incentive to demonstrate compliance so that, in the very unlikely event of a criminal investigation, liability is avoided or at least minimized. None of this logic was lost on a cottage industry of consultancies that soon after the passage of the Sentencing Guidelines turned corporate compliance into a large and, at least initially, profitable industry − all in the name of the Good Corporate Citizenship movement. The compliance industry deftly markets the story that evidence of organizational due diligence likely forestalls a criminal investigation, minimizes the likelihood of a criminal indictment, and regularly leads to a grant of governmental leniency, if not amnesty. Regulators and prosecutors decline cases involving corporations that demonstrate a commitment to compliance and actively cooperative with authorities. Declinations reward firms for their proactive, reactive, and cooperative efforts, reserving resources for the most abusive firms. Policy statements issued by the largest regulatory agencies reinforce the move away from command and control strategies to a brand of negotiated compliance, coerced cooperation, and regulatory persuasion. (11) M ARSHALL CLINARD, PETER C. YEAGER, JEANNE BRISSETTE, DAVID PETRASHEK and ELIZABETH HARRIES , (1979), Illegal Corporate Behavior. 144 Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation Most offer generous leniency and amnesty programs for corporate cooperators. Organizational cooperation and acceptance of responsibility are exchanged by corporations for mitigation, exculpation, or absolution. In fact, corporations have little choice but to trade favors with authorities with the threat of significant Guideline-prescribed fines. The result is a new enforcement landscape − one of substantial assistance, mitigation credits, and voluntary disclosure. In theory, the substantive corporate criminal law is unchanged since New York Central & Hudson River Railroad. In practice, negotiated compliance has all but replaced the substantive law. Corporate cooperation that facilitates the flow of evidence to authorities is the crit ical feature of this regulatory strategy. In the final and most recent phase, characterized by the high profile criminal cases against Arthur Andersen and Sotheby's; settlements with Merrill Lynch, Piper Jaffray, Xerox; and pending investigations against Enron, Worldcom, Qwest, Tyco, ImClone, Martha Stewart, Global Crossing, Dynegy, CMS Energy, El Paso Corp., Halliburton , and Williams Cos., calls for reforms − with a focus on greater individual accountability − have changed little in this landscape. II. Gaming the Partnership Critics of cooperative models credit their ineffectiveness to a combination of «structural constraints of regulatory agencies and the ideological, political, and economic consequences of these constraints»(12). Others focus on the inevitability of collusion and ask, «Who controls the controllers?»(13) We ask similar questions. Our focus, however, is on the effects of gaming «blended» regimes, particularly when regulatory incentives align corporate and governmental interests and create a partnership. The motives behind the creation of this partnership were entirely transparent. «The Guidelines' carrot and stick approach,» according to a former United States Attorney, «represents an unprecedented offer by the government for business to become the government's «partner» in (12) LAUREN SNIDER, «Regulating Corporate Behavior», in M.B. BLANKENSHIP , (1995), Understanding Corporate Criminality, 202. (13) GRAT VAN DEN HEUVEL, Corporate Crimes in the East and West: In Search of ‘Collusion.' Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation 145 controlling crime»( 14). This partnership is designed to increase compliance with laws and regulation; support proactive approaches to preventing unethical and illegal acts; open lines of communication about compliance concerns and failures; and align the interests of government with those of business. Can this partnership ever be too close? In what ways may corporations exploit this partnership to further shift liability risks? One disturbing trend, «Reverse whistleblowing» (RWB), provides answers to both of these questions. RWB is a risk shifting game that is played when an organization, through the actions of senior management, identifies culpable employees and offers evidence against them in a trade with prosecutors for corporate leniency or possible amnesty. RWB is the inverse of the familiar practice of employee whistleblowing. Instead of employees identifying corporate deviance, the practice of RWB identifies deviant employees. In law-abiding organizations, RWB is often justified as a strategy necessary for survival. Unfortunately, however, corporations that share culpability practice RWB to displace blame. In the consensual form of RWB, or consensual «scapegoating,» a corporate agent willingly takes responsibility for a «corporate» wrong. In the more disturbing nonconsensual form, credible though not entirely deserving agents are blamed. In both cases, RWB is rationalized as a necessary compromise to maintain the viability and health of the entity. In both cases, RWB often produces a divergence of interests between management and employees that inevitably leads to actions that appear far less than fair, such as the scapegoating of subordinate employees for the acts of the company. The concern is that subordinate employees with a peripheral connection to organizational deviance will be treated as expendable, particularly when corporate counsel and regulators begin bargaining over criminal liability. «Corporations, if left to their own devices,» according to Brent Fisse and John Braithwaite, «will try to deflect responsibility to a select group of sacrificial personnel, often at a lower level than the actual source of skullduggery»( 15). Blaming subordinates may be nothing more than shielding senior managers and the entity from criminal liability. Harsh and unjustified (14) OTTO G. OBERMAIER, (1991), «A Practical Partnership », National Law Journal, Nov. 11, at 13. (15) BRENT FISSE & JOHN BRAITHWAITE, (1983), Corporations, Crime and Accountability, 29. 146 Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation discipline of employees may be practiced only to satisfy perceptions of Guidelines' compliance. The focus on securing evidence of wrongdoing routinely compromises the rights of employees, including the right against self-incrimination. Prosecutors are known to have coerced employers to pressure suspected employees. Concerns over waivers of attorney-client privilege chill internal investigations. The mad dash to the prosecutor's office by organizations to self-report can compromise the quality of information tendered. Finally, all of this has led to a discernable shift in the role of corporate counsel, from employee advocate to government agent or informant Five factors determine whether the practice of RWB raise fundamental questions of fairness? First, the relationship between the criminal act alleged and the actions of the entity. The greatest risk lies where a signif icant connection exists between the acts of an employee and the actions (or inactions) of the entity converge. For example, fairness concerns are magnified where top management is complicit or where middle management tacitly encourages employees. Organizations that are tightly coupled face increased risks of criminal liability. Corporations tend toward decentralized, divisionalized, loosely coupled structures as they mature in size and specialization. This evolution, some claim, «allows the corporation to take advantage of opportunities as they arise and react quickly to threats, in and from the task environment. It also allows the organization to distance itself from illegal actions, illegal actors, and undesirable attention»( 16). Determining a significant connection between the actions of the corporation and an employee's act, therefore, is often extremely difficult. Loosely coupled organizations are well designed to scapegoat employees without detection. Second, fairness concerns raise the extent to which officers, senior executives, and senior managers condoned the commission of the offense or knew or consciously disregarded knowledge of the illegality. Where senior managers instructed others to commit the offense, were aware of the illegalities, or consciously disregarded the commission of the offense, the risk is greatest. This state of mind variable, like the action variable discussed above, is related to firm size and decentralization. Evidence of corporate knowledge or action is much more difficult to obtain in (16) CARL KEANE, (1995), « Loosely Coupled Systems and Unlawful Behaviour: Organization Theory and Corporate Crime », in Corporate Crime: Contemporary Debates, 168, 169 (Frank Pearce et al. eds.). Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation 147 organizations where decision making is tied to an informal culture of «nudges and winks, of rules which are not really meant to be obeyed»(17). A third variable is the relationship of offending employees to those cooperating with the government. Fairness concerns are greatest where the status of the employee being investigated or charged is far subordinate to those offering cooperation. The notion of scapegoating requires more than mere substitution; scapegoats must be disposable and worthy of being disposed. Ideally, from the perspective of the corporation, a scapegoat should be weak and unable to retaliate. Fourth, the character and quality of compliance initiatives are crit ical. Nonconsensual RWB appears that much more likely in cases where firms purchase compliance to the minimum requirements of prevailing laws − purchases that go to satisfy the impressions of regulators. Finally, the existence of a corporate culture embraced by leadership and committed to organizational integrity minimizes fairness concerns. III. Conclusion The practice of RWB provides a glimpse of the limitations of a cooperative regulation in a blended regime. It is but one unfortunate artifact of a growing trend to exalt the value of corporate cooperation. What signal is sent to employees when it becomes clear that the loyalties of corporate counsel, outside counsel, and prosecutors continue to converge? The answer seems clear. Every year following passage of the Sentencing Guidelines, there has been a noticeable escalation in prosecutorial expectations of organizational cooperation − an escalation made public in the criminal investigations of Prudential Securities, Salomon Brothers, and Sequa Corporation. In each case, crimes were ultimately recast as actions of wayward employees, rather than those of the organization after these targeted corporations satisfied prosecutorial demands for cooperation. The lesson was simple − in the unlikely event that criminal activity is identified in an organization, joining with prosecutors in offering boundless cooperation may very well avert even a near death experience. Without the pressures from this partnership and with unwavering faith in the character of corporate compliance, no one would doubt the integrity of blended (17) BRENT FISSE & JOHN BRAITHWAITE, (1983), Corporations, Crime and Accountability, 184. 148 Corporate Crime and a New Brand of Cooperative Regulation cooperative regimes. But the pressures are real and the metrics for assessing corporate compliance are far from perfect. To address the pressures and the prospects of gaming, there appears one simple solution: increase organizational transparency. Braithwaite's notion of tripartism and Shearing's model of constitutive regulation leverage the power and place of consumer lobbies, unions, and nongovernmental organizations ( 18). Third party participation in the regulatory process may be the most elegant solution to ensure a true compliance and, yet, genuinely combat deviance. Proposals to leverage public interest groups and their capability to more formally monitor the regulated and regulators may hold the greatest promise. (18) See A YRES & BRAITHWAITE, supra note 7, at 54 («[T]ripatism might prevent harmful capture, identify and encourage efficient capture, enhance the attainment of regulatory goals, and strengthen d emocracy.») HOW TO DETERMINE INDIVIDUAL CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY IN SYSTEMIC CONTEXTS: TWELVE MODELS JOACHIM VOGEL Professor and Holder of the Chair of Criminal Law and Criminal Procedure University of Tuebingen Justice at the High Court of Appeal, Criminal Division, Stuttgart, Germany I. Introduction It is agreed that criminal responsibility is individual responsibility. But who is an individual? And who exactly is responsible? The traditional answer to the first question is: a natural person; the traditional answer to the second question: a natural person who voluntarily did an act and knowingly contributed to the criminal result. However, the problem arises whether these traditional answers reflect the systemic structures of modern society. To quote my esteemed colleagues Simone Rozès and Edmondo BrutiLiberati (Provisional Programme): Starting from the division of labour …, there is no longer a ‘central’ figure to charge with liability within the company, since the company worker does not meet the legal requirements to qualify as the author of a crime (producer, exporter, etc.), and company directors or executives themselves are not the material authors of the facts contested in law. Hence the idea of not (only) referring natural persons, but (also) corporate entities to a criminal court. Indeed, there are at least three areas of crime where such problems arise: economic and environmental crime which is typically committed within the framework of companies; organized crime which is committed within the framework of criminal organisations; and last but not least «state crime» which is committed within the framework of governments, armies, police bodies, bureaucracies etc. In these areas many legal systems all over the world have developed special legal regimes to cope with the problem of how to determine individual criminal responsibility in systemic contexts. These legal regimes are partly based on statute law – e.g. the statutory provisions on criminal responsibility of legal persons in the French Nouveau Code Penal – and partly on case law – e.g. the German figure of «Organisationsherrschaft» 152 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts (dominion of an organisation), the French «responsabilité pour fait d’autrui» or the common law «strict» or «vicarious liability» and, in military contexts, the «respondeat superior»-principle. It is absolutely impossible to present even a small fraction of these many and different legal regimes during a 30 minutes lecture. Therefore, I would like to go to a more theoretical, more abstract level and present twelve models of how we can possibly determine individual criminal responsibility in systemic contexts. My analysis differs significantly from the traditional analysis of legal regimes on individual criminal responsibility. Therefore, I would like to start with a short criticism of the traditional analysis and only afterwards turn to my own, new analysis. II. The traditional analysis: «monistic» vs. «dualistic/pluralistic» model In Germany as well as in other Member States of the European Union, we find a classical analysis of the law of individual responsibility, parties to the offence and participation in the offence. According to that analysis, there are only two possible models of legal rules in this area(1): Either a criminal law system is based on a «monistic model» (in German legal terminology: «Einheitstätersystem»). Its basic idea is that each individual contributing to an offence is liable as perpetrator and responsible as such – regardless of the significance of the contribution. Its significance may of course influence the sentencing process but not the responsibility as such. A monistic system can be found, for instance, in Austrian criminal law and – although contested in the legal discussion – in Italian criminal law (Art. 110 Criminal Code). Or a legal system makes use of the «dualistic/pluralistic model» (in German legal terminology: «Beteiligungs» or «Teilnahmesystem»). The basic idea is to distinguish at least two types of parties to the offence: main offenders or perpetrators or authors on the one hand; mere accomplices, instigators, aiders and abettors on the other hand. Such a system can be found, for instance, in German, Spanish or English criminal law. The (1) BAUMANN/W EBER /M ITSCH, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, 10. Aufl. (1995), § 28 margin Nos. 10 et seq.; JAKOBS, Stra frecht Allgemeiner Teil, 2. Aufl., (1991), 21/1 et seq.; KÜHL, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, 3. Aufl., (2000), § 20 margin Nos. 8 et seq.; SCHÖNKE/SCHRÖDER-CRAMER/HEINE, Aufl., (2001), StGB, 26. vor § 25 margin Nos. 6 et seq. – RENZIKOWSKI (1997), Restriktiver Täterbegriff und fahrlässige Beteiligung, p. 10, presumes that in the concept of participation − only? − two terms for distinction are available: «System of participation» and «monolistic model» («Einheitstäterbegriff»). Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 153 dualistic/pluralistic model is said to be closer to social reality where primary and secondary responsibility are distinguished. ( 2) However, the question arises which are the legal criteria to distinguish between main offenders and secondary parties. Traditionally, the distinction is based on subjective elements: the intention of the person contributing to the offence as an author or only as an accomplice («animus auctoris», «animus socii»(3)). Today, legal scholars try to identify more objective criteria such as the significance of the contribution and the individual position of the contributor. In German doctrine, the figure of «Tatherrschaft» (dominion of the act) has been developed by my famous Munich colleague Claus Roxin and has been, to some extent, accepted by German jurisprudence. Anyway, it is clear that the liability of mere accomplices, instigators, aiders and abettors is derived from the liability of the main perpetrator which is called in German «Akzessorietät», in French «emprunt de la criminalité», in English «derivative responsibility». Although the traditional analysis is well established, I feel that it is quite insufficient. It focuses on active and voluntary participation in the offence. But participation by omission – breach of a duty to act(4) – is not covered; neither are negligent offences(5) and offences which can only be committed by qualified persons ( 6) (what is called in German doctrine «Sonderdelikte »). The analysis gives rise to pointless questions such as the Austrian discussion on whether Austrian criminal law really belongs to the monistic model or to a functionally dualistic model( 7). It does not integrate many new forms of individual responsibility and participation we find in comparative criminal law, for instance vicarious liability, responsabilité pour fait d’autrui ou de chef d’entreprise, conspiracy, complicity after fact and responsibility of legal persons. But above all, the traditional analysis is based on a very limited, very technical concept of participation in the offence: the situation that an individual participates in a well-defined, consummated or at least attempted offence committed by another individual. In social life, we often encounter very different situations: more (2) PAUL, Der Strafverteidiger (1998), p. 623 (624); LANGER, Das Sonderverbrechen, pp. 375-376. (3) RGSt 74, 84 (4) Handling these cases is discussed in JAKOBS , (note 1) 29/101 et seq.; ROXIN, Täterschaft und Tatherrschaft, 7. Aufl., (2000), pp. 458 et seq., pp. 702 et seq. (5) Handling these cases is discussed in RENZIKOWSKI, (note1), passim. (6) Handling these cases is discussed in JAKOBS (note 1), 21/2, margin Nos. 115 et seq.; ROXIN (note 4), pp. 352 et seq., pp. 695 et seq. (7) Disussed by BURGSTALLER in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (eds.) (1998), Einzelverantwortung und Mitverantwortung im Strafrecht, p. 13 (pp. 25 et seq.). 154 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts or less structured organisations, even loose networks, which are fully or partly or only exceptionally involved in criminal activities, and individuals which contribute to these activities in various forms – actively or passively – and on various levels. That is what I mean by «systemic contexts». So I feel that the base of an adequate theory of participation in the offence in systemic contexts must be a non-technical, functional understanding of participation as any contribution to criminal activities. Such a comprehensive understanding enables us, for instance, to realize that various new offences such as membership in a criminal organisation, money laundering, financing of terrorism or incitement to genocide are – of course – forms of participation. And it is not surprising that we find a lot more models of legal rules on participation than the «monistic» and «dualistic/pluralistic» model. III. A new analysis: «naturalistic» vs. «normative» model; «individual» vs. «systemic» model; «sentencing orientated» vs. «responsibility orie ntated» model; «special part» vs. «general part» model; «imputation» model; «supervision» model; «conspiracy» model; «collective responsibility» model Indeed, we can identify not less than twelve possible models (which do not exclude each other but can be found, in positive criminal law, in various combinations). Although I am not quite sure whether the English terminology is convincing, I would like to call them: «naturalistic» vs. «normative» model; «individual» vs. «systemic» model; «sentencing orientated» vs. «responsibility orientated» model; «special part» vs. «general part» model; «imputation» model; «supervision» model; «conspiracy» model; «collective responsibility» model. Let us have a look at what is behind these terms: 1. and 2. «Naturalistic» vs. «normative» model Traditionally, participation is a naturalistic concept and means «causal contribution to the offence» or «an act which results in an offence being committed». The causal chain is essential, but also (setting mens rea aside) sufficient. If you apply such a naturalistic concept to complex systemic structures, for instance a company or an army, you will end up at what has been called in German legal discussion «bottom up approach»: You will start with the immediate actors, e.g. workers assembling a dangerous machine or soldiers shooting civilians; proceed to the middle Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 155 level, e.g. construction managers or field officers; and finally reach the top level, e.g. the board of directors or the general staff. The longer the causal chain, the more difficult it is to establish individual responsibility, for instance by proving a command chain (a problem very clearly to be seen in The Hague at the moment). On the other hand, the immediate actors often simply do not know enough to be guilty of an offence, or they can plead necessity, order, mistake of law etc. These problems can be overcome if the naturalistic model is replaced by a normative model. In a normative model, the leading concept is neither «participation» nor «causality» but «responsibility». Responsibility does not necessarily require positive and full causality( 8). A co-perpetrator or accomplice is responsible even if he had not had any decisive influence on the offence being committed or not. A person with supervisory authority and duty is responsible if he could have influenced the offence. There are inchoate offences – e.g. incitement to commit genocide – where criminal responsibility exists even if the main offence has not (yet) been committed. If you apply a normative model in a systemic environment, you will end up at what has been called in German legal discussion as «top-downapproach»: You will start with those who have the «main responsibility», e.g. directors, generals, political leaders, and work your way down the ranks until you finish with the «small fish»( 9). You will argue that, if the «small fish» is responsible as perpetrator, the «big fish» must be responsible as perpetrator, as well. In effect, nearly all will be treated as perpetrators (so that a normative model leads to some kind of monistic model in the sense explained before(10)). The present tendency is clearly in favour of the normative model. It lies at the very heart of international criminal law and can be studied in the jurisprudence of the I.C.T.Y. and I.C.T.R. and also in the Rome Statute of the I.C.C. But also national legislations and natio nal courts prefer normative approaches. For instance, the German Federal Supreme Court has developed a doctrine of «Organisationsherrschaft» (dominion of an organisation) to hold leaders of an organisation – a state, a company, a criminal organisation – liable as main perpetrators even if they neither (8) German law: RGSt 58, 113 (114); BGHSt 37, 106 (129); contrary to this LACKNER/KÜHL, StGB, 24. Aufl., (2001), § 25 margin No. 11 (Mittäterschaft), § 27 margin No. 2 (Beihilfe) [including further references]. (9) The terms go back to SCHMIDT -SALZER (1992), Betriebs-Berater, p. 1866 (p. 1869). (10) BGHSt 40, p. 218 (p. 237). 156 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts planned nor explicitly ordered the offence. (11) In Japanese criminal law, we find special forms of co-perpetration which are tailored to mafia bosses («Komplott-Mittäterschaft»(12)). In English and American law, we find even a strict or vicarious liability of directors of companies for offences committed by subordinates. «Respondeat superior» is an ancient principle of military criminal law; it has now developed into the well-known command responsibility of international criminal law ( 13) . However, a normative model has problems of its own. The term «responsibility» is quite vague, and the term «normative» implies that there are norms or standards or principles which can serve as guidelines to measure responsibility. Such a principle is the principle of personal fault or culpability. Mens rea, knowledge and intention, are still key factors of responsibility. ( 14) However, knowledge and intention are not sufficient to make a person individually responsible, and the Latin saying «cogitationis nemo poena patitur» is still valid (and still a limit to conspiracy responsibilities). You also need some contribution in form of an act or an omission in breach of a legal duty. Therefore, another key factor of responsibility is the power to act in an organisation or to control it ( 15). Furthermore, the principle of proportionality limits responsibility. In particular, problems of proportionality arise in case adequate behaviour is labelled as criminal behaviour ( 16) – e.g. financial services which may constitute money laundering, financing of terrorism etc. – and if behaviour in the very pre- and post-zone of the offence is criminalized( 17) – e.g. conspiracy or complicity after fact. (11) BGHSt 40, 218; ROXIN (note 4), pp. 677 et seq. [including further references]. (12) YAMANAKA in ESER (1991), A LBIN/YAMANAKA , KEEICHI, Einflüsse deutschen Strafrechts auf Polen und Japan, p. 127 (pp. 130 et seq.). (13) TRIFFTERER in LÜDERSSEN-FS (2002), p. 437 (pp. 438 et seq.). (14) JUNG in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 175 (p. 196). (15) VOGEL (1998), Goltdammer’s Archiv für Strafrecht, p. 127 (p. 132). (16) German law: BGH Neue Zeitschrift für Strafrecht (NStZ), (2000), p. 34; BGH NStZ-Rechtsprechungs-Report 1999, p. 184 (p. 186); A MELUNG in GRÜNWALDFS, (1999), pp. 9 et seq.; HASSEMER, Wistra (1995), p. 41 et seq.; OTTO in LENCKNERFS, (1993), pp. 193 et seq.; ROXIN in Leipziger Kommentar StGB, 11th edition as of 05/1992, § 27 margin Nos. 16 et seq. (17) This has been little discussed yet but is nonetheless urgent, for example cases of financing acts of terrorism before they are committed, or laundering money after a crime is committed. In German penology the participation in the forefront of offences is limited by a demand for a specific and concret offence (LACKNER/KÜHL StGB Kommentar, § 26 margin No. 5 and § 27 margin No. 7 offers only a broad Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 157 Of course, these are vague principles. However, I do doubt whether we will be able to develop clearer, more distinct principles. For example, the German legal discussion has identified quite a lot of quite diverse principles: «Tatherrschaft» (dominion of the act); «Sonderpflichtigkeit» (special duty) ( 18); «Risikoerhöhung» (creating or increasing the risk that an offence will be committed) ( 19); «Solidarität» (solidarity with crime)(20); «Normerschütterung» (destabilization of norms) ( 21); «Autonomie» (autonomy)( 22); «Regressverbot» (rupture of imputation). It is unclear how these principles relate to each other, and also whether they are internationally applicable or restricted to German law. A possible general theory might be the so-called «Lehre von der objektiven Zurechnung» (theory of objective imputation) where risk-creation and risk-realization are central concepts which might be very useful for a normative model of participation( 23). 3. and 4. «Individual» vs. «systemic» model Traditional criminal law focuses on the individual, not on society or systems. The responsibility of society as a whole (or of parts of society) is not – or only exceptionally – taken into consideration in a criminal process. In this sense, traditional criminal law is based on an «individual» model. But such a model is certainly inadequate if we look at criminal structures and institutions and at offences committed in an organised and structured manner(24), for example organised crime in economy, public administration or politics and the so-called «Makrokriminalität» (macro crime) such as genocide and other crimes against humanity or war crimes. The German criminal law scholar Klaus Marxen(25) has shown that we need a new and «systemic» model to cope with the problems of individual overview). In German law participation far beyond the offence is only accused in special cases as « Anschlussdelikt». (18) See note 6. (19) RENZIKOWSKI (note 1), pp. 127 et seq. (Participation as endangerment). (20) SCHUMANN (1986), Strafrechtliches Handlungsunrecht und das Prinzip der Selbstverantwortung der Anderen, pp. 50-51; contrary to this Renzikowski (note 1), pp. 46-47. [including further references] (21) LESCH (1992), Das Problem der sukzessiven Beihilfe, pp. 239 et seq. (22) RENZIKOWSKI (note 1), pp. 72 et seq. (23) Again RENZIKOWSKI, (note 1), pp. 72 et seq.; furthermore LESCH (1993), Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 105, p. 271 (p. 281). (24) M ARXEN in LÜDERSSEN (ed.) (1998), Aufgeklärte Kriminalpolitik oder Kampf gegen das Böse?, vol. III, p. 220 (pp. 234-235.). (25) In LÜDERSSEN (note 24), p. 200 (pp. 231-232). 158 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts responsibility for offences committed a structured and organised environment and manner. Here, individual responsibility is generated by three elements: The first element is a specific behaviour of a person within the system, an act or an omission in breach of a duty to act. The second element is the system itself, the criminal organisation and criminal structure, the criminal group and/or the criminal program. And the third element is an offence committed somewhere in the system. The second element – the systemic context – «links» the first element, the act or omission, to the third element, the offence, regardless whether the act or omission was the proximate cause of the offence. That means: a person who knowingly and willingly contributes to the functioning of the system will be responsible for the offence even if he or she does not immediately participate in the commission of the offence, if the offence can be foreseen in the framework of the system. For example, a person who organizes concentration camps where a genocide is being committed will be individually responsible for each single killing even if he or she does not have specific knowledge about place, time and manner of specific killings. In present criminal law, we find such a reasoning in the framework of the conspiracy responsibility: a person who engages in a criminal conspiracy will individually be made responsible for offences being committed subsequently, at least if these offences could have been reasonably foreseen. Extensive forms of co-perpetration in systemic patterns are also recognized in international criminal law, e.g. in the wellknown Tadic decision of the I.C.T.Y, and in Japanese criminal law («Komplott-Mittäterschaft»)(26). Another important feature of the systemic model is the irrelevance of alternative causalities(27). In particular, it is no defence that the offence would have been committed anyway and that the perpetrator would have be probably or even certainly replaced by another person who was willing and capable to commit the offence. Even if such a reasoning is hardly compatible with the causality concept of «condicio sine qua non»( 28), it reflects a fundamental ethical principle: He who runs with the pack is responsible for what the pack will do. (26) See note 12. BGHSt 2, p. 20 (pp. 24-25). (28) PUPPE in Nomos Kommentar StGB, 5. Erg.Lief. 31.10.1998, vor § 13 margin Nos. 90 et seq. (27) Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 159 5. and 6. «Sentencing orientated» vs. «responsibility orientated» model In the first Tadic decision, the prosecution at the I.C.T.Y. cites «the modern trend to move away from very technical definitions about the degree of responsibility, and instead move us to focus on whether the action in any way incurred criminal liability … The relative degree of responsibility is a matter for sentencing»( 29). Indeed, it is the very idea of «monistic» models (in German legal terminology: (30) «Einheitstätersysteme» ) that we should not ask whether a person is liable as main perpetrator (author, pr imary party) or accomplice (instigator, aider and abettor, secondary party) but weigh the degree of participation in the sentencing process. Therefore, «monistic» models may also be called «sentencing orientated». In contrast, it is still the majority of the criminal law systems in the world which make a legal distinction between primary and secondary liability – which may be called a «responsibility orientated» model. However, a closer look reveals that these systems are indeed moving towards a «sentencing orientated» model( 31). In many legal systems, there is no difference between the penalties provided for main perpetrators on the one hand and secondary parties on the other hand. At best, legal systems provide for (mandatory or facultative) mitigation of penalties for accomplices (aiders and abettors)(32). An organizer who is technically only inciter or instigator will often be punished more severely than the persons who actually commit the offence and is technically main perpetrator. Indeed, the practical value of the distinction between primary and secondary parties may well be doubted. Often – and setting symbolic reasons aside – nothing will depend on whether the accused is instigator or accomplice by encouraging. On the other hand, a complex system of degrees of responsibility will lock up precious legal resources. In Germany, books and articles have been written about whether heads of organisations responsible for offences are «indirect» perpetrators under Art. 25 par. 1 German Criminal Code, co-perpetrators under Art. 25 par. 2 or instigators (29) ITCY Trial Chamber 1, Prosecuter v. Tadic, Case No. IT-94-1-A, Judgement of 7 May 1997 (also found in KLIP /SLUITER (ed.) (1998), Annotated Leading Cases of International Criminal Tribunals, vol. I, p. 287). (30) KIENAPFEL (1972), Der Einheitstäter im Strafrecht, p. 29, p. 32. (31) BLOY(1985), Die Beteiligungsform als Zurechnungstypus im Strafrecht, pp. 291-292; Lesch, (note 21), p. 199; contrary to this Renzikowski (note 1), pp. 35 et seq. (32) The compulsive mitigation of punishment in § 27 par. 2 sentence 2 StGB of the aide is an exception in international comparison. e.g. Art. 121-6 Code pénal. 160 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts under Art. 26 – a question of hardly any practical importance because the same penalties apply. ( 33) There is a clear and present danger that real and really important questions are neglected. For instance, a real problem is to define the «minimum threshold» of participation and responsibility, in particular in systemic contexts. Is a person who simply passes on an order to commit an offence responsible and participant? What about a person who is engaged in per se legitimate, usual business which, as a matter of fact, furthers criminality, e.g. sells certain chemical substances to a potential terrorist organisation? And which degree of authority is necessary to trigger liability in systemic contexts – is the truck driver who knowingly brings innocent victims to a concentration camp (co-) responsible for the atrocities committed there? 7. and 8. «Special part» vs. «general part» model The principle of legality («nullum crimen sine lege») requires continental criminal law systems to lay down the rules on responsibility and participation by written law. The very minimum is to declare that any participant is liable (see Art. 110 Italian Criminal Code). Due to the «lex certa »-principle, clear and restrictive definitions of the possible forms of participation are preferable. In modern criminal codes, they are laid down in the general part, they apply – in principle – to any specific offence and are spelt out in an abstract, general and not casuistic way which may be called the «general part» model. In contrast, a «special part» model provides for specific participation rules in specific offences. Historically speaking, the law on participation in the offence started from specific and casuistic rules in the special part – e.g. as annex to the murder prohibition in ancient criminal law – and developed into the abstract, general rules in the general part which are now the international standard. However, we can identify counter movements. Many «new» offences such as money-laundering, financing of terrorism, membership in a criminal organisation etc. are, as a matter of fact, nothing else than special forms of participation, in the case of money-laundering complicity after fact. (34) Recently, criminal legislators tend to mention certain forms of (33) BAUMANN/W EBER/M ITSCH (Note 1), § 28 margin No. 11. Implemented now as well in common law: HUBER in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 79 (p. 89) for the United Kingdom; N. SCHMID, Strafverfahren und Strafrecht in den Vereinigten Staaten, 2. Aufl., (1993), pp. 211-212 for the United States. (34) Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 161 participation explicitly in the text of the specific offence(35), e.g. in the field of drug trafficking offences where certain forms of aiding and abetting are explicitly mentioned so that – technically speaking – a mere aider and abettor will be perpetrator of the offence. The recent trend gives rise to interesting legal questions which are not sufficiently discussed. For instance, the problem arises whether specific rules on participation in a specific offence exclude the application of general rules of participation( 36). An example drawn from German law where it is a separate criminal offence to «aid» a receiver of stolen goods: Is it also a criminal offence to aid an aider of a receiver of stolen goods under the general rule on aiding or abetting( 37)? Another question is whether specific rules on participation in specific offences should be interpreted in accordance with the interpretation of the respective general rules. 9. «Imputation» model If each participant realizes the offence him- or herself – e.g. if a group of soldiers loots a house and each soldier steals valuable objects –, legal problems of participation and responsibility do not arise( 38). It is only when a participant does not realize all the constituent elements of the offence in person that it becomes necessary to impute to him another person’s act. Holding an officer who orders a civilian to be shot by a subordinate liable for murder, we impute the subordinate’s act to the officer. Therefore, we can say that an «imputation» model lies at the heart of any law of participation in the offence. Depending on the participants’ (35) The term «to deal» in narcotic criminal law includes inciting and aiding per se; on this problem NESTLER in KREUZER (ed.), (1998), Handbuch des Betäubungsmittelstrafrechts, § 11 margin Nos. 360 et seq.; ROXIN (note 4), pp. 618 et seq.; for polish criminal law: PLYWACZEWSKI in ESER/YAMANAKA (note 12), p. 109 (pp. 121 et seq.). (36) There are two possible antithetic answers: antecedence of the special part as lex specialis or antecedence of the general part because of their general prevalence. (37) These questions are worked on selectively: e.g. § 129 StGB, the abetting of a criminal organisation is punished autonomously; VON BUBNOFF in Leipziger Kommentar StGB, 11th edition as of 08/1995, § 129 margin Nos. 73 et seq. [including further references] (38) As an example for a normative point of view: BGHSt 18, p. 87 (p. 89) in the famous «Staschynskij-Urteil»; also BGHSt 8, p. 397 and BGH Neue Juristische Wochenschrift (1951), p. 323). discussing the importance of normative tendencies for system «Systemkriminalität» ROGALL in 50 Jahre Bundesgerichtshof, Fes tgabe aus der Wissenschaft, vol. IV (2000), p. 383 (pp. 396 et. seq.); discussing the possibility of normative interpretation: Roxin (note 1). p. 177 (pp. 188 et seq.). 162 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts position we may distinguish between «horizontal» imputation among peers and «vertical» imputation in hierarchies. (39) Paradigm of a «horizontal» imputation is co-perpetration or complicity, paradigm of a «vertical» imputation indirect or mediate perpetration by means of an innocent agent. As a rule, imputation requires fault (intention, mens rea, at least negligence) although there are exceptions, in particular in systemic contexts where a «strict» or «vicarious» liability of superiors, a «responsabilité pour fait d’autrui» is well known in various criminal law systems. However, fault is only the basis and not the object of imputation. What is imputed are acts – either acts as such or illegal or punishable acts. An imputation which starts from a illegal or punishable act done by another person results in a «derivative responsibility», in French «emprunt de criminalité », in German «Akzessorietät». It is, as a rule, the basis of secondary forms of participation such as counselling or procuring, encouraging, provocation, instruction, instigation, aiding or abetting. However, we can see in many legal systems that the principle of derivative responsibility, emprunt de criminalité or Akzessorietät is increasingly undermined(40). In theory, a derivative responsibility cannot exist if the main offender is not or only partly responsible, e.g. a child, a mentally ill person or a person acting in good faith. But exactly these situations are classical examples of «indirect» or «mediate» perpetration by means of an innocent agent. Once again, we notice that the traditional «dualistic» model moves towards a «monistic» model. 10. «Supervision» model Imputation of another person’s illegal, and criminal, behaviour can be based on activity, for instance on instigating, aiding or abetting the other person. However, many criminal law systems acknowledge an imputation based on passivity, on the failure to prevent and control offences committed by subordinates – which may be called the «supervision» model of participation. It is one of the most important instruments to determine individual responsibility in systemic contexts. In international criminal law, the «supervision» model is the basis of the so-called «command» or «superior responsibility». In many national (39) JUNG in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 175 (pp. 180 et seq.); HEINE in ESER/YAMANAKA (note 12), pp. 101 et seq. (40) Comparing tendencies in french complicité: HÜNERFELD in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 43 (pp. 47 et seq.); in english complicity: HUBER in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 79 (pp. 86 et seq.). Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 163 criminal law systems, we find comparable rules in the national military or administrative law, but increasingly also in economic criminal law where directors and managers are bound to prevent offences commited by their subordinates and otherwise are criminally or at least administratively liable if a subordinate commits an offence that would not have been committed if the superior had exercised due care – which is, under German law, an administrative offence of «Aufsichtspflichtverletzung». In a more general perspective, the «supervision» model belongs to the difficult area of participation by omission. It is an accepted principle of criminal law that omissions can be punished if there was a duty to act. So, the key question of the «supervision» model is therefore to establish a duty to prevent subordinates from committing offences and to control them. German legal doctrine has developed a quite unique theory according to which legal duties are derived from factual or social positions, the so-called «Garantenpositionen»(41), and it is highly debated whether superiors are in a position which requires them to prevent and control crime committed by subordinates. However, it is clearly impossible to derive norms from facts. Therefore, we must turn to positive law – military, administrative, economic law – in order to identify obligations to prevent and control crime. As mentioned before, these obligation do indeed exist, also with regard to subordinates who are fully responsible. The practical problems of a superior responsibility are twofold: On the one hand, prosecution must establish that the superior was in effect in power and could have prevented the offence from being committed. In order to ease the burden of proof, many legislations – among them Germany – require not more than the proof that it would have been more difficult for the subordinate to commit the offence if the superior would have exercised due care. (42) In international criminal law, it is even sufficient that the superior did not prosecute the subordinate after the offence had been committed. Here, we see again that modern criminal law replaces causal by statistical or risk relations. On the other hand, the superior’s mens rea must be proven. However, mens rea does not necessarily mean knowledge or intention. Under many national legislations, negligence may be sufficient, and there are even forms of «strict» or «vicarious» liability where not even negligence is required(43). (41) KÜHL, (note 1) § 18 margin Nos. 41 et seq. SCHÜNEMANN, wistra (1982), p. 41 (p. 45) idem Unternehmenskriminalität, pp. 206 et seq. and pp. 266 - 267. (43) JUNG in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 175 (pp. 182-183); HEINE in ESER/YAMANAKA (note 12), p. 101 (pp. 104-105). (42) 164 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 11. «Conspiracy» model The responsibility under the «imputation» or «supervision» model implies that an offence has really been committed or at least attempted. However, many criminal law systems recognize a criminal liability for conspiring to commit an offence even before (and regardless of) the commission of the offence – which can be called «conspiracy» model. It is a traditional model of criminal liability in common law countries but is also advancing in continental countries where risk management has become an idée directrice of modern societies. The traditional criminal law approach – to intervene only after an offence has been committed and after harm has been done – becomes less and less acceptable, also with a view to the extent and the quality of the harm which criminals can cause in a modern technical society. In detail, we can identify four legal techniques based on a «conspiracy» model: firstly, many legislations incriminate the conspiracy itself, i.e. the planning or plotting of an offence by at least two persons (44). Secondly, there are what has been called by German doctrine «climate offences» (Klimadelikte ), i.e. inchoate offences like attempted instigation, private oder public incitement( 45), certain forms of hate crime etc. Thirdly, many legislations make it a separate criminal offence to be member of a criminal or terrorist organisation or to support or aid a criminal or terrorist organisation. The European Union even has made such an criminal offence obligatory for the Member States(46). And fourthly, collective violent action may be punished as such regardless of results, e.g rioting in football stadiums or civil disorder ( 47). Of course, such incriminations are far-reaching. In the German discussion, several voices – many of them belonging to the so-called «Frankfurt school» around the German legal scholars Winfried Hassemer, Klaus Lüderssen and Wolfgang Naucke – have called for a «core» or «classical criminal law» which does without such incriminations of mere (44) HUBER in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 79 (p. 89) for the United Kingdom; N. SCHMID (note 34), pp. 206 et seq. for the United States. (45) HUBER in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 79 (p. 90) for the United Kingdom; N. SCHMID (note 34), pp. 205-206 for the United States. (46) Joint action of 21 December 1998 adopted by the Council on the basis of Article K.3 of the Treaty on European Union, on making it a criminal offence to participate in a criminal organisation in the Member States of the European Union – «Official Journal», L 351, 29/12/1998, pp. 1-3. (47) JUNG in ESER/HUBER/CORNILS (note 7), p. 175 (p. 185). Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 165 «risks» before actual harm has been done. But which are the alternatives? It seems clear to me that a State has the right, and also the obligation, to intervene if a terrorist organisation plans a terrorist attack. Certainly, it is possible to call such an intervention a «police» or «r isk prevention act». But such a juggling with words is not really convincing and even dangerous because the legal consequence would be that essential judicial guarantees – e.g. the right to be silent – would not apply. So I hold that the «conspiracy» model is a possible model of criminal law intervention – provided that fundamental rights and guarantees are respected. 12. «Collective responsibility» model A last attempt to cope with responsibility in complex system contexts is to make the system itself, the collective entity, the organisation responsible – which may be called «collective responsibility» model. However, collective responsibility is not an alternative to individual responsibility but an addition: There is not a single legal system known to me where punishing an individual is excluded if the collective entity is punishable or after the collective entity has been punished. Indeed, «dual» responsibility is the rule – also because most legal systems require an offence committed by an individual member of the collective entity which is imputed to the entity as such. In legal doctrine, it has often been said that collective criminal responsibility serves as substitute where individual criminal responsibility cannot be proven. At least the German experiences do not support such a suspicion. It is well known that the criminal responsibility of organisations, companies, legal persons or other collective entities is not generally accepted although more and more legislations have introduced or are introducing such a responsibility. On the other hand, practically all legal systems do intervene if members of a collective entity commit offences on its behalf or in its favour and make use of administrative measures, administrative sanctions (in particular fines like the German «Geldbuße») or civil liability for harm resulting from the offence(48). The doctrinal debate started from the fundamentalist argument that «societas non delinquere potest» because a collective responsibility would run against the very idea of criminal law, punishment and culpability. Meanwhile, it is well established that collective criminal responsibility is (48) Comparing different law systems: La criminalisation du comportement collectif. DE DOELDER/TIEDEMANN (eds.) (1996), 166 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts possible although its structures differ from the structures of individual criminal responsibility. Important concepts are: derivative or vicarious lia bility; alter-ego-model; aggregation theory; doctrine of self-identity; corporate attitude / climate. Therefore, the discussion turns to real questions: Which is the «trigger mechanism» for collective responsibility (ratione materiae, ratione personae)? Which are the sanctions, and which the criteria for sanctioning? Which is the standard of proof? Which procedural rules apply? And how do you enforce sanctions against collective entities which may change their legal status, may be bought by another entities and even dissolve themselves any time? A rich reservoir of answers can be found in the E.C. law: Collective responsibility is triggered rationae materiae by acting on behalf or in favour of the collective entity, ratione personae by persons with power to represent or to decide or to control. Sanctions are fines, but also exclusion from public subsidies or contracts, judicial supervision, dissolution. Criteria for sanctioning are gravity of the offence, proceeds from the offence, annual turnover. The requirements of responsibility must be proven beyond reasonable doubt; however, it must not be proven which person exactly committed the offence, and negligence may be proven by comparing the company with a careful company. Certain procedural guarantees tailored to natural persons – e.g. the right to be silent – do not or only partly apply to legal persons. Changes in the legal status as such do not matter. III. Final Remarks Simone Rozes and Edmondo Bruti-Liberati point out a «dilution, or broadening of the scope of classic criminal liability (…) in response to the phenomenon, often described by modern sociology, of the collectivisation of social life today». Basically, I do agree: There is indeed a change in the «classic» law of individual responsibility, of participation in the offence: «Modern» participation law is based on a «normative» rather than a «naturalistic» model, has certain «systemic» features, makes use of the «supervision» and «conspiracy» model and recognizes a collective criminal responsibility. Therefore, the scope of criminal liability is indeed «broadened». But I would not say that criminal responsibility is «diluted». Rather, it is focused in a normative – non-naturalistic – perspective on persons with power to represent, to decide and to control. I fear that those who favour a «classic» and naturalistic criminal law intend, or at least accept, that persons with power to represent, to decide and to control enjoy impunity because they – Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 167 as Simone Rozès and Edmondo Bruti-Liberati – note «are not the material authors of the facts contested in law» in a naturalistic sense. But in a normative sense, those who decide and control are material authors and should be made responsible. Bibliography A MELUNG KNUT , Die "Neutralisierung" geschäftsmäßiger Beiträge zu fremden Straftaten im Rahmen des Beihilfetatbestands, in SAMSON ERICH (ed.), Festschrift für Gerald Grünwald zum siebzigsten Geburtstag (Baden-Baden 1999), pp. 9 et seq. BAUMANN JÜRGEN, WEBER ULRICH, MITSCH W OLFGANG, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, 10. edition (Bielefeld 1995). BLOY RENÉ, Die Beteiligungsform als Zurechnungstypus im Strafrecht (Berlin 1985). DE DOELDER HANS,TIEDEMANN KLAUS, (eds.), La criminalisation du comportement collectif (The Hague et al. 1996). ESER A LBIN, HUBER BARBARA, CORNILS KARIN (eds.), Einzelverantwortung und Mitverantwortung im Strafrecht (Freiburg im Breisgau 1998). ESER A LBIN, HEINE GÜNTER, HUBER BARBARA (eds.), Criminal Responsibility of Legal and Collective Entities (Freiburg im Breisgau 1999). ESER A LBIN, YAMANAKA KEEICHI , Einflüsse deutschen Strafrechts auf Polen und Japan (Baden-Baden 2001). HASSEMER W INFRIED, "Professionelle Adäquanz. Bankentypisches Verhalten und Beihilfe zur Steuerhinterziehung", Teil I, wistra, Zeitschrift für Wirtschaft. Steuer. Strafrecht (1995), 41 et seq. JÄHNKE BURKHARD et al. (eds.), Leipziger Kommentar zum Strafgesetzbuch, 11. edition (Berlin 1992 et seq.). JAKOBS GÜNTHER, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, 2. edition (Berlin 1991). KIENAPFEL DIETHELM , Der Einheitstäter im Strafrecht (Frankfurt a.M. 1972). KLIP A NDRE et al. (eds.), Annotated leading cases of international criminal tribunals (Antwerpen 1999). KREUZER A RTHUR, (ed.), Handbuch des Betäubungsmittelstrafrechts (München 1998). KÜHL KRISTIAN, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, 3. edition (München 2000). LACKNER KARL /KÜHL KRISTIAN , Strafgesetzbuch, 24. edition (München 2001). LANGER W INRICH, Das Sonderverbrechen (Berlin 1972). LESCH HEIKO, Das Problem der sukzessiven Beihilfe (Frankfurt a.M.1992). 168 Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts LESCH HEIKO, "Die Begründung mittäterschaftlicher Haftung als Moment der objektiven Zurechnung", ZStW, Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 105 (1993), 271 et seq. LÜDERSSEN KLAUS, Zum Strafgrund der Teilnahme (Baden-Baden 1967). LÜDERSSEN KLAUS (ed.), Aufgeklärte Kriminalpolitik oder Kampf gegen das Böse?, Bd. III (Baden-Baden 1998). M URMANN UWE , Die Nebentäterschaft im Strafrecht. Ein Beitrag zu einer personalen Tatherrschaftslehre (Berlin 1993). NEUMANN ULFRIED, Nomos-Kommentar zum Strafgesetzbuch, Baden-Baden, Updated: 11. Lieferung (2002). OTTO HARRO, «Vorgeleistete Strafvereitelung» durch berufstypische oder alltägliche Verhaltensweisen als Beihilfe, in ESER A LBIN et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Theodor Lenckner zum 70. Geburtstag (München 1998), pp.194 et seq. PAUL CARSTEN, Der Begriff des Handeltreibens nach dem Betäubungsmittelgesetz, StV (Strafverteidiger 1998), 623 et seq. RANSIEK A NDREAS, Unternehmensstrafrecht (Heidelberg 1996). RENZIKOWSKI JOACHIM , Restriktiver Täterbegriff und fahrlässige Beteiligung (Tübingen 1997). ROGALL KLAUS, Bewältigung von Systemkriminalität, in WIDMAIER GUNTER, ROXIN CLAUS (eds.), 50 Jahre Bundesgerichtshof, Festgabe aus der Wissenschaft, Bd. IV (Heidelberg 2000 ). ROXIN CLAUS, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, 3. edition (München 1997). ROXIN CLAUS, Täterschaft und Tatherrschaft, 7. edition (Berlin 2000). SCHMID NIKLAUS, Strafverfahren und Strafrecht in den Vereinigten Staaten, 2. edition (Heidelberg 1993). SCHÖNKE ADOLF/ SCHRÖDER HORST , Strafgesetzbuch. Kommentar, 26. edition (München 2001). SCHMIDT -SALZER JOACHIM, Massenproduktion, lean production und Arbeitsteilung - organisationssoziologisch und -rechtlich betrachtet. Haftungs- und Strafrecht als Mittel zur Konkretisierung und Verdeutlichung der Organisation von Unternehmen und Unternehmensgruppen, BB (Betriebsberater 1992), 1866 et seq. SCHUMANN HERIBERT , Strafrechtliches Handlungsunrecht und das Prinzip der Selbstverantwortung der Anderen (Tübingen 1986). SCHÜNEMANN BERND, "Strafrechtsdogmatische und kriminalpolitische Grundfragen der Unternehmenskriminalität", wistra, Zeitschrift für Wirtschaft. Steuer. Strafrecht (1982), 41 et seq. STEIN, ULRICH, Die strafrechtliche Beteiligungsformenlehre (Berlin 1988). TRIFFTERER OTTO (ed.), Commentary on the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (Baden-Baden 1999). TRIFFTERER OTTO, «Command responsibility« Grundstrukturen und Anwendungsbereiche von Art. 28 des Rom-Statutes; Eignung auch zur Bekämpfung des internationalen Terrorismus?, in PRITTWITZ, CORNELIUS et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Klaus Lüderssen (Baden-Baden 2002). Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts 169 VAN DER WYNGAERT CHRISTINE (ed.), International Criminal Law: A Collection of International and European Instruments, 2. rev. edition (The Hague 2000). VOGEL JOACHIM, "Individuelle Verantwortlichkeit im Völkerstrafrecht. Zugleich ein Beitrag zu den Regelungsmodellen der Beteiligung", ZStW, Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 114 (2002), 403 et seq. VOGEL JOACHIM , Elemente der Straftat, GA (Goltdammer’s Archiv) (1998), 127 et seq. A CARTA DOS DIREITOS FUNDAMENTAIS DA UNIÃO EUROPEIA E A PROTECÇÃO DOS DIREITOS FUNDAMENTAIS RUI MANUEL MOURA RAMOS Professor da Faculdade de Direito da Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal Membro do Istituto de Direito Internacional Juiz o Tribunal de Primiera Instância das Comunidades Europeais 1. A recente proclamação, pelo Parlamento Europeu, o Conselho da União Europeia e a Comissão Europeia, por ocasião do Conselho Europeu de Nice(1), de uma Carta dos Direitos Fundamentais da União Europeia (2), à qual foi por enquanto negada a inserção na lei fundamental da Comunidade e da União(3), oferece naturalmente o ensejo de repensar a problemática da protecção dos direitos fundamentais no interior do sistema jurídico criado por estas organizações. Procuraremos, no presente estudo, de forma necessariamente sumária, abordar alguns dos aspectos que esta questão suscita. Para tanto, e após recordar brevemente as razões que, no plano interno como no internacional, impuseram que a este tema fosse reconhecido, na segunda metade do último século, direitos de cidade, referiremos a evolução que a problemática em apreço sofreu no sistema comunitário e a especificidade de que ela se reveste no seu seio, para concluir com uma breve avaliação da Carta e do lugar por ela ocupado no aprofundamento do ordenamento em que se passa a inserir. 2. Constitui praticamente um truísmo recordar que a consciência da necessidade de inventariar os direitos humanos fundamentais e para eles instituir mecanismos de protecção se afirma sobretudo após o final do segundo conflito mundial que marcou o século que há pouco finda. A circunstância de durante e após o termo das hostilidades se ter tornado claro (1) (2) A 7 de Dezembro de 2000. Para o respectivo texto, cfr. o “Jornal Oficial das Comunidades Europeias”, C, 364, de 18 de Dezembro de 2000, pp. 1-22. (3) A revisão destes textos a que procede o Tratado de Nice não afecta, na verdade, as disposições que se referem à protecção dos direitos fundamentais, designadamente o actual artigo 6.E do Tratado da União Europeia. Apenas se modificam os termos pelos quais o Conselho pode agir nos casos de risco claro de violação grave destes direitos por um Estado-Membro. Veja-se, a este propósito, o novo texto do artigo 7.E deste Tratado. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 172 o grau de violação desses direitos em alguns dos países beligerantes viria assim a estar na origem do desenvolvimento que os textos constitucionais do pós-guerra europeu, maxime em Itália e na Alemanha, deram a esta questão, que atingiria um nível até então desconhecido e que se não pode dissociar da experiência acabada de viver. Mas a história do direito constitucional comparado revela -nos também que se não tratou de uma moda ou de algo de passageiro, podendo ao contrário dizer-se que esta tendência para a consagração da protecção constitucional dos direitos humanos se afirmou como um dado estrutural da evolução jurídica recente. Tenha-se presente, a este propósito, o que se passou com os textos constitucionais que, no dobrar do terceiro quartel do último século, marcariam a transição dos países ibéricos para sistemas de democracia representativa e pluralista ( 4), assim como a de vários Estados latino-americanos (5), na década seguinte, e, um pouco mais tarde, a da generalidade dos Estados leste-europeus. Antecedendo este desenvolvimento, contudo, ou contemporâneo dele, um outro se faria no entanto sentir, buscando fundar na ordem internacional a protecção dos direitos humanos. Trata-se de um mecanismo complementar do anterior que, começando por partir da possível insuficiência deste, uma vez que a protecção que ele garante ficaria sempre dependente da consagração constitucional que aqueles direitos poderiam lograr em cada ordem jurídica estadual, sublinha em particular o universalismo que caracteriza esta problemática(6). Na verdade, é a (4) No que respeita a Portugal, e com referência à Constituição de 1976, vejam-se sobretudo, Vieira de Andrade (1983), Os direitos fundamentais na Constituição Portuguesa de 1976, Coimbra, Livraria Almedina; Gomes Canotilho (1999), Direito Constitucional e Teoria da Constituição, 3.a edição, Coimbra, Livraria Almedina, pp. 349-496, e Jorge Miranda, (1998), Manual de Direito Constitucional, t. IV Direitos Fundamentais, Coimbra, Coimbra Editora. (5) Em particular sobre a experiência brasileira, vide PIOVESAN FLAVIA, (2000), Direitos Humanos e o Direito Constitucional Internacional, 4.a edição, São Paulo, Max Limonad, pp. 47-63. (6) Para uma ilustração desta asserção, cfr. o conjunto de estudos inseridos em Les dimensions universelles des droits de l'homme (sob a direcção de A. Lepeyre, F. De Tinguy e K. Vasak), v. I, Bruxelas, (1990), Bruylant. Sublinhando igualmente que os direitos do homem se não confundem com as garantias constitucionais ou com os direitos da cidadania democrática e que constituem uma classe particular de direitos cuja aplicação é universal e cuja generalidade é incontroversa, cfr. ainda John Rawls (Le droit des gens, Paris, Editions Esprit, 1998, p. 93) que precisa que eles fazem parte de um direito razoável dos povos e especificam os limites que vinculam as instituições internas e que se impõem a todas as comunidades A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 173 circunstância de o fundamento dessa protecção radicar afinal em valores que se têm por universais e perenes, essenciais à convivência humana e social( 7), que justifica que a ordem internacional por ela se venha igualmente a responsabilizar e que os Estados que incorram na sua violação possam ser alvo da condenação de instâncias internacionais. Dando corpo a esta ideia, a Convenção Europeia para a Protecção dos Direitos do Homem e das Liberdades Fundamentais ( 8), concluída em 4 humanas, especificando «o limite exterior do direito interno das sociedades admissível para os membros respeitáveis de uma justa sociedade dos povos». (7) Sobre este fundamento, cfr. Celso Lafer, (1988), A Reconstrução dos Direitos Humanos. Um diálogo com o Pensamento de Hannah Arendt, São Paulo, Companhia das Letras, os trabalhos reunidos em Los fundamentos filosoficos de los derechos humanos, Paris, (1985); Unesco-Serbal e em, (1994), Diritti Umani, Oxford Amnesty Lectures (edited by Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley), Garzanti; e José Manuel Pureza, (1989), «Os direitos do homem na comunidade planetária: auto-referência ou harmonia espacial?» in Estado e Direito, No. E 4, pp. 17-31. E para as suas raízes, cfr. os textos coligidos emDroits de l'homme et philosophie. Une anthologie (1789-1914), Paris, Presses Pocket (1993). (8) Cfr. para uma análise deste texto, dos protocolos adicionais que o modificariam e desenvolveriam, assim como da jurisprudência do Tribunal, Convention européenne des droits de l'homme, Recueil de textes, Strasbourg, (1994), Les éditions du Conseil de l'Europe; Les droits de l'homme à l'aube du XXIe siècle, (1993), Strasbourg, Les éditions du Conseil de l'Europe; Francis G. Jacobs, (1975), The European Convention on Human Rights, Oxford, Clarendon Press; Gérard CohenJonathan, (1989), La Convention européenne des droits de l'homme, Paris, Economica; Jacques Velu, Rusen Ergec, (1990), La Convention européenne des droits de l'homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant; Fausto de Quadros, «La Convention européenne des droits de l'homme: un cas de ius cogens régional», in Recht zwischen Umbruch und Bewahrung, Festschrift für Rudolf Bernhardt, (1995), Berlin, Springer Verlag, pp. 555-562; Frederic Sudre, (1990), La Convention européenne des droits de l'homme, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France; Dimitrios Evrigenis, (1978), «Le rôle de la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme», in New Perspectives for a Common Law of Europe (sous la direction de Marco Cappelletti), Bruxelas, Bruylant, pp. 341-357, e Donna Gomien, Vademecum de la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme, Strasbourg, (1991), Les éditions du Conseil de l'Europe, e, em língua portuguesa, Maria Luísa Duarte, (1989), «O Conselho da Europa e a protecção dos direitos do homem», in Documentação e Direito Comparado, n.E 39/40, pp. 191-242; Pinheiro Farinha, (1980), Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem. Anotada, Lisboa; José Alfredo de Oliveira Baracho, (1998), «A prática jurídica no domínio da protecção internacional dos direitos do homem (a Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem)», in Liber Amicorum Hector Fix-Zamudio, São José, Costa Rica, Secretaria de la Corte Interamericana de Derechos Humanos, pp. 375-413, e Ireneu Cabral Barreto, (1999), A Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem. Anotada, 2.a edição, Coimbra, Coimbra Editora. Para a posição deste instrumento nas ordens jurídicas nacionais, vide Dimitrios 174 A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia de Novembro de 1950, em Roma, no seio do Conselho da Europa, viria a estabelecer um conjunto de direitos que os Estados que a ela se vinculassem deveriam reconhecer a todas as pessoas dependentes da sua jurisdição (artigos 2.E a 18.E), prevendo igualmente a criação de um tribunal permanente (o Tribunal Europeu dos Direitos do Homem) que asseguraria o respeito, por parte daqueles, dos compromissos assim assumidos (artigos 19.E a 51.E). E o mesmo caminho seria posteriormente seguido no âmbito do universo jurídico latino-americano pela Convenção Americana sobre Direitos Humanos assinada em 22 de Novembro de 1969 em São José da Costa Rica(9). De modo não inteiramente idêntico, as Nações Unidas dariam também corpo a um outro sistema de protecção internacional de direitos humanos que, assentando igualmente num catálogo de direitos cujo reconhecimento é imposto aos Estados partes nos instrumentos internacionais que o integram( 10), vê o controlo da respectiva Evrigenis, «L'interaction entre la dimension internationale et la dimension nationale de la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme: notions autonomes et effet direct», in Volkerrecht als Rechtsordnung. Internationale Gerichtsbarkeit. Menschenrechte. Festschrift für Hermann Mosler, Berlin, Springer Verlag, (1983), pp. 193-202 e, entre nós, Moura Ramos, (1996), «A Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do homem. Sua posição face ao ordenamento jurídico português», in Da Comunidade Internacional e do seu Direito. Estudos de Direito Internacional Público e de Relações Internacionais, Coimbra, Coimbra Editora, pp. 5-108, . E para a caracterização do sistema por ele instituído vide, por último, Richard S. Kay, (2000), «The European Human Rights System as a System of Law», 6 The Columbia Journal of European Law, pp. 55-71. (9) E no do africano, ainda que com características diferentes, com a Carta Africana dos Direitos do Homem e dos Povos, adoptada em Junho de 1981 em Nairobi, pela Conferência de chefes de Estado e de Governo da Organização da Unidade Africana. Sob este sistema, em particular, cfr. Philip Kunig, Wolfgang Benedek, Costa R. Mahalu, (1985), Regional Protection of Human Rights by International Law: The Emerging African System, Baden-Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft e Maria José Morais Pires, (1999), «Carta Africana dos Direitos Humanos e dos Povos», in Documentação e Direito Comparado, v. 79/80, pp. 333-350. (10) Constituído pelo Pacto Internacional relativo aos direitos económicos, sociais e culturais e pelo Pacto Internacional relativo aos direitos civis e políticos, adoptados pela Assembleia Geral das Nações Unidas a 16 de Dezembro de 1966 e que desenvolvem, dotando-os de uma garantia jurídica, os direitos que a Declaração Universal dos Direitos do Homem, proclamada a 10 de Dezembro de 1948, consagrava como simples directiva moral. Sobre este sistema, cfr. The United Nations and Human Rights, New York, (1984), United Nations; Jaime Oraá, Felipe Gomez Isa, (1997), La Declaracíon Universal de los Derechos Humanos. Un breve comentario en su 50 Aniversario, Bilbao, Universidad de Deusto, e Alberto de Amaral Junior e Claudia A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 175 observância por estes últimos assentar na discussão e análise, pelo Comité de Direitos Humanos ( 11 , de relatórios estaduais descrevendo as medidas adoptadas no plano nacional para a efectivação daqueles direitos ( 12). 3. A constituição de entidades fruto do desenvolvimento do fenómeno de integração regional introduziria no entanto algumas novidades ao funcionamento do sistema acabado de evocar. Na verdade, como sucedeu com a instituição das Comunidades Europeias, os EstadosMembros aceitaram a limitação de alguns dos seus poderes, passando as respectivas competências a ser exercidas pelos órgãos das novas instituições por eles criadas. Nessas circunstâncias, a admitir-se que estas estariam livres da vinculação aos mecanismos de protecção internacional que os Estados haviam constituído, a sua criação envolveria um retrocesso, Perrone-Moises (orgs.), (1999), O Cinquentenário da Declaração Universal dos Direitos do Homem, São Paulo, Editora da Universidade de São Paulo. (11) Instituído pelo Pacto Internacional dos Direitos Civis e Políticos, referido na nota anterior. (12) Para uma recolha de textos de direito internacional sobre direitos do homem, cfr. Droits de l'homme en droit international, Strasbourg, 1992, Les éditions du Conseil de l'Europe, Droits de l'homme. Recueil de documents internationaux et nationaux, Bruxelles, Bruylant, (1989); e, em língua portuguesa, Jorge Campinos, (1984), Direito Internacional dos Direitos do Homem. Textos Básicos, Coimbra, Coimbra Editora. E para um comentário à sua origem e desenvolvimento, Karel Vasak, (1983), As dimensões internacionais dos direitos humanos, Lisboa, Unesco, Manuais LTC;Thomas Buergenthal, (1988), International Human Rights in a Nutshell, St. Paul, Minn., West Publishing Co; Frédéric Sudre, (1995), Droit international et européen des droits de l'homme, 2.a edição, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France; AAVV, (1998), La protection des droits de l'homme et l'évolution du droit international, Paris, Editions A. Pedone, AAVV, (1999), Los derechos humanos en un mundo dividido, Bilbao, Universidad de Deusto; AAVV, (1999), Os direitos humanos e o direito internacional (org. Carlos Eduardo de Abreu Boucault e Nadia de Araújo), São Paulo, Renovar; Rui Machete, (1978), Os Direitos do Homem no Mundo, Lisboa, Fundação Social Democrata Oliveira Martins; e Juan Antonio Carrillo Salcedo, (1995), Soberania de los Estados e Derechos Humanos en Derecho Internacional Contemporaneo, Madrid, Tecnos. Em especial sobre os direitos culturais, cfr. AAVV, (1970), Os direitos culturais como direitos do homem, Unesco, Porto, 1973, Livraria Telos Editora. E sobre os meios da sua efectivação, cfr. a resolução do Institut de droit international, na sua Sessão de Santiago de Compostela de 1989 e o comentário de Christian Dominicé, «La contrainte entre Etats à l'appui des droits de l'homme», in Hacia un nuevo orden internacional y europeo. Estudios en homenaje al Profesor Don Manuel Diez de Velasco, Madrid, Editorial Tecnos, (1993), pp. 261-272. Colocando a tónica nas instituições internacionais de protecção dos direitos do homem veja-se o panorama apresentado em The Reform of International Institutions for the Protection of Human Rights, Bruxelles, Bruylant(1993). A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 176 no que à tutela dos direitos humanos diz respeito. A menos que se entendesse que elas sucederiam aos Estados-Membros partes nos instrumentos que haviam presidido à sua criação quando exercessem as competências de cujo exercício os Estados haviam sido privados e que, a sê-lo por estes, estariam na origem do funcionamento do referido mecanismo de protecção. Acresce que o risco que se acaba de relevar era de algum modo reforçado pela circunstância de os tratados institutivos, num silêncio que se prolongaria durante bastante tempo, não fazerem qualquer referência à problemática da protecção dos direitos humanos ) e isto apesar de às instituições por eles criadas terem sido devolvidos poderes cujo exercício poderia sem sombra de dúvidas desencadear a respectiva violação(13). E não se esqueça que, num período inicial, o Tribunal de Justiça, quando chamado a pronunciar-se sobre a compatibilidade de disposições comunitárias com as normas constitucionais dos Estados-Membros relativas à protecção dos direitos fundamentais, se limitava a afirmar só ter «que garantir o respeito do Tratado e dos regulamentos de execução, não devendo regra geral pronunciar-se sobre as normas de direito interno», e não podendo, em consequência «examinar o argumento segundo o qual, ao adoptar a sua decisão, a Alta Autoridade violou princípios do direito constitucional alemão»( 14). A instância jurisdicional comunitária negligenciava assim, de alguma forma, a questão da protecção dos direitos fundamentais, ao não indagar se os direitos fundamentais invocados pelo requerente não deveriam ser considerados como existentes na própria ordem jurídica comunitária, por a respectiva consagração resultar afinal de princípios constitucionais comuns aos Estados-Membros (15). (13) Estamos a pensar em disposições que se refiram à questão em geral, não querendo com isto esquecer que divers as regras específicas se inspiraram nos valores que tinham estado na base da consagração dos sistemas de protecção dos direitos humanos. Assim, o artigo 7.E e as demais cláusulas de não discriminação entre os nacionais dos Estados-Membros (artigos 40.E, 48.E, 52.E e 60.E) e o artigo 119.E, que se referia à igualdade entre homens e mulheres, em matéria de remuneração (referimo nos à numeração inicial destes artigos). (14) Acórdão de 4 de Fevereiro de 1959, Storck/Alta Autoridade, processo 1/58, Colectânea da Jurisprudência do Tribunal, 1954-1961, pp. 293-306, ponto 4, alínea a). (15) Recorde-se que o Tribunal havia já considerado que os princípios de direito comuns aos Estados-Membros constituíam uma fonte complementar de direito comunitário, ao afirmar que, na inexistência de disposições do Tratado sobre determinada questão, o Tribunal, «para evitar uma denegação de justiça, se encontrava obrigado a decidir inspirando-se das regras reconhecidas pelas legislações, a doutrina e a jurisprudência dos Estados-Membros (acórdão de 12 de Julho de 1957, Dineke Algera A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 177 Posteriormente a esta tomada de posição, o défice de protecção comunitária dos direitos fundamentais seria sublinhado, no plano nacional, pelo acórdão do Bundesverfassungsgericht de 29 de Maio de 1974( 16) que sublinharia que esta instância não podia deixar de controlar a compatibilidade do direito comunitário derivado com os direitos fundamentais enquanto não existisse, por falta de um catálogo de direitos fundamentais no sistema comunitário, uma garantia suficiente quanto à protecção de tais direitos nesta ordem jurídica. Face à necessidade de evitar as consequências que tomadas de posição como esta poderiam vir a ter sobre o acatamento dos princípios da aplicabilidade directa e do primado do direito comunitário, por si entretanto formulados ( 17), o Tribunal de Justiça chamaria a si, com o acórdão Stauder(18), o papel de garante dos direitos fundamentais. Nesta de cisão, e ao apreciar uma disposição cuja conformidade com os princípios gerais do direito comunitário constituía o objecto da questão prejudicial formulada pelo juiz nacional, o Tribunal acrescentaria num obiter dictum que a interpretação que para ela preconizava não revelava «qualquer elemento susceptível de colocar em causa os direitos fundamentais individuais compreendidos nos princípios gerais do direito comunitário, cuja observância é assegurada pelo Tribunal»(19). A inserção da garantia da protecção dos direitos fundamentais nos poderes de cognição da jurisdição comunitária seria pouco depois precisada e o./ Assembleia Comum da CECA, processos apensos n.Es 7-56 e 3-57 a 7-57, Colectânea, cit., 1954-1961, p. 158, e, para a publicação integral do acórdão, Recueil de jurisprudence de la Cour, v. III (1957), pp. 81-178 (114-115). Maria Luísa Duarte, (2000), A União Europeia e os Direitos Fundamentais, Métodos de Protecção, in Estudos de Direito da União e das Comunidades Europeias, Coimbra, Coimbra Editora, pp. 11-35; qualifica de agnosticismo valorativo a postura do Tribunal referida em texto. (16) Veja-se o v. 37 da Colectânea das decisões do Bundesverfassungsgericht, p. 271-291. Este acórdão fora precedido de outros da mesma instância jurisdicional alemã, na sequência de uma primeira decisão no mesmo sentido de 18 de Outubro de 1967; cfr. a mesma Colectânea, no v. 22, pp. 293-299. (17) Cfr., respectivamente, os acórdãos de 5 de Fevereiro de 1963, Gend & Loos/Administração Fiscal, processo 26/62, Colectânea, 1962-1964, pp. 205-232, e de 15 de Julho de 1964, Flaminio Costa/ENEL, processo 6/64, Colectânea, 1962-1964, pp. 549-577. (18) Acórdão de 12 de Novembro de 1969, processo 29/69, Colectânea, 19691970, pp. 157-166. Esta decisão inaugura aquela a que Maria Luísa Duarte (op. cit. supra, nota 15) chama de fase de reconhecimento activo dos direitos fundamentais (p. 20). (19) Sublinhado nosso. Cfr. o ponto 7 da decisão citada na nota anterior, a p. 160. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 178 com particular destaque no acórdão Internationale Handelsgesellschaft(20), onde o Tribunal procederia à compatibilização das suas afirmações anteriores desenvolvendo ademais o papel reconhecido aos direitos fundamentais no ordenamento comunitário». Pronunciando-se expressamente sobre a protecção dos direitos fundamentais nesta ordem jurídica(21), começaria por recordar a jurisprudência mais antiga nos termos da qual «o recurso às regras ou noções jurídicas do direito nacional, para a apreciação dos actos adoptados pelas instituições da comunidade, teria por efeito pôr em causa a unidade e a eficácia do direito comunitário». E sublinharia que «ao direito emergente do Tratado, emanado de uma fonte autónoma, não podem, em virtude da sua natureza, ser opostas em juízo regras de direito nacional, quaisquer que sejam, sob pena de perder o seu carácter comunitário e de ser posta em causa a base jurídica da própria Comunidade; portanto, a invocação de violações, quer aos direitos fundamentais, tais como estes são enunciados na Constituição de um Estado-Membro, quer aos princípios da estrutura constitucional nacional, não pode afectar a validade de um acto da Comunidade ou o seu efeito no território desse Estado». Para acrescentar em seguida, aprofundando as considerações já afloradas no acórdão Stauder: «Convém, no entanto, analisar se não terá sido violada qualquer garantia análoga, inerente ao direito comunitário. Com efeito, o respeito dos direitos fundamentais faz parte integrante dos princípios gerais de direito cuja observância é assegurada pelo Tribunal de Justiça. A salvaguarda desses direitos, ainda que inspirada nas tradições constitucionais comuns aos Estados-Membros, deve ser assegurada no âmbito da estrutura e dos objectivos da Comunidade». Ficava assim assente a competência jurisdicional para a protecção dos direitos fundamentais, mediante a inserção destes nos princípios gerais de direito cuja observância o Tribunal deve garantir. E estes princípios viam a sua formulação decorrer da utilização do método comparativo, que sublinhava o recurso à tradição constitucional dos Estados-Membros, em lugar da abstracta referência do acórdão Stauder aos princípios gerais de direito comunitário ( 22). (20) Acórdão de 17 de Dezembro de 1970, no processo 11/70, Colectânea, 19691970, pp. 625-657. (21) Pontos 3 e 4 da decisão citada na nota anterior, a p. 628-629. (22) Acentuando esta precisão, cfr. Antonio Saggio, (1993), «A protecção dos direitos fundamentais na ordem jurídica comunitária», in O Sistema Jurisdicional Comunitário e a sua contribuição para a integração europeia, Lisboa, pp. 69-97, p. 74. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 179 Posteriormente, no acórdão Nold/Comissão(23), ao ser confrontado com a alegação de que certas disposições comunitárias, além de contrariarem disposições constitucionais alemãs, violavam ainda «diversos instrumentos internacionais, nomeadamente a Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem», o Tribunal alargaria o quadro de parâmetros de identificação dos direitos fundamentais, ao acrescentar à ideia de que se deveria inspirar, ao garantir a protecção dos direitos fundamentais, nas tradições constitucionais dos Estados-Membros ( 24), o reconhecimento de que «os instrumentos internacionais relativos à protecção dos direitos do homem, em que os Estados-Membros colaboraram ou a que aderiram, podem igualmente dar indicações que é conveniente tomar em consideração no âmbito do direito comunitário». Esta linha de rumo viria a ser concretizada em seguida no acórdão Rutili/Ministro do Interior (25)em que o Tribunal, instado a esclarecer quando é que as limitações ao direito de livre circulação e permanência dos cidadãos de outros Estados-Membros se poderiam considerar justificadas, para os efeitos do artigo 48.E, n.E 3 (hoje artigo 39.E, n.E 3), invocaria determinadas normas da Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem( 26) para acentuar que as limitações introduzidas aos poderes dos EstadosMembros em matéria de polícia dos estrangeiros (27) seriam expressão de um princípio mais geral consagrado naquelas disposições que igualmente dispõem que as ofensas aos direitos por elas garantidos, «em virtude das necessidades de ordem e segurança públicas, não poderão ultrapassar o âmbito do que é necessário para protecção daquelas necessidades ‘numa sociedade democrática’»(28). 4. Assumindo este desenvolvimento jurisdicional, as instituições comunitárias em breve confirmariam no plano político o caminho assim trilhado. Na verdade, por uma Declaração Comum de 5 de Abril de (23) Acórdão de 14 de Maio de 1974, no processo 4/73, Colectânea, 1974, pp. 283-300, especialmente ponto 13. (24) O que teria a consequência de que não poderia «admitir medidas incompatíveis com os direitos fundamentais reconhecidos e garantidos pelas constituições destes Estados». (25) De 28 de Novembro de 1975, no processo 36/75, Colectânea, 1975, pp. 415436. (26) Os artigos 8.E, 9.E, 10.E e 11.E, assim como o artigo 2.E do Protocolo n.E 4, de 16 de Setembro de 1963. (27) Pelo artigo 3.E da Directiva 64/221 e o artigo 8.E do Regulamento n.E 1612/68. (28) Ponto 32 do acórdão citado supra , na nota 25. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 180 1977( 29), o Parlamento europeu, o Conselho e a Comissão vieram sublinhar «a importância fundamental que reconhecem aos direitos fundamentais tais como resultam nomeadamente das Constituições dos Estados-Membros bem como da Convenção Europeia de Salvaguarda dos Direitos do Homem e das Liberdades Fundamentais», acrescentando que «no exercício da sua missão e no prosseguimento dos objectivos das Comunidades Europeias, respeitam e continuarão a respeitar esses direitos». Após as instituições seriam os chefes de governo dos EstadosMembros a reafirmar a mesma linha, ao subscreverem, a 7 e 8 de Abril de 1978, a Declaração sobre a Democracia, onde, para além de se afirmar «que a aplicação dos princípios da democracia representativa, do primado da lei, da justiça social e do respeito pelos direitos do homem implicava um regime político que garantisse as modalidades processuais necessárias ao respeito dos direitos do homem», se acrescentava que «a manutenção da democracia e a defesa dos direitos do homem constituíam elementos consubstanciais da Comunidade Europeia». Estas tomadas de posição só poderiam reforçar a corrente jurisprudencial acima referida, que passaria a fundar a referência à protecção dos direitos fundamentais, de forma sistemática, nas tradições constitucionais nacionais e nos instrumentos de direito internacional pactício, com particular referência à Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem. Exemplo do que afirmamos é o acórdão Lisalotte Hauer/Land Rheinland Pfalz(30) onde, referindo-se ao acórdão Internationale Handelsgesellschaft, o Tribunal sublinharia que «a questão de uma violação eventual dos direitos fundamentais por um acto institucional das Comunidades apenas pode ser apreciada no quadro do próprio direito comunitário» (ponto 14). Para continuar, na esteira do acórdão Nold, referindo que «os direitos fundamentais fazem parte integrante dos princípios gerais de direito cujo respeito lhe cabe assegurar», e que, ao fazê-lo, «está obrigado a inspirar-se nas tradições constitucionais comuns aos Estados-Membros, de tal modo que se não poderiam admitir na Comunidade medidas incompatíveis com os direitos fundamentais reconhecidos pelas Constituições destes Estados; e que os instrumentos internacionais relativos à protecção dos direitos do homem, nos quais os Estados-Membros cooperaram ou a que aderiram, podem igualmente (29) Vide Jornal Oficial das Comunidades Europeias, 1997, C, 103, p. 1. Acórdão de 13 de Dezembro de 1979, no processo 44/79, Recueil, 1979, v. III, pp. 3727-3765. Sobre esta decisão, cfr. Simona Bellini, (1981), «La tutela dei diritti fondamentali nell'ordinamento comunitario secondo la sentenza Hauer», Rivista di Diritto Internazionale, 64, pp. 318-327. (30) A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 181 fornecer indicações que há que ter em conta no quadro do direito comunitário». Para concluir recordando que esta concepção havia sido igualmente reconhecida pela citada Declaração comum das instituições, de 5 de Abril de 1977, que, «após ter recordado a jurisprudência do Tribunal, se referia, por um lado, aos direitos garantidos pelas Constituições dos Estados-Membros e, por outro, à Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem» (ponto 15). 5. Pode dizer-se que a partir desta altura a vinculação das Comunidades à garantia dos direitos fundamentais não deixaria de ser uma constante da jurisprudência do Tribunal de Justiça. Simplesmente, na ausência de textos claros no direito primário que consagrassem com carácter geral esta obrigação, ela apresentava -se assim como uma corrente de natureza pretoriana, que procurava suprir a falta de um catálogo preciso de direitos fundamentais recorrendo às tradições constitucionais nacionais e, de forma crescente, à Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem. A importância deste texto como parâmetro da interpretação do sistema de direitos fundamentais reconhecidos no sistema comunitário seria evidenciada pela jurisprudência posterior ( 31) e levaria inclusivamente a (31) Para mais extensas indicações neste sentido, cfr. Manfred Dauses, (1990), «La protection des droits fondamentaux dans l'ordre juridique des Communautés Européennes. Position du problème, état actuel et tendances», in Documentação e Direito Comparado, 41-42 pp. 9-35; Antonio Saggio, «O sistema jurisdicional comunitário e a sua contribuição para a integração europeia», cit. supra , nota 22, Angel Chueca Sancho, (1989), Los derechos fundamentales en la Comunidad Europea, Barcelona, Bosch, pp. 147-321; Andrew Clapham, (1991), Human Rights and the European Community: A Critical Overview, Baden-Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, especialmente pp. 29-89; F. G. Jacobs, 1992, «The protection of human rights in the member States of the European Community. The impact of the case-law of the Court of Justice», in Human Rights and Constitutional Law. Essays in honour of Brian Walsh (edited by James O'Reilly), Dublin, The round hall press, pp. 243-250; Konstantinos Kakouris, «La jurisprudence de la Cour de justice des Communautées européennes relative aux droits de l'homme. Aperçu général», in Julia Iliopoulos, Strangas (hrsg.), (1993), La protection des droits de l'homme dans le cadre européen. L'adhésion des Communautés Européennes à la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme , Baden-Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, pp. 183-207; Federico Mancini, Vittorio di Bucci, «Die Entwicklung der Grundrechte als Teil des Gemeinschaftsrechts», ibidem, pp. 208-230; Cástor M. Diaz Barrado, (1995), «Reconocimiento y protección de los derechos fondamentales en la Union Europea», in Derecho de extranjeria, Asilo y Refugio, Madrid, Instituto Nacional de Servicios Sociales, pp. 127-153; Gil Carlos Rodríguez Iglesias, (1998), «La proteccíon de los derechos fundamentales en la Union Europea», in Scritti in onore di Giuseppe Federico Mancini, v. II-Diritto dell'Unione Europea, Milano, Giuffrè, pp. 831-845; Montserrat Pi Llorens, (1999), Los derechos fondamentales en lo ordenamiento 182 A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia Comissão a apresentar em 4 de Abril de 1979( 32) um Memorandum sobre a adesão das Comunidades à Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem. Se as diferentes dificuldades postas por uma tal démarche (e que seriam, de resto, elencadas neste documento) (33) estariam necessariamente na origem de um arrastar da reflexão sobre o tema, o certo é que a ideia de dotar a Comunidade de um catálogo de direitos fundamenta is não seria abandonada. É assim que o Projecto de Tratado da União Europeia, aprovado pelo Parlamento Europeu em 14 de Fevereiro de 1984, conteria um artigo 4.E que retomava o compromisso das Comunidades com a protecção dos direitos fundamentais, nos termos da jurisprudência já referida, nela incluindo também os direitos económicos, sociais e culturais ( 34), previa a possibilidade de sanções aos Estados que séria e persistentemente os violassem e anunciava, num prazo de cinco anos, uma decisão sobre a adesão à Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem e à Carta Social Europeia assim como a adopção de uma declaração comunitária sobre os direitos fundamentais ( 35). E se os Estados não viriam a adoptar esta via (nem a dar seguimento ao projecto de Tratado), o certo é que não deixariam de reafirmar, no preâmbulo do Acto Único Europeu assinado em 17 de Fevereiro de 1986, a sua decisão de promover conjuntamente a democracia «com base nos direitos fundamentais reconhecidos nas Constituições e legislações dos Estados-Membros, na Convenção da Protecção dos Direitos comunitario, Barcelona; Ariel e Koen Lenaerts, (2000), «Fundamental rights in the European Union», 25 European Law Review pp. 575-600 (577-585). (32) Na esteira de uma posição anterior do Parlamento Europeu que em 10 de Julho de 1975 aprovaria uma Resolução sobre a União Europeia em que reclamava a elaboração de uma carta dos direitos dos cidadãos da Comunidade com o objectivo de dar aos cidadãos da Comunidade o sentimento da sua comunidade de destino. (33) Para a sua análise, cfr., entre outros, Angel Chueca Sancho, Los derechos fundamentales en la Comunidad Europea, cit. supra, nota 31, pp. 327-353, e Rudolf Bernhardt, (1996), «Probleme eines Beitritts der Europaischen Gemeinschaft zur Europaischen Menschenrechts Konvention, in Festschrift für Ulrich Everling (Ole Due, Marcus Lutter, Jurgen Schwarze, hrsg), v. I, Baden-Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, pp. 103-111. (34) Referindo-se a este propósito também à Carta Social Europeia. Cfr., a propósito deste texto, La Charte sociale européenne. Origines, fonctionnement et résultats, (1991), Strasbourg, Les éditions du Conseil de l'Europe. (35) Veja-se o comentário a esta disposição em The European Union TreatyCommentary on the draft adopted by the European Parliament on 14 February 1984 (por Francesco Capotorti, Meinhard Hilf, Francis G. Jacobs e Jean-Paul Jacqué), Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1986, pp. 39-44. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 183 do Homem e das Liberdades Fundamentais e na Carta Social Europeia, nomeadamente a liberdade, a igualdade e a justiça social». Claramente afirmado no preâmbulo dos Tratados, o compromisso da Comunidade com a protecção dos direitos fundamentais seria ainda retomado pelo Parlamento Europeu, através da adopção, em 12 de Abril de 1989, de uma Declaração dos Direitos e Liberdades Fundamentais ( 36) e seria expressamente realçado pelo Tribunal Constitucional alemão que, por sentença de 22 de Outubro de 1986 ( 37), reconheceria que o Tribunal de Justiça tinha passado a assegurar, pelo desenvolvimento da sua jurisprudência, uma protecção dos direitos fundamentais que no essencial era equivalente à exigida pela lei fundamental alemã ( 38). Se tal compromisso parecia indiscutível, continuava porém a notar-se alguma incerteza sobre as melhores vias para a sua concretização. Assim, (36) Para o respectivo texto, cfr. o Jornal Oficial das Comunidades Europeias, C, 120, de 16 de Maio de 1989, pp. 51-57. Note-se que o Conselho Europeu adoptaria também, a 8 e 9 de Dezembro de 1989, em Estrasburgo, uma Carta Comunitária dos Direitos Fundamentais dos Trabalhadores. (37) Cfr. o respectivo texto na Colectânea das decisões do Bundesverfassungsgericht, v. 73, pp. 339-388. (38) Com o que aquela instância declarava que não exerceria o controlo normativo das disposições de direito comunitário que serviam de base aos actos da administração ou das jurisdições alemãs enquanto o Tribunal de Justiça garantisse uma protecção eficaz dos direitos fundamentais face ao poder da Comunidade. Mas atente-se em que, numa ulterior decisão de 12 de Maio de 1989, o Bundesfassungsgericht voltaria a decidir que se o Tribunal de Justiça continuasse a não garantir os princípios jurídicos sobre os quais se fundamenta a parte da lei fundamental relativa aos direitos fundamentais consideraria admissíveis os recursos que viessem a ser interpostos pelos particulares. É na linha destas preocupações que há que entender a tomada de posição expressa no novo texto do artigo 21 da Grundgesetz (introduzido por ocasião da ratificação alemã do Tratado de Maastricht) e onde se escreve que a República Federal da Alemanha contribui para o desenvolvimento da União Europeia na medida em que esta está vinculada aos princípios federativos, sociais, do Estado de Direito e da democracia e que «garante uma protecção dos direitos fundamentais substancialmente comparável à da presente lei fundamental» (sobre a interpretação deste preceito vide, por último, Uwe Kischel, (2000), «Der unabdingbare grundrechtliche Mindeststandard in der Europäischen Union. Zur Auslegung des Art. 23 Abs. 1 Satz 1 GG», Der Staat, v. 39 pp. 523-545. E sobre os mais recentes desenvolvimentos jurisprudenciais do Tribunal de Karlsruhe a este propósito (falamos do acórdão de 7 de Junho de 2000 proferido a propósito do contencioso das bananas), cfr., numa perspectiva evolutiva, Willy Zimmer, «De nouvelles bases pour la coopération entre la Cour Constitutionnelle Fédérale et la Cour de Justice de Luxembourg? (A propos de BVerfGE, 7 juin 2000, Solange III)», in Europe, Ano 11, n.E 3, de 3 de Março de 2001, pp. 3-6. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 184 enquanto a via pretoriana ensaiada pelo Tribunal de Justiça na sua jurisprudência se mantinha e desenvolvia, e as tentativas de estabelecer um catálogo próprio de direitos fundamentais cujo respeito deveria ser assegurado no sistema comunitário continuavam a não ser coroadas de sucesso(39), a Comissão retomaria a via de um controlo externo do respeito dos direitos fundamentais na Comunidade, ao aprovar, na sequência do já referido Memorando de 4 de Abril de 1979, uma comunicação, a 19 de Novembro de 1990, em que propunha ao Conselho a adesão das Comunidades à Convenção Europeia dos Direitos do Homem( 40). Ainda que apoiada pelo Parlamento, que na sua resolução de 9 de Julho de 1991( 41) sobre os direitos do homem convidaria a Comunidade a aderir à Convenção a fim de melhor garantir o respeito destes direitos, a proposta não colheria a aceitação dos Estados entretanto reunidos em conferência intergovernamental para a revisão dos Tratados, que se limitariam a consagrar expressamente a via pretoriana no direito comunitário primário ao inserirem no Tratado da União Europeia, aprovado em Maastricht em 7 de Fevereiro de 1992, um artigo F, n.E 2, segundo o qual «a União respeitará os direitos fundamentais tal como os garante a Convenção Europeia de Salvaguarda dos Direitos do Homem e das Liberdades Fundamentais, assinada em Roma em 4 de Novembro de 1950, (39) No sentido de que não lograra ainda a aprovação de um documento com carácter vinculativo com este objecto. (40) Sobre o ponto cfr., além dos trabalhos citados supra, na nota 33, G. CohenJonathan, (1984), «La problématique de l'adhésion de la Communauté Européenne à la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme», in Mélanges Henri Teitgen, Paris, Pedone, pp. 81-108; Jean-Paul Jacqué, «L'adhésion de la Communauté Européenne à la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme. Aspects juridiques et techniques», in La protection des droits de l'homme dans le cadre européen (cit. supra, nota 31), pp. 302-319, e «Communauté Européenne et Convention européenne des droits de l'homme», (1992), in L'Europe et le droit. Mélanges en hommage à Jean Boulouis, Paris, Dalloz, pp. 325-340; Moura Ramos, (1990 a 1993), «L'adhésion des Communautés à la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme. Rapport national du Portugal», 16 a 19 Revista de Direito e Economia pp. 753-766; e F.G. Jacobs, (1994), «European Community Law and the European Convention on Human Rights», in Institutional Dynamics of European Integration. Essays in honour of Henry G. Schermers (edited by Deirdre Curtin and Tom Heukels), Dordrecht, Nijhoff, pp. 561571. Identificando também as três possibilidades que citamos em texto, cfr., por exemplo, Jean Vergès, «Droits fondamentaux de la personne et principes généraux du droit communautaire», in L'Europe et le Droit. Mélanges en hommage à Jean Boulouis, cit, pp. 513-531, a p. 515. (41) Cfr. o Jornal Oficial das Comunidades Europeias, C, 240, p. 45. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 185 e tal como resultam das tradições constitucionais comuns aos EstadosMembros, enquanto princípios gerais de direito comunitário». Se os Tratados passavam assim a reconhecer expressamente, no seu texto, a vinculação das Comunidades à protecção dos direitos do homem, a ideia de as submeter a um controlo externo conheceria novo desenvolvimento com a iniciativa do Conselho de, após novo pronunciamento do Parlamento a favor da adesão à Convenção Europeia (42), submeter ao Tribunal de Justiça, em 26 de Abril de 1994, um pedido de parecer sobre a compatibilidade de tal adesão com o Tratado que instituiu a Comunidade Europeia. No parecer que proferiria cerca de dois anos depois ( 43), o Tribunal de Justiça viria a pronunciar-se no sentido de que, «no estado actual do direito comunitário, a Comunidade não tem competências para aderir à Convenção para a Protecção dos Direitos do Homem e das Liberdades Fundamentais». Partindo da constatação (ponto 27) de que «nenhuma disposição do Tratado confere às instituições comunitárias, de modo geral, o poder de adoptar regras em matéria de direitos do homem ou de celebrar convenções neste domínio», o Tribunal analisaria depois a questão de saber se a adesão da Comunidade se pode basear no artigo 235.E (ponto 31). Realçando a importância dos direitos fundamentais e retomando a sua jurisprudência a este propósito (ponto 33), o Tribunal chegaria contudo a uma conclusão negativa quanto ao problema que lhe era submetido considerando que «a adesão à Convenção implicava uma alteração substancial do regime comunitário actual de protecção dos direitos do homem, na medida em que teria como resultado a inserção da Comunidade num sistema institucional internacional distinto, bem como a integração do conjunto de disposições da Convenção na ordem jurídica comunitária» (ponto 35); acrescentando que «tal alteração do regime de protecção dos direitos do homem na Comunidade, cujas implicações institucionais seriam igualmente fundamentais tanto para a Comunidade como para os Estados-Membros, teria relevância constitucional e ultrapassaria, pois, pela sua natureza, os (42) Ver a Resolução de 18 de Janeiro de 1994 in Jornal Oficial das Comunidades Europeias, C, 44, p. 32. Para uma análise da posição do Parlamento na questão que os ocupa, cfr. Jean-Pierre Cot, (2000), «Le Parlement européen et la protection des droits fondamentaux dans le cadre de l'Convention européenne», in Les droits de l'homme au seuil du troisième millénaire. Mélanges en hommage à Pierre Lambert, Bruxelles, Bruylant, pp. 155-170. (43) Parecer 2/94, de 28 de Março de 1996 (in Colectânea, 1996, pp. 1763-1790). A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 186 limites do artigo 235.E», só podendo ser realizada pela via de uma modificação do Tratado (ponto 35) ( 44). Face a esta tomada de posição, a Conferência intergovernamental, que se iniciaria em Turim no dia seguinte à prolação do parecer do Tribunal, optaria por, deixando de lado outras propostas(45), reforçar a referência ao princípio do respeito dos direitos do homem e das liberdades fundamentais, que passa a ser considerado, conjuntamente com os princípios da liberdade, da democracia e do Estado de direito, um princípio comum aos Estados-Membros e que constitui um dos fundamentos da União( 46). Mas não tomaria qualquer iniciativa tendente a elaborar um (44) Para a crítica da solução adoptada e o inventário das diferentes possibilidades que subsistem de melhor assegurar a protecção dos direitos fundamentais na ordem jurídica comunitária, cfr., respectivamente, Michel Waelbroeck, (1996), «La Cour de justice et la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme», Cahiers de droit européen, 37 pp. 549-553; Olivier de Schutter, Yves Lejeune, «L'adhésion de la Communauté à la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme. À propos de l'avis 2/94 de la Cour de justice des Communautés», ibidem, pp. 555-606, e Claudio Zanghi, «Un’altra critica al parere 2/94 della Corte sull' adesione della Comunità alla convenzione europea dei diritti dell'uomo», in Scritti in onore di Giuseppe Federico Mancini (cit. supra, nota 31), pp. 1101-1120. (45) Cfr., sobre as propostas de um «comité de sábios» designado pela Comissão em Outubro de 1995 com o objectivo de reflectir e formular propostas concretas sobre a reforma dos direitos civis e sociais à atenção da conferência intergovernamental, o juízo crítico de Eduardo Garcia de Enteria, (1996), em «Les droits fondamentaux et la révision du traité sur la Convention européenne», Cahiers de droit européen, 37, pp. 607-612. (46) Veja-se o artigo 6.E (antigo artigo F), n.E 1, do Tratado da União Europeia, tal como este preceito ficou depois do Tratado de Amsterdão de 2 de Outubro de 1997. Saliente-se que, de acordo com a nova redação do artigo 49.E (antigo artigo O), n.E 1, daquele Tratado, o acatamento do princípio do respeito dos direitos do homem e das liberdades fundamentais (como dos demais princípios mencionados no artigo 6.E) passa a constituir uma condição de adesão dos outros Estados europeus à União Europeia. E que, pelo seu artigo 46.E (antigo artigo L), alínea d), o Tribunal de Justiça passa a exercer o seu controlo também ao artigo 6.E, n.E 2, no que respeita à acção das instituições na medida em que ele seja competente nos termos dos tratados que instituem as Comunidades Europeias e nos termos do tratado da União. Sobre o alcance destas alterações, cfr. Bruno Nascimbene, «Tutela dei diritti fondamentali e competenza della Corte di Giustiza nel Trattato di Amsterdam», in Scritti in onore di Giuseppe Federico Mancini (cit. supra, nota 31), pp. 683-694; Koen Lenaerts, (2000), «Respect for fundamental rights as a constitutional principle of the European Union», 6 The Columbia Journal of European Law, pp. 1-25 e Peter Oliver, (2000), «Fundamental rights in European Union law after the Treaty of Amsterdam», in Judicial Review in European Union Law. Liber amicorum in honour of Lord Slynn of Hadley, The Hague, Kluwer Law International, pp. 319-342. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 187 catálogo de direitos fundamentos que vinculasse a União ou a Comunidade(47) e conservaria o antigo artigo F (actualmente artigo 6.E), n.E 2 do Tratado da União, que condensava a base jurídica que permitira o desenvolvimento da concepção pretoriana de defesa dos direitos fundamentais no quadro comunitário ( 48). 6. Se as negocia ções que conduziram à adopção do Tratado de Amsterdão se limitaram, no que diz respeito à protecção dos direitos fundamentais na União Europeia, ao ponto que acabamos de mencionar, a situação evoluiria no entanto muito rapidamente mal havia decorrido um mês após a entrada em vigor deste Tratado(49). É assim que, ao mesmo tempo que, no Conselho Europeu de Colónia de 3 e 4 de Junho de 1999, anunciavam a convocação de uma nova conferência intergovernamental para concluir as questões que em Amsterdão tinham ficado por resolver e para as quais urgia encontrar uma solução(50), nomeadamente na perspectiva do alargamento em curso da União(51), os chefes de Estado e de governo decidiam, face ao estado de desenvolvimento desta, «estabelecer uma carta de direitos fundamentais a fim de sublinhar, de maneira visível para os cidadãos da União, a sua importância excepcional e o seu alcance». (47) Como o fizera o comité referido supra , na nota 45. Para uma análise do elenco de direitos a considerar neste âmbito, vejam-se também os trabalhos recolhidos na obra organizada por Antonio Cassese, Andrew Clapham, Joseph Weiler (eds.), (1991), Human Rights and the European Community: The Substantive Law, BadenBaden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft. (48) No sentido de que a protecção dos direitos fundamentais no sistema comunitário parece desde o princípio hesitar entre esta concepção, o estabelecimento de um controlo externo e a instituição de um catálogo de direitos fundamentais próprio ao sistema comunitário, cfr., entre outros, Gregorio Robles Morchon, (1988), Los derechos fundamentales en la Comunidad Europea, Madrid, Editorial Ceura, pp. 153159, e Andrew Claphan, Human Rights and the European Community: A Critical Overview (cit. supra, nota 31), pp. 90-99. (49) O Tratado de Amsterdão, assinado a 2 de Outubro de 1997, viria a entrar em vigor a 1 de Maio de 1999. (50) Tratava-se, fundamentalmente, de um acordo quanto à reponderação das vozes dos Estados no seio do Conselho, ao elenco de matérias quanto às quais uma decisão por maioria qualificada (e não já por unanimidade) seria possível, e à composição numérica da Comissão. (51) Recorde-se que para além da Estónia, da Hungria, da Polónia, da República Checa, da Eslováquia e da Eslovénia, cuja adesão se admite possa ter lugar a partir de 2004, a União Europeia negoceia ainda com a Bulgária, Chipre, a Letónia, a Lituânia, Malta e a Roménia, para além de ter igualmente pendente o pedido de adesão da Turquia cuja consideração continua algo suspensa da situação deste último país em matéria de respeito dos direitos humanos. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 188 Os termos da decisão sublinham de modo claro que se procurou sobretudo dar maior visibilidade e transparência ao sistema de protecção dos direitos fundamentais já existente na União, tornando mais explícitos os parâmetros em que até ao presente se tem baseado a jurisprudência do Tribunal de Justiça. O que pareceria justificar-se à luz do reforço das competências da União em áreas onde a questão da protecção dos direitos fundamentais se coloca em termos particularmente sensíveis, do anunciado alargamento a países até há pouco governados por regimes não democráticos e à necessária concordância com o lugar que a problemática da protecção dos direitos humanos tem ocupado na política externa da União. Procurando, com a elaboração da Carta, dar uma contribuição à identidade da Europa e aumentar o sentimento de pertença dos cidadãos europeus a esta entidade, o Conselho Europeu tinha em mente a elaboração de um documento que pudesse ser redigido e apresentado antes da sua reunião prevista para Nice em Dezembro de 2000, de modo a que nela ele pudesse propor ao Parlamento e à Comissão a sua proclamação conjunta, ficando a sua eventual inserção nos tratados para ser examinada subsequentemente. Mais tarde, na sua reunião de Tampere, em 15 e 16 de Outubro de 1999, o Conselho Europeu, aprovaria a composição do órgão( 52), posteriormente denominado «Convenção», que elaboraria o projecto de Carta. A discussão respectiva iniciar-se-ia em 13 de Janeiro de 2000, estando um primeiro projecto concluído a 28 de Julho e um segundo a 14 de Setembro e obtendo-se a 26 do mesmo mês um consenso sobre um texto que seria formalmente adoptado a 2 de Outubro de 2000( 53). Reunido em (52) A Convenção compreendia, como membros de pleno direito, 15 representantes dos chefes de Estado e de Governo dos Estados-Membros, um representante do presidente da Comissão, 15 membros do Parlamento Europeu designados por este e 30 membros dos parlamentos nacionais (dois por cada EstadoMembro) por eles designados. Como observadores previu-se a participação de dois representantes do Tribunal de Justiça e dois do Conselho da Europa, um dos quais representando o Tribunal Europeu dos Direitos do Homem. Para além disso, diversas instâncias comunitárias (designadamente o Comité Económico e Social, o Comité das Regiões e o Mediador) seriam convidadas a pronunciar-se na fase de elaboração do documento. (53) Sobre o método de trabalho da Convenção e os seus resultados, cfr. em particular, as actas das journées d'études sobre La Charte des droits fondamentaux de la Convention européenne que tiveram lugar a 16 e 17 de Junho de 2000 em Estrasburgo [in Revue universelle des droits de l'homme, v. 12 (2000), pp. 1-83]; Laura Carrasco Macia, «Le projet de Charte des droits fondamentaux de l'Union Européenne», EIPASCOPE, n.E 2000/3, pp. 19-27; António Vitorino, «La Charte des droits A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 189 Biarritz a 13 e 14 de Outubro, o Conselho Europeu aprovaria o texto por unanimidade, abrindo assim a via para a sua proclamação solene em Nice, nos termos referidos. Após um preâmbulo em que se recordam, por um lado, os fundamentos e objectivos da União e a importância da protecção dos direitos fundamentais no desenvolvimento das suas missões, e, por outro lado, as fontes( 54) dos direitos que a União reconhece pela presente Carta, estes aparecem-nos enunciados em 50 artigos, divididos em seis capítulos ( 55), que são completados por um último, contendo quatro disposições de carácter mais geral. Estando fora dos objectivos do presente trabalho a análise cuidada da condensação a que se chegou neste bill of rights, não deixaremos no entanto de fazer uma breve referência ao seu conteúdo. Assim, no Capítulo I enumeraram-se os direitos que decorrem imediatamente da inviolabilidade da dignidade do ser humano (proclamada no artigo 1.E): o direito à vida (com expressa proibição da pena capital) (artigo 2.E), o direito à integridade (com a particularização, no domínio da medicina e da biologia, do necessário respeito do consentimento livre e esclarecido da pessoa, da proibição das práticas eugénicas, da fondamentaux de la Convention européenne», Revue du droit de la Convention européenne, n.E 3/2000, pp. 499-508; Melchior Wathelet, «La Charte des droits fondamentaux: un bon pas dans une course qui reste longue», Cahiers de Droit européen, v. 36 (2000), pp. 585-593; Gráinne de Búrca, (2001), «The drafting of the European Union Charter of Fundamental Rights», 26 European Law Review, pp. 126138; o editorial comment («The EU Charter of Fundamental Rights still under discussion») do n.E 1 do v. 38 (2001) da Common Market Law Review (pp. 1-6) e Giorgio Sacerdoti, (2002), «The European Charter of Fundamental Rights: From a Nation-State Europe to a Citizen's Europe», 8 Columbia Journal of European Law pp. 37-52. (54) A Carta refere-se, a este propósito, aos direitos que decorrem «das tradições constitucionais e das obrigações internacionais comuns aos Estados-Membros, do Tratado da União Europeia e dos Tratados comunitários, da Convenção Europeia para a Protecção dos Direitos do Homem e das Liberdades Fundamentais, das Cartas sociais aprovadas pela Comunidade e pelo Conselho da Europa, bem como da jurisprudência do Tribunal de Justiça das Comunidades Europeias e do Tribunal Europeu dos Direitos do Homem». Sobre a extensão progressiva das fontes dos direitos fundamentais no sistema de direito da União Europeia e para um ensaio da sua sistematização, cfr. Fabrice Picod, (2000),«Les sources», in Réalité et perspectives du droit communautaire des droits fondamentaux, Bruxelles, Bruylant, pp. 125-185. (55) Intitulados, respectivamente, Dignidade, Liberdades, Igualdade, Solidariedade, Cidadania e Justiça. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 190 transformação total ou parcial do corpo humano em fonte de lucro e da clonagem reprodutiva dos seres humanos) (artigo 3.E), a proibição da tortura e dos tratos ou penas desumanas e degradantes (artigo 4.E) e a proibição da escravidão e do trabalho forçado (com especial referência à proibição do tráfico de seres humanos) (artigo 5.E). Sob a epígrafe Liberdades, o Capítulo II consagra em seguida vários dos direitos reconhecidos já pela Convenção Europeia, como o direito à liberdade e à segurança (artigo 6.E), o direito ao respeito pela vida privada e familiar (artigo 7.E), o direito de contrair casamento e de constituir família (com remissão, quanto ao respectivo exercício, para as legislações nacionais respectivas) (artigo 9.E), a liberdade de pensamento, consciência e religião (com o reconhecimento do direito à objecção de consciência) (artigo 10.E), a liberdade de expressão e de informação, que inclui o respeito da liberdade e do pluralismo dos meios de comunicação social (artigo 11.E), a liberdade de reunião e de associação, com específica referência ao domínio político e o reconhecimento de que os partidos políticos ao nível da União contribuem para a expressão da vontade política dos cidadãos da União (artigo 12.E) ( 56v , pelos respectivos Protocolos Adicionais, como o direito de propriedade, com referência expressa à protecção da propriedade intelectual (artigo 17.E), o direito à educação (artigo 14.E) (57), e a protecção em caso de afastamento, expulsão ou extradição (artigo 19.E) (58), pela Carta Social Europeia, como o direito ao trabalho (artigo 15.E) (59) ou por outros documentos internacionais ( 60), como o direito de asilo (artigo 18.E). Mas reconhecem-se igualmente outros direitos, que entretanto obtiveram eco nos ordenamentos constitucionais (56) Cfr., no mesmo sentido, o actual artigo 191.E do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia (antigo artigo 138.E-A), tal como foi introduzido neste instrumento convencional em 1992, pelo Tratado da União Europeia. (57) O artigo 2.E do Protocolo n.E 1 falava, com um alcance aparentemente mais restrito, do direito à instrução. Mas assinale-se que o direito à formação profissional era já reconhecido pela Carta Social Europeia (artigo 10.E). Sublinhe-se porém que o texto a que nos reportamos consagra expressamente «o respeito (...) da liberdade de criação de estabelecimentos de ensino, no respeito pelos princípios democráticos e o direito dos pais de assegurarem a educação e o ensino dos filhos de acordo com as suas convicções religiosas, filosóficas e pedagógicas». (58) Ainda que em termos mais alargados do que acontecia nas disposições dos Protocolos n.os 4 e 7. (59) Que surge enunciado em termos mais latos como liberdade profissional e direito de trabalhar. (60) Trata-se, no caso, da Convenção de Genebra, de 28 de Julho de 1951 e do Protocolo de 31 de Janeiro de 1967, relativos ao estatuto dos refugiados. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 191 nacionais e no próprio sistema comunitário, como a protecção de dados pessoais (artigo 8.E) ( 61v e a liberdade da empresa (artigo 16.E), ou que em geral não são objecto de um reconhecimento específico, como a liberdade das artes e das ciências (artigo 13.E). O Capítulo III, a propósito da igualdade, consagra especialmente a igualdade perante a lei (artigo 20.E) e a proibição da discriminação (artigo 21.E) (62), para afirmar depois o compromisso da União com o respeito da diversidade cultural, religiosa e linguística (artigo 22.E), a igualdade entre homens e mulheres em todos os domínios, incluindo emprego, trabalho e remuneração, com explícita previsão da possibilidade de medidas positivas a favor do sexo sub-representado (artigo 23.E), os direitos das crianças (artigo 24.E) (63), e das pessoas idosas (artigo 25.E) e a integração das pessoas com deficiência (artigo 26.E). No Capítulo IV, e sob a epígrafe Solidariedade, reúne-se um conjunto de direitos de natureza social que na maior parte dos casos já se encontram consagradas quer na ordem jurídica comunitária (ou nos Tratados ou no direito derivado) quer nas ordens jurídicas dos EstadosMembros (64). É o que se passa com as disposições relativas à protecção da (61) Cfr., no que toca a Portugal, o artigo 35.E da Constituição da República. No sistema comunitário, saliente-se que por força de um novo artigo 213.E-B, introduzido no Tratado da Comunidade Europeia pelo Tratado de Amsterdão (hoje artigo 286.E) os actos comunitários relativos à protecção das pessoas singulares em matéria de tratamento de dados de carácter pessoal e de livre circulação desses dados (trata-se das Directivas 95/46/CE e 97/66/CE, ambas do Parlamento e do Conselho, respectivamente de 24 de Outubro de 1995 e de 15 de Dezembro de 1997) serão aplicáveis, a partir de 1 de Janeiro de 1999, às Instituições e órgãos instituídos pelo presente Tratado, ou com base nele (n.E 1) e que, antes dessa data, o Conselho, através do processo da codecisão, deveria criar um órgão independente de supervisão, incumbido de fiscalizar a sua aplicação, e tomar as demais disposições que se revelem adequadas (n.E 2) ) para o efeito, veja-se o Regulamento n.E 45/2001 (in Jornal Oficial, L, 8, p. 1). (62) Que, para além de recordar a proibição da discriminação com base na nacionalidade, no âmbito de aplicação dos Tratados da Comunidade Europeia e da União Europeia, alarga a outros fundamentos, como as características genéticas, a deficiência ou a orientação sexual, a expressa proibição da discriminação. (63) Onde, para além da referência ao interesse superior da criança, na linha da Convenção das Nações Unidas sobre os direitos da criança, de 20 de Novembro de 1989, se consagra o direito à livre expressão da opinião desta, que deverá ser tomada em consideração nos assuntos que lhe digam respeito em função da sua idade e maturidade. (64) Para uma análise recente, numa perspectiva comparatística, da situação dos direitos sociais nos sistemas jurídicos dos Estados-Membros da União, cfr. Julia Iliopoulos-Strangas (ed.), (2000), La protection des droits sociaux fondamentaux dans 192 A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia saúde (artigo 35.E), ao acesso a serviços de interesse económico geral (artigo 36.E) (65), à protecção do ambiente (artigo 37.E) e à defesa dos consumidores (artigo 38.E) que consagram um dispositivo que se não afasta particularmente do que encontrávamos já, respectivamente, nos artigos 152.E, 86.E, 174.E e 153.E do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia. Ou com os direitos à informação e à consulta dos trabalhadores na empresa (artigo 27.E), de negociação e acção colectiva (artigo 28.E), e de acesso aos serviços de emprego (artigo 29.E), reconhecidos já nos artigos 17.E, 11 e 6. E do Título I da Carta Comunitária dos Direitos Sociais Fundamentais dos Trabalhadores. Da mesma forma que o disposto a propósito das condições de trabalho justas e equitativas (artigo 31.E), da proibição do trabalho infantil e protecção dos jovens no trabalho (artigo 32.E), da vida familiar e profissional (artigo 33.E) e da segurança social e da assistência social (artigo 34.E) se situa na linha do prescrito, respectivamente nos artigos 2.E, 7.E, 16.E e 12.E e 13.E da Carta Social Europeia, ainda que as novas regras reflictam compreensivelmente os desenvolvimentos entretanto operados nas concepções e práticas existentes. Mas salientam-se de igual modo alguns rasgos inovadores neste plano, como a afirmação da protecção em les Etats membres de la Convention européenne. Etude de droit comparé, Bruxelles, Bruylant. (65) A problemática dos serviços de interesse económico geral ganharia especial actualidade a partir do Tratado de Amsterdão que introduziria no Tratado da Comunidade Europeia um novo artigo 7.E-D (hoje artigo 16.E) que, atendendo à posição que estes serviços ocupam no conjunto dos valores da União e ao papel que desempenham na promoção da coesão social e territorial, dispõe que, sem prejuízo dos artigos 77.E, 90.E e 92.E (hoje artigos 73.E, 86.E e 88.E), a Comunidade e os seus Estados-Membros, dentro dos limites das respectivas competências e dentro do âmbito de aplicação do presente Tratado, zelarão por que esses serviços funcionem com base em princípios e em condições que lhes permitam cumprir as suas missões. A Conferência Intergovernamental aprovaria ainda uma Declaração a este artigo (Declaração n.E 13) que sublinharia que as suas disposições relativas aos serviços públicos seriam aplicadas no pleno respeito pela jurisprudência do Tribunal de Justiça, nomeadamente no que se refere aos princípios da igualdade de tratamento, da qualidade e da continuidade desses serviços (sobre o ponto, cfr. C.F. Molina del Pozo, (1999), «Los servicios de interés general en el derecho comunitario: especial referencia a su regulacíon en el Tratado de Amsterdam», in Cuadernos Europeos de Deusto, v. 21 pp. 125-160). Mais recentemente o Conselho Europeu de Nice tomaria nota da comunicação da Comissão sobre os serviços de interesse geral (in JOCE, C, 17, pp. 4-23) e aprovaria a declaração adoptada pelo Conselho a este respeito, que reconhece o papel daqueles serviços para assegurar a coesão económica e social na União Europeia no seio dos valores comuns que fundam o modelo social europeu (sem prejuízo dos referidos artigos 73.E, 86.E e 87.E). A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 193 caso de despedimento sem justa causa (artigo 30.E), ainda que o seu conteúdo concreto seja obtido por remissão para o direito comunitário e as legislações e práticas nacionais. Em matéria de cidadania, o Capítulo V da Carta segue de perto a actual parte II do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia, ao consagrar o direito de eleger e de ser eleito nas eleições para o Parlamento Europeu (artigo 39.E), de eleger e de ser eleito nas eleições municipais (artigo 40.E), de se dirigir ao Provedor de Justiça (artigo 43.E), de circular e permanecer livremente no território dos Estados-Membros (artigo 45.E) e de beneficiar de protecção diplomática e consular (artigo 46.E) ( 66). E inclui também o (66) Cfr., respectivamente, os artigos 19.E, n.E 2, 19.E, n.E 1, 21.E, parágrafo 2, 21.E, parágrafo 1, 18.E e 20.E do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia. E sobre a origem, desenvolvimento e sentido da cidadania da União, instituída pelo Tratado de Maastricht, cfr. Moura Ramos, (1999), «Maastricht e os direitos do cidadão europeu», in Das Comunidades à União Europeia. Estudos de Direito Comunitário, 2.a edição, Coimbra, Coimbra Editora, pp. 323-358; Carlos Closa, (1992), «The concept of citizenship in the Treaty of European Union», Common Market Law Review, 29 pp. 1137-1169; Robert Kovar, Denys Simon, (1993), «La citoyenneté européenne», Cahiers de Droit Européen, 29 pp. 285-315; Stephen Hall, (1995), Nationality, Migration Rights and citizenship of the Union, Dordrecht, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers; Maria Elizabete Gomes Ramos, «Breves notas sobre a cidadania da União Europeia», Temas de Integração, v. I (1.E semestre de 1996), pp. 63-112; Elisa Perez Vera, (1996), «Citoyenneté de la Convention européenne: Nationalité et Condition des Étrangers», Recueil des Cours de l'Académie de Droit International de la Haye, t. 261, pp. 245425; Jo Shaw, (1997), «The Many Pasts and Futures of Citizenship in the European Union», European Law Review, 22, pp. 554-572; Joseph H.H. Weiler, (1998), «To be an European Citizen», in Scritti in onore di Giuseppe Federico Mancini, v. II-Diritto dell'Unione Europea, Milano, Giuffrè, pp. 1067-1099; Patrick Dollat, (1998), Libre circulation des personnes et citoyenneté: enjeux et perspectives, Bruxelles, Bruylant; Maria Dolores Blázquez Peinado, (1998), La ciudadania de la Union (Los derechos reconocidos en los articulos 8.A a 8.D del T.C.E.) , Valencia, Tirant lo blanch; Pilar Juarez Perez, (1998), Nacionalidad estatal y ciudadania europea, Madrid; Marcel Pons, Marie José Garot, (1999), La Citoyenneté de la Convention européenne, Paris, L'Harmattan; Miguel Gorjão Henriques, «Cidadania e Integração», ibidem, v. IV (2.E semestre de 1999), pp. 65-91, (2000), La Citoyenneté européenne (sob a direcção de Christian Philip e Panayotis Soldatos), Montreal, Chaire Jean Monnet, Université de Montréal; e a série de estudos recolhidos na colectânea organizada por Massimo Le Torre intitulada European Citizenship. An Institutional Challenge e citada supra, na nota 7. Para uma análise do desenvolvimento jurisprudencial dos preceitos que a consagram, cfr. Helen Toner, (2000), «Judicial Interpretation of European Union Citizenship. Transformation or Consolidation?», Maastricht Journal of Comparative Law, 2, pp. 158-182. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 194 direito de acesso aos documentos (artigo 42.E) (67) que o Tratado de Amsterdão inserira naquele mesmo Tratado, passando a contribuir o seu artigo 255.E. Além sido, o artigo 41.E da Carta consagra o direito de todas as pessoas a uma boa administração que, para além de abranger dois direitos até agora já expressamente reconhecidos no Tratado da Comunidade Europeia ( 68), se desdobra igualmente no direito de todas as pessoas a que os seus assuntos sejam tratados pelas instituições e órgãos da União de forma imparcial, equitativa e num prazo razoável, direito cujos corolários haviam sido já igualmente recebidos nos próprios Tratados, no direito derivado ou na jurisprudência dos tribunais comunitários ( 69). O catálogo dos direitos fundamentais reconhecidos pela Carta concluiu-se com o capítulo dedicado à Justiça onde se consagram o direito (67) Situando este direito num contexto mais geral, no plano da ordem jurídica comunitária, cfr. Hans Ragnemalm, «Démocratie et transparence. Sur le droit général d'accès des citoyens de la Convention européenne aux documents detenus par les institutions euro péennes», in Scritti in onore di Giuseppe Federico Mancini, v. IIDirittto dell'Unione Europea, Milano, Giuffrè, (1998), pp. 809-830; Roberto Viciano Pastor, «Publicité et accès aux documents officiels dans les institutions de la Convention européenne avant et après le Traité d'Amsterdam», in Mélanges en hommage à Michel Waelbroeck, v. I, Bruxelles, Bruylant, (1999), pp. 649-681; Bo Vesterdorf, (1999), «Transparency. Not just a vague word», in 22 Fordham International Law Journal pp. 902-929, maxime 913-924 e D.M. Curtin, (2000), «Citizens fundamental right of acess to EU information: An evolving digital passepartout?», 37 Common Market Law Review, pp. 7-41. (68) O direito à reparação, por parte da Comunidade, dos danos causados pelas suas instituições ou pelos agentes no exercício das respectivas funções, de acordo com os princípios gerais comuns às legislações dos Estados-Membros e o direito de se dirigir às instituições da União numa das línguas oficiais dos Tratados, devendo obter uma resposta na mesma língua, consagrados, respectivamente, nos actuais artigos 288.E, parágrafo 2, e 21.E, parágrafo 3, do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia. (69) A Carta refere expressamente, a este propósito, o direito de qualquer pessoa ser ouvida antes de a seu respeito ser tomada qualquer medida que a afecte desfavoravelmente (cfr., por exemplo, em matéria de concorrência, o artigo 19.E, n.E 1, do Regulamento n.E 17/62, do Conselho, de 6 de Fevereiro de 1962, e os artigos 2 a 9 do Regulamento n.E 99/63/CEE, da Comissão, de 25 de Julho de 1963), o direito a ter acesso aos processos que se lhe refiram, no respeito dos legítimos interesses da confidencialidade e do segredo profissional e comercial (cfr. o artigo 287.E do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia) e a obrigação, por parte da administração, de fundamentar as suas decisões (cfr. o actual artigo 253.E do Tratado da Comunidade Europeia). Em particular quanto ao direito a obter uma decisão da administração num prazo razoável, cfr. o acórdão do Tribunal de Primeira Instância de 22 de Outubro de 1997, SCK e FNK/Comissão, T-213/95 e T-18/96, Colectânea, p. II-1731, que o qualifica como princípio geral de direito comunitário (ponto 56). A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 195 à acção e a um tribunal imparcial (artigo 47.E), a presunção de inocência e os direitos da defesa (artigo 48.E), os princípios da legalidade e da proporcionalidade dos delitos e das penas (artigo 49.E) e o direito a não ser julgado ou punido penalmente mais do que uma vez pelo mesmo delito no interior da União (artigo 50.E), em termos que, salvo quanto ao último( 70), reproduzem praticamente o disposto nos artigo 6.E e 7.E da Convenção Europeia. Finalmente, a Carta inclui ainda num último capítulo (o VII) um conjunto de disposições gerais que visam o alcance e os efeitos dos preceitos anteriores. Assim, na primeira (artigo 51.E), e a propósito dos destinatários das regras da Carta, sublinha-se que estes são constituídos pelas instituições e órgãos da União, na observância do princípio da subsidariedade, e pelos Estados-Membros, apenas quando aplicam o direito da União( 71). A ambas estas entidades cabe assim respeitar os direitos, observar os princípios e promover a sua aplicação, de acordo com as respectivas competências. Fiel ao objectivo de se limitar a garantir a transparência do sistema, o número 2 deste artigo sublinha ainda que a Carta não cria quaisquer novas atribuições ou competências para a (70) O acolhimento, nos termos em que é feito, do princípio do ne bis in idem configura no entanto uma concepção algo limitativa deste princípio uma vez que apenas dá relevo para o efeito a um anterior julgamento no território da União. No sistema jurídico português, por exemplo, o princípio tem um alcance mais lato, obtendo inclusivamente consagração constitucional no artigo 29.E, n.E 5 da lei fundamental. Cfr., já no domínio do Código Penal de 1886, Eduardo Correia (com a colaboração de Figueiredo Dias), 1968, Direito Criminal, v. I, Coimbra, Livraria Almedina, p. 175, e, hoje, o artigo 6.E, n.E 1 do Código Penal de 1982. (71) Para uma análise dos primeiros arestos jurisprudenciais neste sentido, cfr. Joseph H. H. Weiler, (1991), «The European Court at a crossroads: Community human rights and member State action», in Du droit international au droit de l'intégration. Liber amicorum Pierre Pescatore, Baden-Baden, Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, pp. 821842. Sublinhando as limitações da fórmula utilizada, em contraposição com a (mais ampla) expressão utilizada pela jurisprudência comunitária que precisa que as exigências dos direitos fundamentais devem ser respeitadas também quando se trate de uma regulamentação nacional que «entre no campo de aplicação do direito comunitário», cfr. Sophia Koukoulis -Spiliotopoulos, «De Biarritz à Nice: le projet de Charte des droits fondamentaux est-il bien articulé avec le droit de l'Union?», in Gazette Européenne, n.E 25 (dimanche 29 au mardi 31 octobre 2000), pp. 18-23. E sobre o alcance desta última fórmula, cfr. Florence Zampini, (1999), «La Cour de justice des Communautés Européennes gardienne des droits fondamentaux ‘dans le cadre du droit communautaire’», Revue trimestrelle de droit européen, pp. 659-707. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 196 Comunidade ou para a União, não modificando também as atribuições e competências definidas nos Tratados. Em sede de âmbito dos direitos garantidos, o artigo 52.E dispõe sobre a sua restrição e o seu conteúdo. Quanto ao primeiro aspecto, prescreve o n.E 1 que ela deve ser prevista por lei e respeitar o conteúdo essencial desses direitos e liberdades(72). Mais particularmente, precisa-se que, na observância do princípio da proporciona lidade, essas restrições só podem ser introduzidas se forem necessárias e corresponderem efectivamente a objectivos de interesse geral reconhecidos pela União. ou à necessidade de protecção dos direitos e liberdades de terceiros. Quanto ao alcance dos direitos reconhecidos, o n.E 2 sublinha que, quando eles se baseiam nos Tratados comunitários ou no Tratado da União Europeia, são exercidos de acordo com as condições e limites por estes definidos ( 73), acrescentando o n.E 3 que igual regra vale quanto aos direitos correspondentes aos direitos garantidos pela Convenção Europeia, a não ser que a Carta lhes confira uma protecção mais extensa ou mais ampla (74). A propósito do nível de protecção conferido, o artigo 53.E clarifica ainda que as disposições da Carta não podem ser interpretadas no sentido de restringir ou lesar os direitos do Homem e as liberdades fundamentais reconhecidos, nos respectivos âmbitos de aplicação, pelo direito da União, o direito internacional e as convenções internacionais em que são partes a União, a Comunidade ou todos os Estados-Membros, nomeadamente a Convenção Europeia, bem como pelas Constituições dos EstadosMembros. Enfim, numa disposição final (artigo 54.E) proíbe-se o abuso do direito, esclarecendo-se que as normas da Carta não devem ser interpretadas no sentido de exercer actividades ou praticar actos que visem a destruição dos direitos ou liberdades por elas reconhecidos, ou restrições maiores desses direitos e liberdades que as previstas na Carta (75). 7. Das considerações que precedem parece emergir a conclusão(76) de que o sistema de protecção dos direitos fundamentais proclamados com a Carta se não concebe em termos de instrumento de uma alteração substancial da situação a este respeito vivida no seio da União. Bem pelo contrário, e muito mais modestamente, para além de não lhe ser atribuída (72) Cfr., em idêntico sentido, o artigo 18.E da Constituição Portuguesa. De algum modo se confirmando assim a natureza não inovatória da Carta, quanto ao conteúdo do sistema de protecção dos direitos fundamentais nela contido. (74) Possibilidade esta que o preceito em análise expressamente reafirma. (75) Em idêntico sentido, cfr. o artigo 17.E da Convenção Europeia. (76) Sublinhada em particular nas Disposições Gerais. (73) A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 197 especial força jurídica vinculante, a Carta aparenta não visar alterar de modo algum o equilíbrio existente entre a Comunidade e a União, por um lado, e os seus Estados-Membros (77), por outro, resultado que aliás deveria ser atingido por alteração dos Tratados. Daí que se insista em que os destinatários dos seus comandos são as instituições e órgãos da União, na observância do princípio da subsidariedade (78), bem como os EstadosMembros apenas quando apliquem o direito da União( 79). Mas se a Carta não pretende trazer nada de novo no domínio das relações entre a Comunidade e a União e os seus Estados-Membros, ela também não parece inovar demasiado, em sede de conteúdo dos direitos garantidos, quando precisa, no artigo 52.E, n.E 2, que os direitos nela reconhecidos que se baseiam nos Tratados comunitários ou no Tratado da União são exercidos de acordo com as condições e limites por estes definidos ( 80), e que as suas disposições não podem ser interpretadas no sentido e restringir ou lesar o nível de protecção dos direitos fundamentais já atingido no sistema comunitário ( 81). (77) Expressamente neste sentido o artigo 51.E, n.E 2, sublinha que a Carta «não cria quaisquer novas atribuições ou competências para a Comunidade ou para a União, nem modifica as atribuições e competências definidas nos tratados». (78) Sublinhado nosso. (79) Cfr. o que dizemos supra, na nota 71. A fórmula parece querer sublinhar que a aprovação da Carta não envolve qualquer novo compromisso ou limitação da competência estadual. (80) Uma disposição paralela acrescenta que na medida que os direitos reconhecidos na Carta sejam correspondentes aos garantidos na Convenção Europeia o seu sentido e âmbito são iguais aos conferidos por esta Convenção, a não ser que a Carta garanta, o que sempre será possível, uma protecção mais extensa ou mais ampla. A recondução do conteúdo dos direitos fundamentais que a União deve garantir ao alcance que estes obtiveram na jurisprudência do Tribunal dos Direitos do Homem é um dado adquirido pela jurisprudência comunitária ) cfr. por exemplo o acórdão de 28 de Março de 2000, Krombach, C-7/98 (ainda não publicado) e Moura Ramos, (2000), «Public policy in the framework of the Brussels Convention. Remarks on two recent decisions by the European Court of Justice», 2 Yearbook of Private International Law, pp. 25-39 (33-39). Atente-se porém em que o relacionamento entre a jurisprudência de Estrasburgo e a do Luxemburgo não se faz apenas neste sentido, podendo igualmente detectar-se uma influência da existência do direito comunitário sobre a interpretação da Convenção Europeia. Neste sentido, cfr. já Maurice Mendelson, (1984), L'incidence du droit communautaire sur la mise en oeuvre de la Convention européenne des droits de l'homme, Strasbourg, Conselho da Europa, especialmente pp. 28-31. (81) Cfr. o artigo 53.E. A carta dos direitos fundamentais da União Europeia 198 Confirma-se assim que a Carta corresponde ao objectivo querido pelo Conselho Europeu de dar visibilidade ao sistema comunitário de protecção dos direitos fundamentais, sem prejudicar o destino de questões que até agora se encontravam em debate, como a adesão da Comunidade ou da União à Convenção Europeia, nem dar passos significativos na senda da definição quer de um sistema de protecção de direitos humanos a que seja reconhecida centralidade na construção do ordenamento comunitário ( 82), quer do conteúdo específico que àqueles direitos deva caber, tendo em conta as suas exigências, neste sistema jurídico( 83). Mas esta modéstia não exclui que, sem pretender embora constituir mais do que o fruto da codificação e do desenvolvimento progressivo do sistema preexistente, a Carta não deixe de vir a inspirar, independentemente do seu valor jurídico, o quadro de valorações da jurisdição comunitária ( 84), e não venha a ter igualmente um efeito de irradiação sobre os demais mecanismos (nacionais e internacionais) de protecção dos direitos fundamentais. (82) Para uma análise orientada neste sentido, cfr., por último, as contribuições recolhidas na obra editada por Philip Alston (com Mara Bustelo e James Heenan), (1999), The EU and Human Rights, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Mas demonstrando algum cepticismo quanto à possibilidade de transformar a problemática dos direitos humanos na razão de ser da União, veja-se Armin von Bogdandy, (2000), «The European Union as a Human Rights Organization? Human Rights at the core of the European Union», Common Market Law Review, v. 37 pp. 1307-1338 e Deirdre Curtin, «The ‘EU Human Rights Charter’ and the Union Legal Order: The ‘Banns’ before the marriage?», in Judicial Review in European Human Law (cit. supra, nota 46), pp. 303-318. (83) Veja-se a propósito, J.H.H. Weiler, (1999), «Fundamental rights and fundamental boundaries: on the conflict of standards and values in the protection of human rights in the european legal space», in The Constitution of Europe, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 102-129. (84) Ve ja-se neste sentido a recente invocação que dela faz o Advogado-Geral Tizzano nas suas conclusões (de 8 de Fevereiro de 2001) (ainda não publicadas) sobre o processo prejudicial C-173/99 [Broadcasting, Entertainment, Cinematographic and Theatre Union (BECTU) contra Secretary of State for Trade and Industry]. A propósito do carácter fundamental do direito a férias pagas (reconhecido no artigo 31.E, 2 da Carta) o Advogado-Geral escreve que embora desprovida, do ponto de vista formal, de valor obrigatório autónomo, não é possível, num litígio que se refira à natureza e ao alcance de um direito fundamental, ignorar os enunciados pertinentes da Carta nem sobretudo a sua vocação evidente para servir, quando as suas disposições o permitam, de parâmetro de referência substancial para todos os autores ) EstadosMembros, instituições, pessoas físicas e morais ) da cena comunitária (ponto 28) (sublinhado nosso). THE TRUTH AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSIONS : A JUSTICE LOOKING ALSO TO FUTURE GENERATIONS ADOLFO CERETTI Associate Professor of Criminology, Faculty of Law, Milano-Bicocca University, Italy; ISSD Assistant-Secretary-General ALBERTO NOSENZO Judge, Milan Court, Italy «the truth must dazzle gradually ... or all the world would be blind» Emily Dickinson 1. The Rights of Future Generations This work of ours sets out to make a contribution – within the sphere of the topic chosen for this Convention, the «Rights of Future Generations» – to the debate on International Criminal Tribunals and Truth and Reconciliation Commissions, which are by many now singled out as being meaningful and effective tools for the management of the periods of transition from an author itarian regime to democratic rule a number of countries go through ( 1). In confronting such a sensitive issue, fraught with social, juridical and philosophical implications, we have decided to privilege the analysis of some theoretical traits typical of the Truth and Reconciliation Commissions, devoting specific attention to the model of justice the Commissions draw inspiration from, that is Restorative Justice. In order to proceed in such a direction it proved first of all necessary to identify the theoretical framework within which any analysis of the Commissions must necessarily be viewed, whilst not losing sight of more general themes such as the meaning and role of historical «truth», the themes of forgiveness and oblivion related to the issue of amnesty, the significance and import of the narrative structure of a collective experience. Such theoretical considerations stem out of the specific experience of a country, South Africa, which opted for reconciliation but a few years ago, (1) The debate has raged, for instance, in Argentina, Cambodia, Chad, Chile, El Salvador, Ethiopia, in Greece after the rule of the Colonels, in Uruguay, in post-Franco Spain, in all Eastern European countries following the fall of the communist regimes. See: Gentili, Lollini, 2000. 202 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions specifically through the setting up of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission (henceforth referred to as «TRC»). In our opinion, the issue of «future generations» is inseparable from that of the Commissions as such. Of course, the work of Commissions is entirely focused on the investigation of the past, on unveiling any violation of human rights and any abuse perpetrated, and does not have the present as its direct object. This undoubtedly stems from the attention – the legitimate attention – paid to the victims of such violations. Yet this is far from being the only goal pursued by a Commission: its attention is also addressed to the future, to the generations following the one that has had to live through a period – long or short that it may be – of violations and abuses. As we will see further on, re-activating the past or memory is a task that is directly related to the issue of the peaceful coexistence of future generations and cannot be based on oblivion of what has been. As the Commission's President Tutu (Tutu, 2000) has repeatedly stated, the Final Report on the TRC's work will take its place in the historical context of which «future generations» will try to make sense. The questions which pose themselves forcibly and spontaneously are the following ones: «Do future generations have any rights?». And: «What is the social milieu in which such rights are to be respected?» These are not merely philosophical speculations, but issues definitely bound to affect decisions in present action. In political philosophy said questions have found answers in the recent debate highlighting a paradoxical difference in opinion between those who believe rights are to be viewed within the context of a community and that only within a community can they be guaranteed (Communitarians), and those, the Liberals, who instead believe that, if the issue is broached seriously, individuals' rights should be made to prevail over the rights of the community. In a period in which welfare had not yet shown its limitations, it was Rawls (Rawls, 1972) among the Liberals, who insisted that it is of the utmost importance to observe how generations are placed in time, and who drew attention to the fact that any actual exchange between generations can take place only in one direction: while we are in a position to do something for the generations to come, they cannot do anything for us. That is, actual exchanges between generations do exist, but they are virtual and always mediated by a present which engages in self-study and self-adjusts in a possibly binding relationship with the future. Generations, their virtual relations and their interplay are nothing more than the world of symbols society consists of. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 203 Resta instead (Resta, 1997) calls attention to the fact that the term generations is complex, paradoxical, inasmuch as generations cannot exist as identitites if not in relation to a difference (other generations). Yet it was once again Rawls, this time in his more recent Political Liberalism (Rawls, 1994), who described society as a system of cooperation (the term to be interpreted – as we have just said – as a stable though virtual link, functional to a common task) over time, from one generation to the next. For the American philosopher, contractarian public ethics are to be set against the notion of society based on the endless interplay of generations, and he goes so far as to state that it is the way of thinking of and viewing society that is opening up. What is changing is the very grammar of viewing. Without espousing Rawls' theories, Resta remarks that nowadays the problems raised by ethics inform us about the limits of the present thus interrupting the soliloquizing temporal dimension of techne, which may be summarised in the expression: «we can do all we can do». This temporal dimension is interrupted when another language – that of ethics, as already said – transforms this soliloquy showing us that the space and time in which our lives unfold are neither unique nor absolute and that the idea of our fellow-beings deserves more attention. Yet, while enabling us to extend our vision to the future, such an approach ambiguously reminds us that the only life we can live is in the present. «As modernity draws to its end, – Resta points out – a subtle fear impels us to adjust our view of society so as to place indiv iduals in relation to a spatially and temporally wider notion of our fellow-beings. The responsibilities are our own but it is future generations we are acountable to; there being no sovereign third-party to enjoin responsibility, responsibility mirrors itelf nakedly in the present, the contemporary» (Resta, 1997, p. 28). As we know, the emergence of such ideas echoes the heuristics of fear, an issue which Jonas has brilliantly dealt with (Jonas, 1984). He warns us that it is the anxiety created by the uncontrollable pace of technological time that creates the need to stop and think. As already stated, it is ethics that interrupts the soliloquy of technology and poses questions on the «imperative of responsibility» which also invests the social system, raising the issue of how another time, that of future generations, relates to the present temporal horizon. But how can one «identify» the rights of future generations? It should be made clear from the very outset that Jonas does not base his «imperative of responsibility» on the traditional idea of rights and duties, the idea grounded upon reciprocity, according to which my duty is the counterpart of another's right, which in turn is seen as the like of my 204 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions own right; so that once certain rights of another are established, then my corresponding duty to respect such rights is established. For Jonas the traditional idea of rights and duties is unsatisfactory. Only what makes claims can have claims – what exists. Every form of life makes a claim to life, but the nonexistent makes no claims and can therefore suffer no violation of its rights: «The claim to existence begins only with existence». Yet Jonas's ethic is concerned precisely with this «not-yet-existent»: his «imperative of responsibility» is, as a matter of fact, independent of any idea of a right and a reciprocity. A right of the unborn to being born (of the ungenerated to generation) is simply not arguable. We are therefore confronted with a duty that is not the counterpart of another's right. Jonas therefore introduces the notion of the duty toward the existence of future mankind and the condition of future progeny, even if no descendants of ours are among them. The duty to care for one's children can be grounded on the factual responsibility of having originated their existence and then, in consequence, upon the right that pertains to these children insofar as existing, the duty toward the existence of future mankind does not call for the thorny task of grounding, since we need not fear the procreative drive may come to an end. More dangers seem to threaten the future condition of mankind. According to Jonas, the problem can be viewed in the following terms: «since there will in any case be later men, who had no say in their coming to exist, they will in their time have the right to accuse us who came before them of being the originators of their misfortune – if we have spoiled for them the world or the human constitution through careless and avoidable deeds. Whereas for their existence they can hold responsible only their immediate begetters (and even there have a right to complain only if the parents’ right to progeny can be questioned on specific grounds), for the conditions of their existence they can hold distant ancestors or, more generally, the originators of these conditions responsible. Thus, from the right of the anticipated being of later subjects there issues for us today, as the causative agents, an answering duty, which makes us responsible to them with those of our deeds whose effective range extends into such dimensions of time, space, and depth» (Jonas, 1984, p. 41) ( 2). (2) All this is not sufficient in the light of Jonas's ethics. His line of reasoning becomes, if anything, even more articulate and sounder, when he points out that ultimately we cannot consult – foreseeing them – our successors' wishes (which can be of our making). What we consult is what they ought to be which is not of our making The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 2. 205 The Phase of Transition and the Role of Truth In the second half of the Twentieth Century, the history of a number of countries was characterised by transition toward democracy after decades of authoritarian, dictatorial and military rule: in Europe, after the end of World War II and the fall of Nazism; still in Europe, but more recently, following the collapse of the Soviet Union; in South America, with opposition to the authoritarian regimes born of the military coups; and finally, in South Africa, following the end of the regime of apartheid (Goldstone, 1996, p. 485; Flores, 1999, p. 7). The path taken by those countries that proved to be capable of managing said transition in a peaceful way is undoubtedly a novelty and a trait peculiar to contemporary history. Where instead the passage, the transition of peoples has resulted in war as in former Yugoslavia or in a number of ex-Soviet Union Republics, this was due to complex causes, mirroring above all the controversial issues of national vindication and ethnical identity. The peaceful transitions, or negotiated revolutions, we have witnessed – the South African one being extremely significant as the country was on the brink of civil war – were as a matter of fact characterised by their non-violent nature, by the insistence on trying to come to a more or less official compromise between the authorities of old times and the movements embodying the new issues. In South Africa, in particular, the choice of a negotiated settlement was favoured by yet another consideration: even if it had resulted in improved living conditions for the black population, a violent clash would have inevitably resulted in an exodus of the whites from the country. And since it is the whites who controlled and control most economic activities, a further consequence would have been an economic crisis it would have taken the country decades to overcome. All this means, therefore, that among the considerations that led to privilege a compromise, there was the convenience of both sides. This approach has led on a number of occasions to an overlapping of the economic and political interests and the values and the socio-cultural and stands above both of us. To make it impossible for our successors to be what they ought to be is the true crime, behind which all frustration of their desires, culpable as it may be, takes second place. This means that it is not so much over the right to happiness of future men we must watch, but over their duty to be truly human, that is over their capacity for this duty, a capacity which we could possibly rob them of with the alchemy of our utopian technology. (Jonas, 1984, p. 42). 206 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions needs of the defeated ruling class with those of the élites representing the new needs, but above all has entailed seeking a solution which would make such co-existence, such overlapping possible. The political sphere was undoubtedly the sphere in which such overlapping was less evident, following the more or less widespread turnover in the ruling class, while said overlapping was more marked in the economic sphere and within those institutions (the army, the magistracy, the higher echelons of the Civil Service) engaged in the research for a compromise and at times playing the role of guarantors of the agreements reached (Flores, 1999). Following a period of conflict, abuse and violation of human rights and leading to the restoration of democracy and the turnover of the politicians in office, negotiated revolution is a very delicate phase which entails a period of reconstruction. The strategic and political role of this phase (and above all of the procedures and the modes chosen to tackle the problem) is indeed that of reconstructing, creating a new understanding of the previous political regime in order both to legitimize the new political system and to delegitimize the old one and its ideology, drawing a lasting picture of past events(3) (Teitel, 2000) (Gentili, Lollini, 2000). If on the one hand all this makes it possible to avoid further armed conflict and the unflagging resistance to change by the old ruling class, on the other hand it must not entail that the price to be paid for a peaceful transition is oblivion of the past. Negotiated revolution does not imply silence on the crimes committed (Flores, 1999). Peaceful transitions, as a matter of fact, imply the need to rediscover the history of the country and the irruption of individual and collective memory in the public debate, that is the need to find out what was so long hidden. In this process of rediscovery, a crucial role is played by the construction of a divided or shared historical identity within the single national realities, the single communities. Of course, the importance of the memory of a recent past cannot be identical in countries which have experienced violations and abuses of human rights often very different the one from the other( 4). That is why, in pursuing this recovery of memory, in (3) «…by creating a realistic perspective of past human rights abuses individual and collective cognitive recovery could be aided by allowing survivors to accept what happened to them and deal with their resultant emotional responses. Importantly, it could also absolve the feelings of guilt and personal causal responsibility that survivors often experience after traumatic events» (Hamber ,1995, p. 2). (4) «New Democracies in Transition. Countries in transition share a number of similarities which include: 1) a shift from totalitarianism to a form of democracy; 2) a legacy of oppression and serious violations of human rights; 3) a fragile government and a precarious unity; 4) a commitment to the attainment of a culture with human The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 207 pursuing its own «historical truth», every country embarks on a course of its own, by means of: a) the passing of political and moral judgements on the key representatives of the past regime; b) the debate on political responsibilities and on the causes of those events which, more than others, have imprinted themselves on collective memory; c) indictment of those responsible for the violations; d) the rediscovery of traditions banned under the authoritarian regime. 2.1. Individual and Collective Truth Mention of memory brings us back to the main central issues of defining «historical truth», in the meaning it is invested with by the experience of the Commissions ( 5). When a country where a Commission has been set up sets out to investigate its history, a dual dimension of truth emerges: - an individual dimension, related to the experience of the individual, which is highly «subjective» and coincides with memory, characterised by the presence of feelings and sensitivity. In this respect, «historical truth» is identified with the subjective perception of facts and events by the individual victim or persecutor; - a collective dimension, this too related to the experience of individuals but seen within the framework of community experience, resulting from the evidence gathered and any investigation carried out in order to reconstruct the historical picture of the violations committed by the past regime (Teitel, 2000; Villa -Vicencio, 2000). It is a truth resulting from a narration involving all the community to rights and a respect for the rule of law; 5) a determination to make it impossible for the past violations to be repeated. Questions confronting these newly emerging democracies include the following: 1) how do emerging democracies deal with past violations of human rights? What measures are desirable and possible for each country’s transition? 2) how do new democracies deal with leaders and other individuals responsible for disappearances, death squads, psychological and physical torture? Where should the line be drawn between those who gave the orders, and those who carried them out? 3) how do new democracies deal with perpetrators who remain part of the public sector, within the new government, security force or as influential public personas? Do they pose a risk to the new democracy? Different countries make different choices in dealing with past violations» (Boraine, 1994, p. 2). (5) Such considerations will prove to be particularly useful when we take a closer look at the setting in which the work done by the TRC is carried out. 208 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions which the narrator belongs, so that the narrator reconstructs his/her truth for the community listening to him/her. But why is collective truth perceived as being so essential for the survivors of a regime? To begin with, because it is attributed a value per se. After generations of denial and lies, a burning, almost obsessional desire arises to know exactly what happened. Victims of torture are often more insistent in asking for the truth than in asking for justice. People who have been tortured do not necessarily and automatically wish their past tormentors to be sentenced and imprisoned. First and foremost they want the truth to be known (Cohen, 2001). This mental mechanism, writes Weschler (quoted in Cohen), is a mysterious, quasi magical mechanism, because often everybody already knows the truth, everybody knows who the torturers were and what they did; the torturers themselves know everybody knows and everybody knows they know. Why, then, this need to make such knowledge explicit? Nagel claims that the answer is to be found in the difference between the notion of knowledge and that of acknowledgement. One has acknowledgement when at last knowledge is officially sanctioned and, in the form of discourse, enters the public sphere (Nagel, 1989). Another question is related to the sensitivity of the victims , above all to the sensitivity of those whose family members and friends have gone missing. Although they might have lost all hope of ever finding their loved ones alive, there is a desperate need to know what has happened to them. The unidentified bodies in common graves require some form of symbolic burial. In one of his speeches, Tutu said: «I recall so vividly how at one of our hearings a mother cried out plaintively, 'Please can't you bring back even just a bone of my child so that I can bury him?». Finally, in order to understand the reasons impelling this quest for the truth, it might be very helpful to bear in mind that the TRC’s Final Report is replete with metaphors relating to the wounds, the indelible scars left by the past in the collective conscience. These scars often hide «still bleeding wounds» which must be reopened to be cleansed and treated. The collective dimension of truth contributes to the success of said operation. 2.2. Reactivating the Past Both individual truth and collective truth are of the utmost importance in the experience of Commissions and testify to the twofold goal they set themselves: on the one hand, individual truth makes it The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 209 possible to focus one's attention on the suffering of the victims, who are given an opportunity to recount their experiences; on the other, collective truth provides us with an overall picture of the violations, a description consisting of a number of individual stories told publicly, thanks to which it proves easier to distance onself, once the attempt to unveil «historical truth», albeit through such an unusual procedure, has been made. What makes the phase of transition so tricky is the fact that one mediates between individual and collective history, between individual and collective responsibilit y, between individual and collective truth. The different levels of truth have different roles and functions, yet they are all equally necessary: if historical and «judicial» investigation aim at a reconstruction and an understanding as «objective» as possible of the causes and consequences of and the responsibilities for the violations committed, personal truth, heard through the accounts of the victims and the perpetrators of the violations, apart from providing individual acknowledgement, leads perpetrators, victims and the communities to which they belong to take part in the shaping of a common memory and identity, by sharing and collating individual experiences. In such a perspective, the reactivation of a memory of a shared past helps take the first steps towards the recognition and acceptance of the others and respect for them (Toscano, 2000, p. 44), above all if such a process is invested with the political purpose of highlighting and helping identify the ties and bonds the two sides have, rather than the reasons for division and juxtaposition. The meaning attributed to the symbolic lieux of this reconstruction of individual and collective truth is that of creating a moment of transition from looking back to looking forward: «the revealed truth brings on the switch from the tragic past to the promise of a hopeful future» (Teitel, 2000); reactivating the past means – in this perspective – also indicating the possibility for political and social change: a) by helping to attribute individual responsibilities, thus avoiding the imposition of collective responsibilities on groups of an ethnic or religious or other nature. This way, on the one hand one limits the risk that hatred and lust for revenge might have repercussions on a group as a whole, on the other one seeks to ascertain individual responsibilities. This, of course, does not mean playing down any collective or institutional political and historical responsibilities nor does it mean the acceptance of «exemplary» trials against individuals. Indeed, reconstructing the nature and extent of the crimes makes it possible to unveil systematic and institutional patterns of gross violation of human rights or the involvement or 210 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions acquiescence of large social, political or cultural groups; this kind of truth-seeking can help identify and demolish the mechanisms, the patterns of behaviour and the institutions responsible for the prolonging of the violations (Goldstone, 1996, p. 488; Calzini, 2000); b) by reconstructing and revealing what happened. This comes to constitute a form of official and public recognition for the victims, which certainly represents a first step towards reparation and reconciliation; c) finally, by offering an opening to the issue of forgiveness – an issue which we will discuss further on, but which it is necessary to examine when having to decide if it is best to reactivate memory or allow oblivion to prevail. In reality, the two paths, memory and oblivion of «historical truth», are not necessarily antithetical; the issue can instead be dealt with differently by considering, side by side with «historical truth», the possible effects of the revelation and transmission of a «narrative» truth, which has a lot to do with storytelling. On examining the issue from this point of view, Bettini (Bettini, 2000) considers the two alternatives of oblivion of the past and recollection as both essential for the shaping of a memory, which is also a «unifying» collective identity. In such a perspective, memory privileges the transmission of «what unites» and decides to set aside «what has divided»; a choice, this, which favours a collective identity based on recognition of the fact that all the parties involved have a common history. It has been said by many, and first and foremost by the TRC promoters, that what is at stake here is the production of a new collective identity, through the reconstruction of a common memory and a shared vision of the past. Though not wishing to deal with the complex issue of identity( 6), we believe that (6) As for the complex and controversial issue of a collective group identity, we shall here provide but a brief outline of the theoretical and philosophical framework within which the Commissions are to be viewed. We shall therefore simply report a few interesting remarks: «Psychology, sociology and history agree in defining identity as an inalienable requirement not only for individual psychological well-being, but for social cohesion and joint action. Yet, in the course of the last decade of the twentieth-century, we witnessed hideous atrocities perpetrated and justified on the grounds of an unconditional and violent affirmation of a group identity: from genocide in Rwanda to ethnic cleansing in former Yugoslavia. But what should we then make – both from the political and the ethical point of view – of the issue of identity? the «nationalists» have recourse to the semantical trick of distinguishing between «patriotism» (their own) and «nationalism» (that of the others). Just as schematic is the reply of the The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 211 the interweaving of narratives and hearings, of explicit recollections and oblivion, rather than the birth of a collective identity constitutes – though less ambitiously – an opportunity for the healing of the statement-givers, making it possible to add details to the truth to be shared and to start building pathways to mutual recognition and reconciliation, by attaching importance to individual experiences (7). 3. Judicial Truth and Historical Truth Emphasizing the individual and collective dimension of truth cannot excuse us from analysing, albeit briefly, also other notions of truth, undoubtedly more deeply rooted in our heritage and which we have recently mentioned: judicial truth and historical truth. When analysing the latter concepts – as we will clearly see further on – we are far removed from the notions of truth (individual-narrative, collective-social and restorative) elaborated by the Commissions (8). Nevertheless, we must briefly examine them if we are: a) to reason on the choices made by the other model, that of «victors' justice» which we will deal with, though not at length; ( 9) b) to understand, through juxtaposition, the deeper meaning of the work carried out by the Commissions. 3.1. Historical Truth That history, law and trials are strictly interrelated is a known fact. In such a context the notion of «historical truth» takes on a meaning – let us reaffirm it clearly, though we run the risk of seeming to «cosmopolitans», of those who hold that belonging to a common mankind allows for no distinctions or specific identities, which are viewed as being both artificial and conflictual… Let us therefore start by saying that at the root of any group identity there is a cultural artefact, an intellectual construction elaborated by élites defined as «professional producers of subjective visions of the social world»… Failing all objective and verifiable support to the definition of group identities, one has recourse to what has been called «the invention of tradition», to the creation of «imaginary communities», to the elaboration of a «founding myth». Thus we go from speculations about the hypothetical nature of group identity to actual political construction», Toscano (2000), pp. 22-24. (7) See infra § 5.2. (8) See infra § 5.2. (9) See infra § 4.1. 212 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions be pedantic – altogether different from that attributed to it by the experience of the Commissions (10). As Ricoeur points out (Ricoeur, 2000), the specific roles of the historian and of the judge impose on both the need to confront themselves with the issues of truth and justice, with regard to which they undertake, as it were, to be impartial, given the role of «third party» taken on (and attributed to them) in the social consortium ( 11). It is Ginzburg, in an epoch-making essay, Il giudice e lo storico (The judge and the historian, Ginzburg, 1991), who reminds us that after a series of changes late Nineteenth-Century political historiograhy took on – or, rather, claimed it was taking on – a judiciary physiognomy. Carefully assessing evidence, witnesses' accounts and documents meant (10) See supra § 2.1 and infra § 5.2. It is understood that such third-partiness is not "absolute", but is constantly redefined within the mobile confines traced from the outside by the level of critical attention devoted by a given social system to the themes of truth and justice . Ricoeur (Ricoeur, 2000) reminds us that an important consideration on impartiality as a moral intellectual virtue common to anyone aspiring to the function of "third party" has been offered by Nagel, (Nagel, Italian translation, 1993, p. 23) where he affirms that the most conspicuous part of our experience of the world and of our wishes belongs to our individual points of view: it is from such individual points of view, as it were, that we see things. Nonetheless we are capable of thinking of the world also detaching ourselves from the specific position we occupy in it and even from the kind of people we are. It is also possible to detach onself from the contingences of the self in a far more radical manner (...). Each of us embarks on reflection starting from a complex of worries, wishes and interests and each of us is capable of recognising what is also true for the others. We can therefore detach ourselves from the thought of the specific position we occupy in the world and think simply about all those people, without distinguishing as self what we happen to be. Like Nagel and Ricoeur we define as impersonal this point of view, which is a sort of non-point of view. It is both epistemological and moral and could be defined in this respect as an «intellectual virtue». The epistemological aspect is related to the split within the point of view, while the moral one concerns the implicit affirmation of the equal value and dignity of points of view. As Nagel says, at first the basic intuition emerging from the impersonal point of view is that everybody's life is important and that nobody is more important than the others. He also claims that we should live as if we were actually guided by a kind-hearted impartial onlooker from a world in which we are nothing more than an individual among billions of other individuals. (Nagel, Italian translation, 1993, p. 25). The question spontaneously arising and which – of course – we leave open also after the pages that follow is: "To what extent do the historian and the judge meet this need for impartiality inscribed in their professional codes of conduct and what role do social and political forces play in such a context?". (11) The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 213 for the historian of that day and age (12) focussing on the events (be they political, military, etc.) which could be taken to result from the actions of one or more individuals; in doing so, the historian stood above disputes, not viewing as relevant all those phenomena that did not call for explanation (for example the history of social groups, of outlook, etc.). In the following years, the massive cultural impact on experts in the field exerted by the review Annales d’histoire économique et sociale, founded in 1929 by Bloch and Febvre, and the ensuing loss of interest in the histoire événementielle, led those who were confronted with the dilemma if the historian was to judge or understand, to opt for the second alternative, thus renouncing any attempt to interpret the State's superior reasons. Nowadays, according to Ginzburg, further enriching the range of existing explanations, there is a growing intolerance by historians towards the notion of «evidence», a term which – instead – used to justify the analogy between the work of the historian and that of the judge. For many a historian such a notion is outmoded (like that of truth), while far more credit is given, also overseas, to the notion of representation( 13). But doesn't setting aside the notions of truth and evidence eventually produce a sad brand of skepticism? Ginzburg's opinion is in this respect categorical: the notions of truth and evidence are essential elements of the historian's trade, as also evinced from the fact that the historian is entitled to raise doubts also where a judge would enter a nonsuit. Paradoxically, it is this difference that brings out the element common to the trades of judge and historian: the use of evidence, that is. In any case, if it not possible here to deal with the issue, if not through a few occasional cultural references, likewise we can do nothing more when turning our attention to another highly controversial issue: that of judicial truth. (12) Ginzburg quotes as ad hoc example the address given by Lord Acton in 1895 on the occasion of his appointment as Regius Professor of Modern History at Cambridge University. (13) When one speaks of representations the sources (be they in writing or figurative) – as Ginzburg explains – are analysed inasmuch as sources relating to themselves (how they were constructed), inasmuch as evidence of social representations and not as sources for what they discuss (Ginzburg, 1991, p. 12). 214 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 3.2. Judicial truth On the theme of judicial truth, Ferrajoli (Ferrajoli, 1989) ( 14) has written pages we cannot overlook. What a criminal judge ascertains and declares to be «true» – unlike the truth ascertained and declared by the Commissions – is related to the analysis of the meaning of the predicate «true» associated with the propositions motivating a judicial ruling. «If on a theoretical level one may admit that ‘truth is in the facts’ – writes Ubertis, one of the most important Italian experts on these matters – in trials, where truth -seeking is irrenounceable (…), one cannot do anything more than ascertain ‘the truth of a proposition’: what has to be verified, therefore, is not a ‘fact’ but a ‘statement’» (Ubertis, 1993, p. 58) ( 15). Let us take as a starting point a proposition such as: «So-and-so has (or has not) committed the fact denoted by law as an offence»; Ferrajoli specifies that such a proposition can itself be broken down into two propositions: one factual or de facto (the truth of which can be ascertained by proving the fact took place), the other judicial or legal (the truth of which is judicial, in as much as it can be ascertained by means of the interpretation of the meaning of the legal provisions classifying the event as an offence) (Ferrajoli, 1989, p. 21). Such interpretation: a) offers the advantage of partially re-defining the intuitive notion of truth as «correspondence» (that is, the notion enclosed in the Enlightment ideal viewing jurisdiction as mere «verification of the event» and «mouthpiece of the law»), establishing that the term «true» can be employed without any metaphysical implications; asserts that the term «true» designates here only conformity or difformity from jurisdictional propositions ( 16); b) defines judicial truth not as «absolute», «objective» but «relative», «approximate» in relation to the principle of «perfect (14) See above all the chapter titled Cognitivismo o decisionismo (Cognitivism or Decision-making), pp. 5-45. (15) UBERTIS instead quotes FRANCESCO CARRARA, Programma del corso di diritto criminale (Syllabus of the criminal law course). Parte generale , III, Prato, 1886, § 900, p. 201. (16) «Both the conditions for the use of the term ‘true’ and the conditions required to assert that a judicial hypothesis is true are not independent of the way in which the legal system with reference to which judicial truth can be proclaimed is formed» (FERRAJOLI, 1989, p. 24). The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 215 correspondence», which becomes a «regulatory principle» or an «extreme model» in jurisdiction. It is in this interplay of reasons, that makes of judicial truth an «approximate» truth that we can trace, in Ferrajoli's ideas, some interesting analogies and differences between the work of the judge and that of the historian, above all because judicial truth cannot be affirmed, like historical truth, on the grounds of direct observation. As a matter of fact: a) «Factual judicial truth is a peculiar form of «historical truth», related to propositions relating to past events, and as such not directly accessible to experience…» (Ferrajoli, 1989, p. 24); b) juridical judicial truth is instead a truth we might term classifying, inasmuch as it qualifies accepted historical facts on the grounds of the categories supplied by legal jargon and processed through the interpretation of legal language. Given these premises, if we confront the stritctly interrelated issues of verifications and verificability of the judicial propositions drawn up by the judge, we will notice they are strictly related to the issues the historian must deal with: a) the truth of factual verifications can be enounced only on the grounds of the «effects» produced, that is on the «signs of pastness» traced in the present in relation to past events. Like the historian, then, the judge cannot examine the fact, which eludes the direct observation of the one as of the other, but only evidence of the fact, which with Ubertis we define as «that mechanism, that complex of elements and activities having the function of consenting the ascertainment of the truthfulness or untruthfulness of one of the factual enunciations integrating the thema probandum» (Ubertis, 1979, pp. 89-90). It follows that both «factual judicial truth» and «historical truth» «result from an inference of the proven facts of the past from the probatory facts of the present … the premise including a description of the event to be explained and of the evidence provided and… in its conclusion the enunciation of the event which ones assumes has been proved by the premises and which equates to a possible explanation of said events» (Ferrajoli, 1989, p. 26) ( 17); (17) «The task of judicial enquiry is to eliminate dilemma in favour of the simpler hypothesis, the one endowed with more explicatory powers and, above all, compatible with most of the evidence and knowledge previously acquired.» (Ferrajoli, 1989, p. 24). 216 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions b) judicial verification is also the result of an inference: here too there is no direct observation of the events but a reasoning – termed «subsumption» – consisting in a classifying procedure based on deduction( 18). Moreover, just as the historian is necessarily selective in his construction, inevitably swayed by historiographical interests, points of view and interpretative hypotheses, the subjectivity of the judge also massively impacts on the judicial enquiry( 19), which is all the more serious because while historiography is capable of self-correction, for the judge a judicial mistake is never fecund. In some respects, therefore, there seems to be an overlapping of the figures of the judge and of the historian. It should be added, however – and Ferrajoli would certainly agree with us – that such overlapping is to be viewed with mistrust and perplexity: as a matter of fact, it is already on the «… level of the language that the historian must be careful not to reduce himself to the kind of language a judge uses, nor must he use the same concepts, methods or, even worse, set himself the same goals» (Flores, 2000). Let us consider by way of example that, following Pinochet's return to Chile, Antonio Cassese, formerly Chairman of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Jugoslavia, recommended that, so that the past should not be forgotten, a criminal trial be started, in the course of which historical facts could be gathered and viewed through rigorous examination and evaluation procedures. This is, as a matter of fact, a statement which might be derived from the delusion of establishing together both «judicial truth» and «historical truth», or of the fallacy that the two truths may be exchangeable. Instead, unlike justice, history cannot boast any «official vestals» capable of coming up with a fitting close (judicial truth) to the events under examination; history is necessarily the subject of verification and revision, and its canons are more ambiguous than those of criminal justice (Flores, 2000). Such ideas have been successfully dealt with by Ricoeur (Ricoeur, 2000), who calls attention to the fact that what creates a marked difference between the judicial approach and the historiographical one – especially when it is the same facts that are being «judged» – is above all (18) It must, however, be clarified that subsumption is only distinguished from the ascertainment of fact from a logical and practical point of view, while the rule of the law transcendentally influences the judges' operational language and also his approach to the facts to be judged. (19) See retro § 3.1, and footnote No. 11. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 217 the ruling , inasmuch as the event upon which judgement has been passed with an irrevocable ruling can only be challenged by public opinion, but cannot become the subject of a new impugnation, save for review, which Garapon, however, rightly termed «a single -shot weapon». That is: non bis in idem. In other words, the judge must reach a conclusion, he cannot deny justice: he «must» decide in order to avoid that others should decide, by having recourse to other codes. The law states that his decisions «have to be», and once the communication network has been activated – for the most diverse reasons – in its communicative mechanism, the same law states which la nguages shall be relevant. It is Resta who reminds us: (Resta, 1996, p. 301): «One cannot decide by having recourse to other codes because the law explicitly lays it down that one cannot decide by having recourse to other codes: say the ethical or economic code... which does not mean that all these codes are not relevant, indeed they always are, but only under the conditions to which the law recognizes relevance». The judge, therefore, must conclude, he/she must re-establish a correct distance between the defendant and the victim, by relying on a basically binary logic: the defendant is either guilty or is not guilty. The historian cannot carry out such functions nor does he wish to do so. If he falls prey to the temptation to take on the role of «historical judge» – Ricoeur points out (Ricoeur, 2000) – the price he will have to pay will be that of acknowledging he has expressed a partial, militant view. But apart from this specific instance, it is the opening itself to the possibility of revisitation by the scientific community of historians that marks the difference between historical evaluation – as such always temporary – and a final judicial sentence. A further specific difference between historical and judicial enquiry is that the latter extends to include new sources of evidence (interrogations, witness accounts, confrontation, experts' opinions). As Ferrajoli bluntly puts it: «A trial is, as it were, the only instance of ‘historiographical experimentation’: in a trial sources are made to intervene de vivo, not only because they are acquired directly, but also because they are confronted the one with the other, undergo crossexamination and are made to reproduce, as in psychodrama, the events being judged» (Ferrajoli, 1989, p. 32). All this goes to prove that in trials – unlike what happens in historical investigation – the final decision derives from the active working of the dialectics engaged in by the parties, and not only from the acknowledgement of external reality. The fairness of the sentence stems 218 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions above all from the work done to reach such a decision, so much so that any elements gathered violating the rules disciplining cross-examination cannot contribute to the shaping of the judge's ruling, consisting as they do of limitations of the right to defend oneself and ways of eluding rules meant to protect defendants' rights (Ubertis, 1993). Any evidence gathered violating said principles cannot be used. Such limitations do not bother the historian. 4. The International Experience of Countries in Transition The above considerations on subjective-individual-narrative «truth» and on collective-social-community «truth» represent the theoretical premises to understand the reasons for that kind of agreement we have already designated with the term negotiated revolution, a mechanism privileging different objectives from the classical one of the punishment of the perpetrators («victors' justice» ( 20)) as it privileges the search for «judicial truth.» Anyway, the problem common to all the countries engaged in the transition towards democracy following a period of repression and human rights violations is that of deciding how to deal with their past and by which institutional means (Garrett, 2000): one the one hand, the problem is that of how to relate to the old ruling class responsible for terrible abuses; on the other, the perplexities concern the victims of said violations. At present, the possible tools to which one may have recourse in order to reconstruct truth (both collective and individual) and promote the re-activation of memory are therefore multifold, just like those one may have recourse to when assigning responsibility. From the politicaldiplomatic point of view one uses the symbolic term of post-conflict peace building to refer to all the tools aimed at the reconstruction of a social fabric making for mutual understanding and for co-existence after periods of strife and violence (Toscano, 2000, p. 43). Juxtaposed to the model created in Latin America after the end of the military dictatorships and in South Africa (Truth Commissions; see Schey, 1997, p. 332) there is the Nuremberg model (Taylor, Italian (20) «Victors' justice», which we will deal with more at length in § 4.1, can coexist with «negotiated revolution», provided application of said mechanism alongside the judicial is foreseen. Let us take, by way of an example, the South African experience. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 219 translation, 1993) – historically older and defined as «victors' justice»; there is also that opted for by Central and Eastern Europe following the fall of communist regimes (Lustration Mechanism( 21)), and a further model was chosen to deal with the crimes committed during the conflict in former Yugoslavia (International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia). Given the variety of possible options, the path taken by the Truth and Reconciliation Commissions differs from that taken by the Criminal National and International Tribunals. It must be added that, apart from the historical and political reasons for the negotiations conducted in the single countries and apart from the objections and perplexities a solution of compromise can often arouse, (22) by now it is being insistently asked that international codifications should foresee, in the perspective of Restorative Justice, mechanisms other than international criminal trials. More specifically, it is being asked that enquiry Commissions, both national and non-national, be set up, that the perpetrators be removed from office, that the victims receive reparation and that counselling be provided for them (Bassiouni, 2000). But before discussing these new experiences more at length, we wish to recall, even if not in detail, the principles on which «victors' justice» is based, which basically calls for judicial truth-seeking. (21) See infra § 4.2. On the other hand, a critical reading has been given for the viable models in periods of transition (Commissions and International Criminal Tribunals) setting against the incredibly high number of victims caused by conflicts of a non-international nature (internal conflicts and dictatorial regimes provoked in the past century 170 million victims – 86 million of which after World War II –, while over the same period the number of victims of armed conflict between nations was of thirty-three million; see the research figures reported in Bassiouni, 2000, p. 17) the number of acknowledgements of responsibility, which is too low even to be termed symbolic. But then: «the question arises as to why there have been so few instances of prosecution and other accountability mechanisms» (Bassiouni, 2000, 18; Bassiouni, 1996). The reason for this is to be found in the research for compromise typical of negotiated revolutions: «The answer is that justice is all too frequently bartered away for political settlements. Whether in international, non-international or purely internal conflicts, the practice of impunity has become the political price paid to secure an end to the violence of ongoing conflicts, or as a means to ensure tyrannical regime changes. In these bartered settlements, the victims’ rights become the objects of political trade-off, and justice becomes the victim of Realpolitik… in order to obtain peace, negotiations must be held with the very leaders who frequently are the ones who committed, ordered, or allowed atrocious crimes to be committed. Thus, the choice presented to negotiators is whether to have peace or justice» (Bassiouni, 2000, p. 18). (22) 220 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 4.1. The Judicial Path: Criminal National and International Tribunals The model of the Criminal National and International Tribunals has its historical and cultural roots in the Nuremberg and Tokyo trials, which in turn look back to the trials celebrated after World War I. In the Nuremberg trial, the punishment of Nazi criminals was made possible thanks to the application of «victors' justice», a formula used to refer to the most critical aspect of this model, that is to the fact that the Military International Tribunals judged exclusively the crimes and the violations committed by the higher echelons of the Nazi hierarchy, and not, instead, the crimes committed by the allies. Suffice it here to recall but an example: at Nuremberg, the act of indictment did not contemplate the German bombings with the V1s and the V2s simply because in 1942 the allies themselves had decided to raze to the ground the German towns, regardless of their strategic importance in the military field (see AlfredMaurice de Zayas, Italian translation, 1996, p. 112). Although the Court (whose Statutes, enclosed to the London agreement, contained the most important legal provisions) was set up as an International Court, as a matter of fact it might be better defined as an Inter-allies Occupation Tribunal, as Germany had not accepted the creation of a supranational body. The Tribunal was an institution based on an agreement against a third party. And as a matter of fact, the Nazi defence-lawyers raised as a first objection, then overruled by the Court, that of its incompetence through lack of jurisdiction (Alfred-Maurice de Zayas, Italian translation, 1996). All this reminds us of what is now happening before the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia, where, upon the opening of the trial for genocide and human rights violation against Slobodan Milosevic, former President of the Yugoslav Republic, Milosevic challenged the legitimacy of the institution of an ad hoc Tribunal with arguments partially re-echoing those used in Nuremberg, which goes to prove that to this day a number of knots remain to be untied – though the issue was partially dealt with in Rome in 1998, with the approval of the Statutes of the International Criminal Court (Balboni, 2000). It is also true, however, that the Nuremberg model, whilst embodying «victors' justice», also helped provide a definition of the category of international crimes. If we have now created an International Criminal Court (although ratification of the agreements is likely to take quite long), it is because an international consensus has been reached as to what is meant by international crime and people at large have been The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 221 sensitized to the problem (Calzini, 2000), which is a long-term effect of Nuremberg. In other words, what was then held to be extraordinary is now viewed as «normal» (Teitel, 2000). Also the positive experiences of the ad hoc International Criminal Courts partially find their origins in the paradigm of «victors' justice». Apart from the above-mentioned institutional subjects, who have to a greater or lesser extent been legitimated by that experience, also the legal classification of crimes adopted in Nuremberg – crimes against peace, war crimes and crimes against humanity( 23) (see Alfred-Maurice de Zayas, Italian translation, 1996) – helped international lawyers start to think about and work on the issue, thus leading to the approval of a number of UN conventions. If the Nuremberg experience proved to be decisive in developing modern sensitivity to the issue of international criminal responsibility, it is also true that «victors' justice», fifty years after its most complete historical manifestation has – inevitably – come in for a lot of criticism. If one temporarily overlooks their symbolic significance and their capacity to embody a desire for punishment or retaliation, the choice of a judicial trial, the desire to seek a judicial truth( 24), – the application of the principle of «victor's justice» –, have left a number of unresolved issues. As a matter of fact,: - the number of perpetrators found guilty has been so low as to prove meaningless in spite of the legal provisions and political intentions which often had as their avowed aim that of bringing to justice large groups of people; ( 25) (23) Crimes against peace: the planning, preparation, waging of a war of aggression or of a war declared in violation of international agreements, treaties or warranties, or participation in a joint project or plot with a view to carrying out any of the above listed acts. Crimes against war: violation of war laws or customs. Crimes against humanity: murder, extermination, subjection, deportation or other inhuman acts, committed against civilians before or during a war, persecution on political, racial or religious grounds indulged in while committing one of the offences or in relation to one of the offences over which the Court has jurisdiction. (24) See retro § 3.2 (25) On the other hand, « it would be naive to expect proceedings instituted by the winners to be characterised by some form of legal fundamentalism, of extreme widespread coherence in prosecuting all the people against whom large amounts of evidence have been amassed. Even the staunchest supporters of drastic purges and non ordinary judicial proceedings engaged in with the utmost efficacy could not eacape the political imperative to establish limits to prevent the legal proceedings becoming counterproductive and dangerous for the stability of the new democratic institutions... 222 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions - the victims have received no recognition and, indeed, have publicly declared they felt excluded from the procedures of reconstruction following the violations suffered; - the persecutors, instead, have often felt unjustly indicted for facts they had often committed in complicity with large segments of the communities they belonged to; - the community has been apparently pacified but a number of divisions and misunderstandings deriving from the absence of a process of reconstruction and the shaping of a common identity through the seeking of a shared «historical truth» persist – divisions which have periodically surfaced as resentment and lust for revenge (Llewellyn-Howse, 1999, p. 358; Flores, 1999). Anyway, everytime the judicial approach and «victors' justice» are taken to be viable solutions, they will inevitably place at the very heart of the public debate the persecutors and their judges (Joinet, 1997), whilst at the same time denying room for the victims' deeper needs, such as the right to actively contribute to the reconstruction of the historical-collective dimension of truth, the right to reparation. The considerations made for the International Criminal Courts also apply to the choice of opting for the judicial approach with the celebration of domestic criminal trials; indeed, in such an instance, the doubts as to the advisability for countries in transition to embark on such a path are even greater. Apart from the unsettled issues listed above, the fact that the task of restoring justice is delegated in such cases to that same magistracy who administred justice in the years of the dictatorship is a factor which – coupled with the lengthy proceedings and the difficulty of dealing with the high number of complaints filed – contributes greatly to frustrating and dashing the high hopes set on «victor’s'' justice». Such perplexity, after fifty years, is still felt in Italy when one considers the period immediately following the end of World War II, characterized by the institution of an incredibly high number of judicial proceedings against Fascist regime representatives. Historical records prove that, following the impressive number of complaints filed as soon as the According to the law, the number of potential culprits has always been far larger than the number of defendants actually standing for trial. Whether this was due to inability in conducting inestigations, an arbitrary or a political choice is, all things considered, of little relevance and everywhere victims have protested against the impossibility to prosecute the culprits ... while the persecutors have declared themselves to be they too victims of excessive and prolonged persecution» (Flores, 1999, p. 23). The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 223 hostilities came to an end, the early proceedings embarked upon led to very severe sentences, but that sentences grew milder and milder, eventually leading to a deluge of acquittals and anulments following the June 1946 amnesty – the result, from the judicial point of view, of the tendency to acquit inaugurated by the Court of Cassation ( 26). Given the nature of our work, we are not in a position to discuss Italian history following the fall of Fascism in detail; what can be said is that the harsh criticism levelled already at the time at the judicial approach which was adopted in the transitional phase still holds true (Crainz, 2000). Failure to reactivate memory at that given time in history mirrors itself in a debate still raging in which the failure to understand a number of episodes of violence of the day is still sadly felt ( 27). 4.2. National Lustration Mechanisms and Civil Remedies Before going on to discuss the Commission model, we would like to briefly consider two other tools: the Lustration Mechanisms and Civil Remedies. Lustration Mechanisms are part of a purging process, adopted above all in the former communist countries, whereby individuals who supported or participated in violations committed by a prior regime may be removed from the position still occupied and barred from positions of authority or elective positions. These are political sanctions of which it has been said they risk affecting whole classes or groups of people without accounting for individual responsibilities (Ellis, 1996; Bassiouni, 2000; Boraine, 1994). Such measures were not taken into account in the TRC experience. (26) Of the hundreds of death sentences meted out about ninety were carried out, while about 770 were carried out in France over the same period (Crainz, 2000). (27) An interesting reconstruction of the different phases of this debate identifies three particularly interesting moments: «a) The first critical su mming-up belongs to the immediate post-war period and came even before the formal conclusion of the legal proceedings (…) b) The second moment of interest coincided with the thirtieth anniversary of the liberation (…) c) Finally a third wave of interest was recorded in the nineties (…) in a perspective which we might term «global», including, that is, both the actions directly ascribable to the parties involved and those decided on the grounds of contradictory laws and therefore born of the workings both of administrative purges and criminal justice(…) Looking back on those years, one now tends to privilege the single episode, the event, and around it to elaborate an account centering on the human beings involved and on the uncertain watershed the memory is always confronted with on the occasion of an act of violence between truth and justice, guilt and innocence, the accuser and the accused, lust for revenge and legal codes» (Salvati, 2001, pp. 141-142). 224 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions The option of civil suits includes, instead, the right of victims and of their heirs to start a lawsuit to obtain protection, including economic damages, as the result of an individual or group claim. 4.3. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions The paradigm inspiring traditional criminal proceedings stands in juxtaposition to that of the Truth and Reconciliation Commissions, ( 28) viewed not necessarily as an alternative to, but possibly as a way of integrating the former. To begin with, Commissions may occasionally not be aimed at the twofold purpose of Truth and Reconciliation; at times indeed they are only Truth Commissions, when they resemble more closely traditional enquiry commissions than the kind of commission we are about to discuss, that is Commissions also foreseeing reconciliation among their goals. Such a goal obviously impacts on the activity of the Commission, starting from the planning of the work to be done to the way victim hearings are conducted, from the response to persecutors to the drawing up of a final report. As a rule, Commissions symbolically represent «bridges» between the past and the future and are perceived by the collectivity at large as tools capable of helping us interpret the changes taking place and of representing a turning-point and a fresh start as compared to the previous power structure (Goldstone, 1996, p. 493). As regards the way of interpreting the transitional phase, it is still necessary to remember that, even if the hope expressed when a Commission is set up is that it may reduce the likelihood of such atrocities and abuses being repeated, the Commission's work will impact only indirectly on future political choices, investigation centering instead on past violations. Yet a new political line-up may view the work done as a meaningful and, in a certain sense, community-shared startingpoint to promote policies more attentive to and more respectful of human rights (Hainer, 1994, p.608; Hamber, 1995). The work of a Commission can, however, even more directly contribute to reducing the risk of new abuses if among the tasks it is attributed there is also that of submitting recommendations and proposals for reform to the new institutions, or of identifying support measures for the victims who have testified (Hayner, 1994, p. 609). The final reports of some Commissions, for example, (and among them the TRC's Final Report) included recommendations of this kind and raised issues such as: - the consolidation of new democratic institutions; (28) See list of Truth Commissions sub Schedule 1. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 225 - the reform of military apparatuses; - the reform of police apparatuses and of the legal system; - the introduction of measures for the promotion of national reconciliation; the introduction of reparation measures for the victims of violations and abuses. It is however true that often such recommendations are not foreseen as binding for the new institutions. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions are, therefore, technically speaking, institutions created to investigate a past of human rights violations at the international, national or regional level. Although each Commission presents peculiar traits, all of them are born from the dynamics of transition here above described and generally set themselves similar objectives: - reparation for the victims; - the reconstruction of the historical-collective dimension of the violations; - community involvement in a reconciliation project; - the involvement of the authors of the violations in a project of disclosure and awareness of their individual responsibilities (Allen, 1999, p. 315). As affirmed by Archbishop Desmond Tutu when speaking of the TRC, the issue of restoration takes on a central function in the experience of the Commissions which is inspired to Restorative Justice in relation to which the interests and needs both of the perpetrators and the victims become the central and main consideration (Gentili, Lollini, 2000). Unlike «victors' justice», Restorative Justice promotes reintegration into society of the perpetrators, posing this requirement on the same level of importance as the healing of victims through recognition of their suffering. It is not possible here to examine at length the issues co-occuring in Restorative Justice (Ceretti, Mannozzi, 2000), a term employed to describe a phenomenon which is very wide in scope and with a content which is multidirectional. Zher, in fact, defines Restorative Justice as a model of justice which «involves the victim, the offender and the community in a search for solutions which promote repair, reconciliation and reassurance» (Zehr, 1990, p. 181). Similarly, Wright sees it as avoiding that one ill be added to another (suffering the imposition of the punishment added to the suffering caused by the offence), in order to devote every possible effort to the real protection of the victims through a process of reparation (Wright, 1991, p. 112). The most commonly accepted definition of Restorative Justice is the one proposed by Marshall: «Restorative Justice is a process whereby all the parties with a stake in a particular offence come together 226 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions to resolve collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offence and its implications for the future» (Marshall, 1999, p. 7). 4.3.1. The Commission's constituting elements In spite of the wide range of possible options – after all they are institutions influenced both by the historical and political climate in which they are set up and by the groups which in the transition phase manage to exercise a greater decision-making power – the Truth and Reconciliation Commissions refer to a model including the following characteristics: - the activity of the Commission focuses on the past, while it does not investigate the respect of human rights in the period in which it is set up; - the attention of the Commission is not addressed to a specific event, but to the reconstruction of an overall picture of the abuses and violations of human rights recorded in a given period of time defined when the Commission is set up; - the Commission, which is given a temporarily predefined mandate, ceases to exist when a final report containing the outcome of the investigation and any recommendations is submitted; - the Commission must have the necessary autonomy to access essential information and to carry out the investigations needed for the historical reconstruction of events; said autonomy can vary significantly; - uncertain is the aspect referring to the extent of the Commission's mandate. As a rule, there seems to be agreement that the terms of the mandate should be sufficiently ample and flexible, so as to make it possible to investigate all forms of abuse, allowing for a certain degree of autonomy which will enable it to identify the most significant cases or appropriate procedures (Hainer, 1996, p. 179). Many Commissions have operated within a very rigid and limited mandate; (29) (29) A problem that has arisen as to the extent of a Commission's mandate is whether the final report should include an analysis of the role of the international actors involved in the internal conflict. At almost all times, as a matter of fact, in the course of an internal conflict, there are relevant pressures and intrusion by foreign governments. The role of such «indirect actors», should be acknowledged and investigated, especially when there have been violations of human rights and such external interference has contributed to prolonging the conflict. But most Commissions have not investigated the international context nor have they reported any investigations of this kind in their final reports. (Hainer, 1996). The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 227 - there is widespread and heated debate about the advisability for a Commission to disclose the names of those responsible for gross violations of human rights (Gentili, Lollini, 2000). The choice of the one or the other option has to take into account two opposing principles: on the one hand the due process principle, which establishes, among other things, that everybody is entitled to defend himself/herself in the course of a trial before being declared to have been responsible for the violations – a principle which would be violated if the Commission's report were to disclose the names of the persecutors without giving them a chance to defend themselves; on the other hand the truth principle, according to which making the whole truth known implies disclosing the names of the people responsible for the violations, once their guilt has been proved beyond all reasonable doubt( 30). Above all, the description of the main features of the Commissions makes it possible to highlight an onthological difference between this paradigm and the judicial one. Trials before the Criminal National and International Tribunals can no doubt contribute to demonstrate the extent and the seriousness of the violations and the abuses committed. The fact remains that judicial enquiry focuses on the specific actions of single individuals, without setting itself the goal – in our opinion irrenounceable – of investigating and bringing to public attention the whole picture of the violations. Indeed, to think, as a matter of fact, that a trial can address this need means deluding oneself – as already hinted when speaking of Pinochet's Chile – that one can reach both judicial and historical truth. Given these premises, the reconstruction of the past could be left exclusively to the Commissions, thus avoiding the risk that the Tribunals might – even if indirectly – be attributed a function alien to their competences and which may be potentially dangerous given their essential duty to guarantee the impartiality, objectivity and non exemplary nature of the trial. In reality, one cannot rule out that, as in South Africa, it may be possible at the same time both to set up a Commission and to institute legal proceedings against individuals responsible for crimes (Bassiouni, 2000), (30) Up to 1992, no Truth Commission had disclosed the names of persecutors. 228 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions even if, historically speaking, there have been very few proceedings instituted after the submission of a Commission's final report ( 31). Taking into account the traits peculiar to Commissions, with a view to attempting to avoid their being unduly influenced by the circumstances and any display of clout, and to avoid, therefore, that their flexibility might prove to be a weakness, in 1996 the United Nations came up with a first detailed list of recommendations for the criteria to be adopted in setting them up (United Nations, 1996). This is a carefully detailed document constituting an important contribution towards the definition of an as yet unsettled issue (Hainer, 1996). From all the points made, next to the general recommendation in favour of the creation of Commissions for the historical reconstruction of violations, there emerges the need to promote practices aiming at recognizing a «right to truth». In particular, it is foreseen that: - the components of the Commission be unmovable; - the evidence emerging from the investigations be safeguarded for a possible use in successive trials before criminal courts; - the names of those responsible be disclosed; - the final report be published and divulged; - that measures be taken for the preservation of files and to avoid the destruction of documents. The Commissions can be set up or supported: at a national level by the government or Parliament; at the international level by the United Nations or by NGOs. Working under the auspices of the United Nations may involve some positive ( 32) practical aspects but also some drawbacks (33), which may make (31) As a matter of fact, let us here hint at the fact that the coordination of a Commission's work with the activity of the ordinary legal system is a delicate and complex issue, which is generally taken into account when a Commission is set up. (32) Among the possible advantages let us mention the most significant: a) the neutrality of the body set up by the international community; b) the authoritativeness deriving from international legitimation and the ensuing pressure exerted on the parties involved to make them collaborate with the Commission; c) the possibility of strong economic support, an element which might prove to be decisive to complete the work of the Commission. In Chad, in Uganda and in the Philippines, for examp le, the different Commissions have been adversely affected by economic problems, while in El Salvador international sponsorship has resulted in United Nations funding (Hainer, 1994). (33) A number of arguments against the advisability of international sponsorship have been identified. To begin with, if all the members of the Commission are The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 229 it preferable to set up a Commission completely internal to the country involved (Hainer, 1994, p. 642). 4.3.2. Critical Aspects: an Outline Besides allowing for a first theoretical reconstruction of their principles and guidelines, the experience of the Commissions, set up in recent decades, has also highlighted a number of critical issues on which the debate is still open. These are, in short: - the choice itself of considering the search for and diffusion of «historical truth» (in its widest acception) as a principle of justice necessary to reconciliation and peace-building – let us remember here the considerations on the positive role which we believe the reconstruction of individual and collective truth and the reactivation of memory have – is not accepted unconditionally. In particular, some have also challenged the advisability of circulating a final report in a moment of transition characterized by criticality and institutional fragility (Woods, 1998, p. 83; Hayner, 1996, p. 176). As a matter of fact, this is not an altogether theoretical issue, as there are countries which, in spite of having just been through a period of civil war or of terrible violations, have shown no interest in investigating the most recent events (in Mozambique and in Angola the opposing parties have refused the proposal of some human right organizations to set up a Truth Commission); - a relevant limit is also represented by the fact that, as a rule, the Commissions are not empowered to carry out investigations (they are not entitled, for example, to summon witnesses). The TRC constituted an important exception in this respect because it was endowed with ample powers of investigation and could link up in some cases with the judicial authorities and the police; foreigners this might result in an impaired understanding of certain events, due to a lack of first-hand knowledge of the events themselves. Moreover, an International Commission, as a rule, leaves the country once the investigation is over, which means it cannot apply any pressure within the country for the adoption of the measures and the recommendations set out in the final report. Finally, some countries have refused the setting up of an International Commission in the name of a rigid interpretation of the principle of national sovereignty on internal affairs (Hainer, 1994). 230 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions - it is also necessary to consider a further possible limitation to the reconstruction of the picture of the violations ( 34): the difficulty or, sometimes, the impossibility to investigate individual cases when one is in the presence of an elevated number of abuses and widespread violations. A country, above all when going through a delicate phase of transition, rarely has the resources or knowledge needed to investigate all instances of individual violations, also if the evidence is easily accessible, managing only to outline a general truth, according to some «models» of repeated violation. Such an outcome may well engender – as in the case of «victors' justice», though to a lesser extent – feelings of frustration among the victims, who often give evidence hoping that their personal cases may be thoroughly investigated; - with the exception of the TRC, (35) the Commissions set up so far have not been legitimized through democratic means. In periods of transition, as a matter of fact, one is unlikely to have conditions conducive to a public, political or social debate or to a referendum aimed at making the people choose. Often, the facilities needed for elections do not as yet exist, which would instead be of the utmost importance, since the objective is that of setting out on a common (34) «…all Truth Commissions have their limitations. In the words of Michael Ignatieff: ‘All that a Truth Commission can achieve is to reduce the number of lies that can be circulated unchallenged in public discourse. In Argentina, its work has made it impossible to claim, for example, that the military did not throw half-dead victims in the sea from helicopters. In Chile, it is no longer permissible to assert in public that the Pinochet regime did not dispatch thousands of entirely innocent people...’. Applying Ignatieff’s notion of reducing the number of lies, one can say that the information in the hands of the Commission made it impossible to claim, for example, that: the practice of torture by state security forces was not systematic and widespread; that only a few ‘rotten eggs’ or ‘bad apples’ committed gross violations of human rights; that the state was not directly and indirectly involved in ‘black -onblack violence’; that the chemical and biological warfare programme was only of a defensive nature; that slogans by sections of the liberation movement did not contribute to killings of ‘settlers’ or farmers; and that the accounts of gross human rights violations in the African National Congress (ANC) camps were the consequence of state disinformation. Thus, disinformation about the past that had been accepted as truth by some members of society lost much of its credibility». See: TRC- Final Rreport, vol. 1, chap. 5, pp. 33-34. (35) The TRC is the first instance of the creation of a Commission preceded by a procedure explicitly aiming at encouraging the participation of the community in its setting up. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 231 path, based on the analysis of past events and the idea of turning over a new leaf. In conclusion, the theoretical picture is still quite complex: the decision to set up a Commission, as a matter of fact, entails not only the evaluation of the social, political and economic circumstances making it advisable, but also makes it imperative to solve in one direction or the other the endless issues concerning its actual setting up( 36). 5. The TRC 5.1. The Setting up of a TRC The choice of setting up a TRC, aimed at the recognition of the violations and the abuses committed during apartheid and at the attribution of the historical and judicial responsibility for said violations and abuse to perpetrators from all walks of life without necessarily seeking their punishment is undoubtedly to be viewed as an option grounded on the advanced principles of Restorative Justice (Tutu, 2000; Pitch, 2001, p. 336). In order to understand the work done by the TRC, it is first of all necessary to understand how the TRC was born (Gentili, Lollini, 2000). It was the result of a peaceful transition from the segregationist apartheid regime to democratic rule, which interested all South-African peoples (Villa -Vicencio, 2000; Hamber, 1998). Together the political parties involved (the ANC, the National Party and Inkata) negotiated a transfer of powers, which were embodied in the approval of the 1993 provisional Constitution, containing among other things a number of indications on the setting up of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission. The option to be chosen, whether a Commission or a Criminal National and International Tribunal, was therefore openly debated and there was a clear-cut refusal of the idea of opting for «victors' justice». Some important political figures in the different line-ups, especially some ANC members, were of the opinion that the alleged perpetrators of gross human rights violations should be prosecuted, the way the allied forces opted for prosecution in Nuremberg. A number of arguments, besides the basic one (36) The choice of setting up a Commission was defined as «open» (Llewellyn, Howse 1999, p. 375), as opposed to the judicial model, because its structure and activities can be adapted to the specific situation, encouraging from the very beginning a careful analysis of existing circumstances. 232 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions that sets reparation and reconciliation – not punishment – as essential goals, were decisive in leading to the setting up of a Commission: «In South Africa, where we had a military stalemate, that (the Nuremberg option) was clearly an impossible option. Neither side in the struggle (the state nor the liberation movements) had defeated the other and hence nobody was in a position to enforce so-called victor’s justice. However, there were even more compelling reasons for avoiding the Nuremberg option. There is no doubt that members of the security establishment would have scuppered the negotiated settlement had they thought they were going to run the gauntlet of trials for their involvement in past violations. (...) Another reason why Nuremberg was not a viable option was because our country simply could not afford the resources in time, money and personnel that we would have had to invest in such an operation. (...) the route of trials would have stretched an already hard-pressed judicial system beyond reasonable limits. It would also have been counterproductive to devote years to hearing about events that, by their nature, arouse very strong feelings. It would have rocked the boat massively and for too long. The Malan trials and the Goniwe inquest have also shown us that, because such legal proceedings rely on proof beyond reasonable doubt, the criminal justice system is not the best way to arrive at the truth. There is no incentive for perpetrators to tell the truth and often the court must decide between the word of one victim against the evidence of many perpetrators. Such legal proceedings are also harrowing experiences for victims, who are invariably put through extensive cross-examination (...) We have been concerned, too, that many consider only one aspect of justice. Certainly, amnesty cannot be viewed as justice if we think of justice only as retributive and punitive in nature. We believe, however, that there is another kind of justice - a Restorative Justice which is concerned not so much with punishment as with correcting imbalances, restoring broken relationships – with healing, harmony and reconciliation. Such justice focuses on the experience of victims; hence the importance of reparation.» (Tutu, 2001; see also anche Caron, 1999). Hamber, possibly resorting to words which are less poignant from the emotional point of view but just as effective in summarizing the reasons why South Africa opted for a Commission, states that «A Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC) is to be established in South Africa with the express purpose of facilitating a truth recovery process aimed at reconciling with the past. According to the objectives of the latest draft of the Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Bill this process of reconciliation is to occur through the establishing of as complete a picture as possible of the causes, nature and extent of past abuses. The so-called The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 233 «victims» of these abuses will be located and allowed to relate their stories so as to restore human and civil dignity. Thereafter, the TRC aims to make amends to these individuals through the granting of reparations and rehabilitative measures. Furthermore, the TRC intends to enhance reconciliation by granting amnesty to perpetrators of human rights abuses and by compiling a comprehensive report of past abuses. The Report will make recommendations on how such events can be prevented from occurring again » (Hamber ,1995, p. 1). 5.2. TRC Activity (1) As we have repeatedly pointed out at the very heart of the TRC's work (as of the work done by the Commissions set up in other countries) is the new and unprecedented way of dealing with the link between truth and justice, in the specific instance consisting in the creation of three different levels of intervention: a) the Commission was vested simply with the authority to seek the truth, a circumscribed activity having no direct link with the power to prosecute and mete out punishment; b) the determination of truth is directly related to accountability – through the identification of alleged perpetrators or explicitly referring prosecution to another agency (37); c) the Commission was authorized to implement reconciliation and amnesty policies, for those who made «full disclosure», provided that their crime was politically motivated and showed remorse. (2) The work of the TRC was huge and complex and unfolded through the activities of three Committees: a) the Human Rights Violation Committee which took victims' statements; b) the Reparation and Rehabilitation Committee, whose task it was to gather information and evidence on the identity of the victims and (37) The problem of the coordination between the TRC's work and the criminal judicial system is extremely complex, so much so that specific mechanisms of coordination have been foreseen. The Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, 1995 laid down, as a matter of fact, that the TRC could subpoena witnesses, having previously informed of its intention to do so the General Prosecutor and explained why the need existed, even if the answers given or evidence sought could lead to the indictment of the witnesses. However, it also explicitly prohibited the use of any declaration or information or incriminating evidence obtained during the Commission's hearings in legal proceedings (Woods, 1998). 234 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions their families, on the nature and the extent of their suffering, and to make recommendations to the government as to the measures needed to ensure reparation and rehabilitation for the victims themselves (Lansing, King, 1998, p. 765); c) and the Amnesty Committee, which assessed the possibility of granting amnesty to individual perpetrators, in return for full disclosure of the abuses committed. a) b) c) d) e) f) (3) The main modes through which information was collected were: the hearings (of the victims; related to specific events; related to specific groups – women, youth and children, the military; the institutions; political parties); the investigations, to corroborate the statements, check them and integrate them with additional information; research work, through the setting up of a true and proper specific department to assist in the analysis and contextualization of the huge amount of data, evidence and information received; 22,500 victims came before the local chapters of the Human Rigths Violation Committee to tell their stories; «all those who have suffered physical or mental injury, emotional suffering or a substantial impairment of human rights due to gross violation of human rights associated with the political conflicts of the past» were recognizeded to be victims (Hamber, 1995, p. 2); 7,100 requests for amnesty were submitted to the Amnesty Committee(38). The Commission, as we have already repeatedly said, was aware of the fact that it had to come up with a version of the past capable of bringing about common consensus. «We believe we have provided enough of the truth about our past for threre to be a consensus about it» ( 39). But which truth is meant here? The Final Report mentions a truth altogether different from judicial truth( 40), yet far more complex than that which is normally termed consensual truth (Cohen, 2001). As a matter of fact, it identified four different kinds of truth ( 41): (38) See infra Schedule 2. Tutu D., Chairperson’s Foreword, 18, quoted by Cohen, 2001. (40) See retro § 3.3. (41) «Given the magnitude of this exercise, the Commission’s quest for truth should be viewed as a contribution to a much longer-term goal and vision. Its purpose in attempting to uncover the past had nothing to do with vendetta; it had to do, rather, with helping victims to become more visible and more valuable citizens through the (39) The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 235 a) factual truth: this is defined as legal or scientific information which is factual, accurate and objective, obtained through impartial procedures. On an individual level this means information on particular incidents and people: what exactly happened to whom, when, how and where. On a social level this means recording the context, the causes and the patterns of violation: an interpretation of the facts that should, that is, do away with any tendency to deny the past. But the Commission was not a Tribunal, and, rightly so, did not subject the victims' statements to cross-examination. It anyway assessed, through confirmation, said statement on the grounds of likelihood. As Simpson holds, «it is fascinating to note that most of the legal and jurisprudential dilemmas presented by the TRC process are actually rooted in its own almost bipolar roles as both a ‘factfinding’ and quasi-judicial enterprise on one hand, and as a psychologically sensitive mechanism for story telling and healing on the other» (Simpson, 1999, p. 15); b) personal and narrative truth: these are the stories told by the perpetrators and, more exhaustively, those told by the victims. This experience constitutes an opportunity for the healing of the statement-givers, making it possible to add details to collective truth and to pave the way for reconciliation attaching value to the individual experience of people who had previously been silenced; c) social truth: this is born of interaction, discussion and debate. Public hearings foster transparency and encourage participation. Highly conflicting points of view on the past can be taken into account and compared. What it highlights is the confrontation, the process rather than the final result; d) restorative and healing truth: these are the kinds of narrative dealing with the past in an attempt to come to terms with it. It is based on the assumption that truth, inasmuch as evidence based on facts, is not sufficient: the interpretation must have self-healing, reconciliatory and restorative aims. This requires the acknowledgement that everyone’s suffering was real and worthy of attention (Cohen, 2001). Truth, however, is but the first of the TRC's objectives. Just as important is reconciliation. If the two are not taken together, the latter is but a mere statement of principle. The philosophy informing such an interpretation is that which enabled the South African people to deal with the conflicts of the past in public recognition and official acknowledgement of their experiences». See: TRCFinal Report, vol. 1, chap. 5, 27. 236 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions the name of a new social contract, which is the pursuit of truth with no hankering for vengeance. Far removed from a predominantly religious approach, reconciliation is based on the acknowledgement of past history and on the censure of the evil done, whichever party was the wrong-doer.»The trouble is that there are erroneus notions of what reconciliation is all about. Reconciliation is not about being cosy; it is not about pretending that things were other than they were. Reconciliation based on falsehood or not facing up to reality, is not true reconciliation and will not last» (Final Report, 1998). 5.3. Public Hearings: Story-Telling and Narration It would be very interesting to have time to go into the procedures and the praxis of the TRC (to analyze in detail its functions, powers, composition, structure, procedures, the results obtained). Unfortunately it is not possible to do so here. We shall therefore be content with examining an aspect we are particularly interested in and which came to be the main activity of the TRC: that of both victims' and perpetrators' narratives and story-telling within the context of public hearings with community participation. It is the victims, as a matter of fact, who are at the very heart of the attempt to come to terms with the past; it is the victims who are the protagonists of the Commission's research and investigation, and because of this they are sought, approached and listened to with the utmost attention (Flores, 1999, p. 24). In such a context, the Human Rights Violation Committee, presided over by Archbishop Desmond Tutu, was entrusted within the scope of the TRC mandate, to take the statements of the victims ( 42) in public hearings held throughout the country. To begin with, the people were informed by the Committee members, who went to the towns and villages in the different regions to explain the aims of the TRC and the way it would work; then, anybody who had been the victim of abuse or violence was invited to make a statement in his/her language and to provide any evidence he/she might have. The statements were made in front of statement-takers belonging to non-governmental organisations, faith organisations and civic bodies who spoke the country's main languages. (42) For an accurate definition of the term 'victim', see the Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, No. 34, 1995, chapter 1, par. 1, which basically coincides with the definition given by Hamber. See retro § 5.2. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 237 The taking down of the stories told in public had a twofold function: on the one hand, it meant the stories of human rights violations were collected by the parties directly interested in doing so, thus helping form a picture of the abuses perpetrated; on the other, it offered the victims an opportunity to relate their suffering to people who listened to them sympathetically and recognized their pain (Final Report, 1998). For many people, the public hearing was the first place in which they felt free to recount the experience lived under apartheid, to give vent to the impressions gathered and to put forward their requests and expectations; besides the fact of being listened to could be considered as a first form of restoration. It has, as a matter of fact, been said that story-telling, the oral handing down of individual memory has an important catartic and symbolic function and constitutes an opportunity to learn about the victims' most urgent needs (Teitel, 2000). Which is why, «By holding public hearings or granting private interviews, the Commission attempted to diminish the legal, andat times adverserial, nature of its work and to focus on the restorative and therapeutic dimensions of its mandate» (Final Report, 1998). The evidence, the truth revealed must be listened to for what it is: a cry from the heart, a suffering which is close to that expressed by the characters in Greek tragedy and which must therefore also be listened to in its silences. The Commission therefore worked to transform what seemed a pre-ordained destiny into a chance of a possible future. However, it must be borne in mind that «despite the potential for the TRC to operate as a psychologically healing mechanism it is not a sufficient process in itself to promote psychological rehabilitation. It is argued that a range of psychological structures and strategies will be needed to run parallel to the TRC» (Hamber, 1995, 1) ( 43). (43) About the nature of trauma: «The people who suffered most from traumatic episodes fell into five categories: the victim, the perpetrator, their families and dependants, the community and, in a different way, Commission personnel. Commission personnel and so me dependants and family members formed a distinct group in that their traumatic experience was often of a vicarious nature. However, all groups vicariously or directly shared classic symptoms of post-traumatic stress syndrome. Symptoms included lowered self-esteem, depression, emotional blunting, avoidance behaviour, impulsiveness, uncontrollable anger, substance abuse, paranoia, relationship difficulties (social and interpersonal), complicated bereavement and sleep disturbance. Often such symptoms had become a part of life for the sufferer and were so deeply entrenched in the individual that they had to be viewed as part of that person and not merely a passing crisis. 238 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions Already when the TRC was set up, as a matter of fact, doubts were expressed as to the enormous difficulties which the impact of the victims' story-telling would have, also from a psychological point of view, and it was held they should be provided with support services. In this respect, it might be useful to remember some of the major challenges and problems the TRC had to contend with at the time of its creation (Hamber, 1995, 4): a) South Africa was a country with limited resources, and mental health care services are particularly «under-resourced»; b) the conflicts of the past were not easily viewed as a unitary complex. The roots and context of conflicts are still complex and in specific areas are still continuing. Often, the clear division between political and criminal violence and the delineation between perpetrators and victims have been obscured for a long time. Further, the re-telling of stories, irrespective of enormous psychological backup, cannot substitute for addressing the causes and nature of the violence and the development of mechanisms for preventing its re-occurrence; c) it has been underlined that a continued focus on the psychological needs of the victims and on the TRC activity has the risk to overmedicalise a social phenomenon. The social process of reconciliation is not about diagnosing and treating pathology. These views can prompt mental health-care workers to want to «repair» individuals rather than becoming part of the process of reconciliation or healing; d) finally, from a more political angle, psychologists need to be aware that often political processes run counter to psychological processes. The process of not remembering and re-visiting the past becomes difficult to be substained for a political rationality that often demands forgetting and the need for political consensus. It has been underlined that this condition required that mental health care workers develop an active stance and engage in the political debates. It was important not to generalise or simplify diagnosis or, indeed, understanding of treatment. Often the trauma that individuals presented had been complicated by a range of socio-economic and medical problems and was also affected by the time that had elapsed since the traumatic event. Often living conditions caused a new range of emotional difficulties that conflated with previous ones, resulting in a complicated traumatic cocktail that demanded more then a mere therapeutic or healing intervention. The mental health of a person could not be seen or understood in isolation from socio-economic realities». See: TRC- Final Report, vol. 1, chap. 11, pp. 4-5. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 5.4. 239 The other models of public hearing The activity of the Committee was carried out not only through public hearings devoted to the listening of individual stories and experiences but also through other kinds of hearing: - those focusing on specific events (gross widespread human rights violations) ( 44); - special ones, in which one tried to focus the attention on victims belonging to particularly «vulnerable» social groups (children, women, etc.); - those focusing on the institutions and the different social contexts (the world of business and work( 45), the health sectors, the legal system, the media, the economic set-up, the prison system and the faith community) in order to reconstruct the role played by the different professional or institutional sectors and by the different organisations within the system created by apartheid, so as to understand the antecedents, the circumstances, the factors and the context of violations; - those devoted to the legal community: the emergency legislation was surely one of the main tools of the regime. Especially when the state of emergency was proclaimed for the second time in the eighties, the police and the defence forces were practically given a «licence to kill», and the hearings carried out to investigate such events made it possible to uncover the existence of true and proper «death squads», whose task it was to kill the opposers and spread violence and terror throughout the country (Boraine, 2000). The hearings about the legal system made it clear that the courts and the legal system in general connived in the legislative and executive pursuit of injustice; (46) (44) Some of the specific events investigated are events whose echo spread beyond the South African pale and drew the attention of the world at large. We might take as an example the uprising of the Soweto students in 1976; the killing, in 1986, of the «Guguletu seven» following police infiltration into the ANC; the seven-day war between the ANC and IFP (Inkatha freedom party) in 1990. (45) Two dominant points of view emerged from these hearings and from the ensuing public debates: on the one hand there were those who viewed apartheid as part of a system of «racial-capitalism» and held it was beneficial for white business because it was an integral part of a system based on the exploitation of black workers; on the other hand, there were those who held, instead, that apartheid raised the costs of doing business, severely eroded South-Africans' skill base and technical competitiveness and, as a reult, undermined long-term productivity and economic growth. (46) In October 1997 the TRC and the population at large, also those most inured to public lies, were surprised at the repeated denial of responsibility by the notorious 240 6. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions The Issue of Amnesty At this point we should deal with a second issue which is just as complex and of paramount importance: the possibility to foresee the granting of an amnesty. Regardless of the paradigm to which one has recourse to come to terms with the past, one of the most widely debated issues in the phase of transition and of change from a past of violations and abuses is the granting or not of amnesty to those responsible for the violations being investigated (Quaritsch, Italian translation, 1995) ( 47). Minister of the Police, Adrian Vlok. There was no doubt that Vlok had been a member of the State Security Council, and he had been undeniably responsible for police behaviour, as he had had specific powers to manage and control the "death squads" organised within the police forces. He entrenched himself behind two techniques of denial. The first was denial of responsibility: Vlok held that not only could he not be charged with the violation of any human rights, but also that, as a Minister, he had done all he could to sensitise the police and get them to treat blacks and whites the same way. Any form of abuse that had taken place had never, anyway, been explicitly commissioned. The neutralisation to which Vlok and like-minded people had recourse to by way of justification sounded more or less like this: "We at the top took certain decisions and used certain terminology without thinking about it. It worked its way to the ground, where people misrepresented it" (quoted in Cohen, 2001, p. 127). Some witnesses therefore justified themselves saying that their intentions had been misinterpreted: the orders imparted to "get rid" of an ANC activist, for example, meant to them an invitation to get them to move out of a given area, not to kill them. The second artifice advocated by Vlok was based on the denial of knowledge. Vlok declared he had been kept in the dark by the lies of his police-colleagues. He had never known about the torture and the death squads. Here his words take on an unprecedented concreteness and become ludicrously literal:"There was never any report on my desk saying 'we tortured someone or we killed someone and buried his body'. I never approved it, it was never brought to my attention"(quoted in Cohen, 2001, p. 128). Leon Wessel, former Deputy Minister for Law and Order, has supplied a refined analysis for this kind of denial: "I do not believe the political defence of 'I did not know' is available to me, because in many respects I believe I did not want to know... In my own way, I had suspicions of things that had caused discomfort in official circles, but because I did not have the facts to substantiate my suspicions, or I lacked the courage to shout from the rooftops, I have to confess that I only whispered in the corridors... It may be blunt, but I have to say it... the Nationalist Party did not have an inquiring mind about these matters"(quoted in Cohen, 2001, p. 128). (47) As Quaritsch points out, when an illegitimate political regime falls, the question inevitably ariseas as how to deal with those who held offices in the old The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 241 The problems of punishment and reconciliation, of revenge or forgiveness, of memory or oblivion converge, as a matter of fact, in amnesty. The word amnesty derives from the Greek amnestia, which means forgetting, oblivion or remission. In the meaning we are here concerned with, the term refers to an act by a sovereign power aimed at exempting those it concerns from criminal prosecution for past offences. It is a measure of a predominantly political nature and as such answers above all needs of advisability and expediency. Given that this is the meaning of the term, there is a first consideration to be made: in a country in transition from a past of violations and widespread injustice to democratic rule, any request, especially if made by the victims, to «learn the truth» on the one hand and to «obtain justice» on the other (Ratner, 1999, p. 732) becomes an imperative – while oblivion and forgiveness pose themselves as possible further and extremely complex phases. And it is here that an approach privileging the punishment of the culprits clashes with an approach that considers it advisable in some situations to grant amnesty to those responsible for the abuses. In the most convincing of reconstructions, the second position comes to hypothesise a possible incompatibility between peace (the primary object of the reconciliation process) and justice (interpreted as punishment of the culprits). When discussing the negotiated revolution, some point out that the 20th century was characterised by a huge number of conflicts and violations of human rights, which was followed by an altogether inadequate response in terms of punishment of the culprits (Bassiouni, 2000). It is clear that oblivion and forgetting, not preceded by the experience of forgiveness, have covered most of these violations and extended to most of the victims. All this happened in a number of countries, without even needing a law in this sense. Elsewhere, instead, after the fall of a repressive regime or after the end of a conflict, the most regime, those who carried out orders and their followers. In our century too different peoples have come up with very different answers. Five different methods can be chosen either separately or at the same time or the one after the other: the deeds performed under the old regime and now legally censored are (1) ignored or (2) immediately amnestied by law; (3) for weeks if not for months one indulges in retaliation without having any recourse to legal proceedings; (4) the crimes of the old regime are judged by special tribunals or by ordinary magistrates; (5) the old regime's supporters are dispossessed of their property and offices, interned and killed (in totalitarian regimes) for supporting the old regime, or subjected to economic sanctions or penalised on the professional level. (Quaritsch, Italian translation, 1995, p. 139). 242 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions serious violations of human rights have been covered up by blanket amnesties(48). For these reasons, amnesty for crimes against humanity or human rights has always been looked upon with suspicion (Flores, 1999, p. 29). The problem arising is therefore twofold: on the one hand it is above all necessary to decide whether amnesty is a viable option, without however renouncing to affirm principles of justice(49); on the other it is just as indispensable to question whether the conditions required to grant such a measure exist (bearing in mind that blanket amnesties are, as a rule, viewed as denials of justice). An amnesty is therefore an act of a predominantly political nature, of «political justice», which historically has been resorted to also when one has opted for prosecution to deal with the past; also «victors' justice» has found a collocation for such measures (Flores, 1999; Crainz, 2000) ( 50). In such instances, amnesty consists in a display of will-power by the «winners», made all the more justifiable, from a political point of view, by the passing of time (and by the scanty effectiveness of criminal proceedings). In the course of the eighties and the nineties, instead, amnesty was often an integral part of the agreements and compromises negotiated to reach a peaceful solution in countries in transition (Scharf, 1996, p. 1) ( 51). In (48) As happened, for example, in Brazil: «…the atrocities committed by the Brazilian government have received little attention since the passing of a general amnesty in 1979. The amnesty-granting process in Brazil is a detailed and complex one, but the key point for this discussion is that the amnesty passed was, in the words of President Geisel, «ample, general and unrestrictive». In effect, it was a «Blanket Amnesty» without full disclosure or compensation for victims. This Blanket Amnesty, coupled with no investigation into the past by the old or new governments, has meant that an official truth was never uncovered in Brazil. As a result, the families of victims continue to seek the truth and draw attention to the numerous atro cities perpetrated by the past government despite the fact that a civilian government was instated in 1985» (Hamber,1997). (49) In the course of the preparatory conference for the setting up of the International Criminal Court, it had been suggested that the Court may consider the granting of an amnesty so as to foster international peace and national reconciliation, when having to decide whether to exert its jurisdiction in a given context or to prosecute a given individual. The final text of the Rome Statute contains some points which might be interpreted in the light of said suggestion (Scharf 1999, p. 139). (50) Suffice it to think of the many amnesties which brought to a close the denazification or de- fascistization processes after World War II. (51) In such cases (Argentina, Chile, El Salvador, Guatemala, Haiti, Uruguay, South Africa), amnesty resulted from the negotiated revolution which characterised the peace agreements reached. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 243 such processes, the groups in a position of power are animated by the desire to avoid a head-on collision with the emerging élites and by the need to play an active role in the confrontation with their successors in order to survive, in political, economic, and judicial terms in the society to come. Opposition movements, on the other hand, have sought a negotiated solution to avoid clashing from the social and military point of view against an enemy who is still too strong. In such a situation, insisting on criminal proceedings at all costs entailed the risk of prolonging the conflict, while the granting of an amnesty became the tool to put an end to the raging conflict. ( 52) 6.1. Amnesty and the TRC In order to exemplify what we have said so far, reference shall be made once more to the TRC(53), whose choice to foresee the possibility of the amnesty was part of a negotiated compromise at the end of the apartheid regime (Hamber 1995), without which it would have been difficult to reach a somewhat peaceful transition( 54). (52) More specifically: a) those who hold that an amnesty could prove to be a necessary tool for bargaining do not view the granting of an amnesty as being equivalent to impunity, because they couple such an option with the idea of effective and more specific mechanisms for the ascertaining of responsibilities: it is to be noticed, therefore, that whenever an amnesty was granted so as to bring about peace, damages were always awarded to the victims and their families, Truth Commissions were set up to document the abuses, disqualification from public offices was always foreseen. Even those who conceive of amnesty in such terms believe, however, that an amnesty should be granted only in exceptional cases (Scharf, 1999, p. 512); b) those who instead view the punishment of culprits as an essential and irrenounceable part of justice view amnesties as standing in absolute juxtaposition to the peace-building process. Many have asked that at least as far as the three main classes of international crimes are concerned (that is, genocide, crimes against humanity and war crimes) the option of granting amnesties to perpetrators be ruled out both at a national and international level (Bassiouni, 1999). While it is, as a matter of fact, quite easy to accept the ideal that a State may pardon the crimes it has suffered directly, gross violations of human rights are considered to be first and foremost crimes against people; this makes it extremely difficult to establish to what extent it may be legitimate for the State to stand in for the individual in granting «forgiveness». (53) For quantitative data on the work of the subcommission that has seen to the granting of amnesties – the Amnesty Committee – see infra Schedule No. 2. (54) «The amnesty provisions in the TRC's charter represented essentially a compromise between the demands of the old regime for a Blanket Amnesty for all those charged with human rights abuses and the equally strong insistence of many in the 244 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions The Amnesty Committee examined the granting of amnesty for single deeds, in return for full disclosure of all the relevant facts related to that same act, which «were advised, planned, directed, commanded, ordered or committed within or outside The Republic…» between 1960 and 1994 (Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, No. 34, 1995, chapter 4, par. 20 (2)), and which were connected with a political objective. The constitutive act (Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, No. 34, 1995) defined as an act with a political obiective any action constituting an offence related to a political end or which was committed to fight or resist the political struggle under apartheid ( 55) without distinguishing between perpetrators or material executors or instigators of the violations being examined. The constitutive act also foresaw, fully in line with the TRC's general scope to obtain as full as possible a picture of the violations committed, as a pre-requisite for the granting of amnesty, the «full disclosure of all relevant facts», and this also if such disclosure were to prove selfincriminating for the petitioner. Such a pre-requisite however was never clearly laid down and the task of assessing the exhaustiveness of the disclosures was entrusted to the Committee. The meaning attributed to amnesty, in the approach adopted by the TRC, was therefore twofold: - to help ascertain the truth; - to foster the reconciliation process. anti-apartheid movement that just punishment had to be meted out to the miscreants. The decision to proceed on a course that represented a middle ground between "Nuremberg and amnesia" was dictated by the fact that the transition to the new South Africa was the result of a negotiated settlement between the old regime and the liberation forces. Absent the possibility of at least selected amnesties for past crimes, it is virtually certain that the government of President F.W. de Klerk would simply have refused to proceed with the dismantling of apartheid and to allow the African National Congress to come into power» (Garrett, 2000, p. 4). (55) More precisely, the acts in question must have been commited during «political uprising, disturbance, protest, strike». The act has a political objective if «the conduct was primarily directed at a political opponents or State property or personnel or against private property or individuals» (Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, No. 34, 1995, chapter 4, par. 20 (3) (b) (d)), and if the conduct was «the result of the deliberate planning on the part of the State (or former State) or any of its organs, or the part of any political organisation, liberation movement or other group or individuals» (Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, No. 34, 1995, chapter 2, par. 4 (a) (IV)). The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 245 On the one hand, as a matter of fact, the purpose was to obtain the statements of the perpetrators of the violations so as to reconstruct the truth on the past (Lansing, King 1998, p. 770), that is to ascertain who was to blame for the violations, what drove them to be so and behave so and what influenced their behaviour (Final Report, 1998). In other words, the procedure leading to the granting of amnesties obliged the apartheid regime to own up to their abuses, making it inevitable for the white population to acknowledge the systematic violence perpetrated and the horrors committed during the period. (56) On the other hand, the amnesty procedure has made it possible for the perpetrators of violations, invited to publicly disclose the crimes they committed, to participate in and contribute to the construction of a segment of the reconciliation process. The Commission, which had not been given the mandate to directly bring about reconciliation between single victims and perpetrators(57), was however allowed to express in its Final Report its recommendations that strategies should be adopted to favour the peaceful co-existence of those who had acknowledged their responsibilities, thus obtaining amnesty. Once again the experience of the TRC goes to prove that opting for amnesty is undoubtedly one of the most difficult and critical choices to be made (Markel, 1999, p. 390), when a country has to decide which tools to use to deal with its past. As a matter of fact, the usefulness of amnesties in the truth-reconstruction process has long been debated. (58) Not everybody (56) In reconstructing persecutors' truth, the TRC was confronted with the issue of the relationship existing between individual responsibility and collective responsibility. The crimes for which it was possible to apply for amnesty, as a matter of fact, were those committed on political grounds, that is those motivated by ideology, by political beliefs or the crimes committed within a criminal system as such. In order to understand the underlying dynamics, it was necessary to contextualise the investigated crimes, considering them the result of an individual action but not only (Llewellin, Howse, 1999). In the Final Report it is specified that those responsible for violations may be viewed as people who carried out orders, as people indoctrinated, threatened, or influenced by their education. (57) «The contribution of the Commission to reconciliation between specific victims and perpetrators was necessarily limited (by its time frame, mandate and resources). In some cases, however, the Commission assisted in laying the foundation for reconciliation. Although truth does not necessarily lead to healing, it is often a first step towards reconciliation. Father Michael Lapsley, who lost both arms and an eye in a near fatal security police parcel bomb attack in Harare in 1990, told the Commission: ‘I need to know whom to forgive in order to endeavour to do so’ ». See: TRC- Final Report, vol. 1, chap. 5, p. 16. (58) «The argument was that, despite the noble motivations for national reconciliation, any amnesty arrangement without a parallel obligation to disclose the 246 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions has accepted that a truth declared but not followed by an acknowledgement of responsibility could be viewed as a form of justice, and some indeed have declared that it is unlikely that the identification of the perpetrators, if unaccompanied by some form of judicial hearing and accompanied instead by the granting of an amnesty, may in some way help reconciliation with one's past (59) (Lansing, King, 1998; Woods, 1998). systemic nature of the crimes perpetrated, in fact has potentially grave implications for the long-term prospects sustainable democracy. In particular, for the victims of these abuses of power the implication would be that they would never have access to the information essential to their rehabilitation, let alone any prospect of redress at civil or criminal law. One possible consequence of this is that, in the absence of any public acknowledgment, coupled to the impossibility of restitution through the courts, widespread resentment could well manifest itself in informal retribution at both an individual and a collective level, resulting in escalating rather than de-escalating violence under the new democratic dispensation. The TRC represents a creative response to this very concern. It was therefore decided to combine the process of granting amnesty to perpetrators, with the processes of officially establishing the truth about past human rights abuse, providing victims with some form of reparation and making recommendations to the President as to measures the government should take to prevent any future recurrence of systematic violations of human rights. By attempting to foreground the needs and interests of victims, the TRC can be viewed as an attempt to restore the moral balance to an amnesty agreement, borne of negotiated political compromise, and which would otherwise engender a reconciliation-building enterprise in South Africa which exclusively ministered to the needs of former perpetrators. This fusion of an amnesty process with a truth recovery and reparative process is without precedent among similar initiatives internationally. It also demands that any evaluation of the TRC must be undertaken in its own terms, that is as a process designed to prioritize the needs and interests of victims of past gross human rights abuses» (Simpson, 1998, p. 2). (59) « Those who have cared about the future of our country have been worried that the amnesty provision might, amongst other things, encourage impunity because it seemed to sacrifice justice. We believe this view to be incorrect. The amnesty applicant has to admit responsibility for the act for which amnesty is being sought, thus dealing with the matter of impunity. Furthermore, apart from the most exceptional circumstances, the application is dealt with in a public hearing. The applicant must therefore make his admissions in the full glare of publicity. Let us imagine what this means. Often this is the first time that an applicant’s family and community learn that an apparently decent man was, for instance, a callous torturer or a member of a ruthless death squad that assassinated many opponents of the previous regime. There is, therefore, a price to be paid. Public disclosure results in public shaming, and sometimes a marriage may be a sad casualty as well». See: TRC- Final Report, vol. 5, chap. 9, p. 35. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 7. 247 Conclusions: which For-giveness can be given? To sum up. Much, possibly too much has been said. Yet, as we take leave, there emerges – forecefully – a last issue which cannot be overlooked: that of forgiveness. From what has been already been said, it is clear that the issues of amnesty and forgiveness are closely linked. Yet, while amnesty is an act of «politic al justice» granted through a law, which also foresees the modes whereby such amnesty should be granted( 60), forgiveness is an individual and collective virtue which cannot be imposed by law. «Justice and forgiveness are different measures with which to process time and involve altogether different decisions which must be kept separate », writes Resta (Resta, 1998, p. 83). From an anthropological point of view, forgiveness is part of the circuit of giving: those who forgive present themselves as people who, freely and without any obligation, give something to somebody else. What matters is that forgiveness meant as a gift, that is an act implying some form of return, can turn the original hostility into a relationship based on exchange and reciprocity, precisely because a gift has been implanted on the hostility originally characterising the relationship between the two opposing parties. «Morals and politics can only wait for it (forgiveness) to come about … It remains an individual virtue that cannot be delegated to law: the law cannot afford this particular supplement of feeling» (Resta, 1998, p. 87). In these terms, forgiveness is to be viewed as an ajuridical act, whose essential, basic, distinguishing trait is, first and foremost that of its being «free», that is, the fact that it cannot be subjected to conditions ( 61) (Jankélévitch, ital. transl. 1968) ( 62). (60) As to whether amnesty, inasmuch as a juridical act, may be classed or not as a «form of forgiveness» see infra footnote No. 62. (61) For the conditions enouncing it and the rules generally accompanying the use or the modes of expression of «moral forgiveness» see infra footnote No. 65. (62) The theory of the ajuridical nature of forgiveness, held by Rousset (1987) and adopted by Silvi (2001, p. 219), apparently lies in the very fact that an «act of forgiveness, to be such, cannot be performed by carrying out a duty or satisfying the conditions of lawfulness and/or validity any legal system lays down to regulate the sphere of application of any juridical act». It follows that, in the light of such a theory, forgiveness cannot be classed as a juridical act. Instead, according to Silvi, a theory in favour of the juridical nature of forgiveness may be constructed not on the grounds of rational truth, but on the grounds of factual truth: that is by verifying whether there are – within any legal system – any acts that, regardless of their nomina iuris, are characterised by a prescriptive structure mirroring the essential elements of the conceptual structure of forgiveness (that is: 248 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions This being so, which forgiveness can individuals and the collectivity actually grant? ( 63). When discussing forgiveness(64) it is necessary to distinguish between «moral forgiveness» (forgiveness to those who have acknowledged their guilt) from other forms of forgiveness, which, as we will see, are far more interesting and topical in the economy of our discourse. There is, however, a form of forgiveness bound to cover a universal moral function, which is to re-estabilish reciprocity, interrupting the moral circuit of evil. It is a form of basic forgiveness which reinforces the principle of retribution and which states that only what can be punished can be forgiven. It is a forgiveness that entails the promise the wrong-doing will never «occur again», which entails reparation and is based on the assumption of a temporal and spatial dimension within which good and evil are causes always ascribable within the structure of exchange. The point is such forgiveness applies only where the validity of obligations foreseeing commensurate exchanges is sanctioned and where the validity of a legitimately detained power is not challenged( 65). These are gratuitousness). For instance, being an «act of leniency», an amnesty may, in this respect, be viewed as a «form of forgiveness». (63) Let us here set aside – no matter how relevant in other discourse contexts – the difference between the notion of forgiveness as a speech act (an utterance such as: «I forgive you») and as a psychological event (taking place in the person who forgives and not requiring any form of utterance to be carried out (Silvi, 2001, p. 223). Our line of reasoning, as it were, places itself prior to such a distinction. (64) The following paragraph was written drawing inspiration from the following texts, which we are quoting here and which we will refrain from quoting further on, for brevity's sake: Abel, 1993; Abel, 2000; Lyotard, Italian translation, 1985; Ricoeur, Italian translation, 1989; Silvi, 2001. (65) But let us broach analytically the modes of enunciation and the rules which, according to Abel, generally accompany recourse to or the granting of «moral forgiveness». The main points are: a) forgiveness is not a magic word but a breaking of silence, a releasing of memory, which makes it possible to remember a past up to that very moment too painful to be put into words; b) only he/she/they who have acknowledged their wrong-doing can be forgiven. Nobody can repent on their behalf (that is, this happens but occasionally, for example when "representatives" of religious or political communities publicly repent for deeds they did not commit personally); c) the fact that he/she/they who forgive must be the he/she/they who suffered the wrongdoing. Nobody is to usurp their place; d) the fact that there can be no forgiveness until every possible attempt has been made to redress the wrong done. One can always find new forms of reparation and engaging in doing so, if coupled with an awareness of the irreparable, teaches not to make the same mistakes again; e) the fact that no forgiveness can be granted where no punishment can be meted out. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 249 situations in which it is possible to identify a victim and a culprit and in which, as Resta and Ceretti write (Resta, 1996, p. 333; Ceretti, 2000), any kind of difference will always be subjected – or can be subjected – to the unifying power of law, which comes to represent «the lowest common multiple», a shared language capable of translating and interpreting the dialects of the opposing parties. Here the culprit can be found guilty and acknowledge guilt and beg forgiveness, the victim grant it. In relation to them the third party (that is the judge) is always a third party because he obeys the law which creates a sense of belonging to the community that has created such a law. The problem, though, lies in the fact that most real-life historical events have to do with conflicts of a very different nature. They are conflicts in which the contending parties do not speak two different dialects of a same language, but two different languages, because there is no consensus on the wrong-doing and one is confronted with irreparable and ancient facts, where there are victims from past generations and the wrongdoing is too strictly intertwined with other instances of wrong-doing, so that it becomes impossible to appeal to a linear cause-effect relationship to identify the guilty parties. We are confronted with specular forms of behaviour which have degenerated; we are bordering on folly. In such situations, where the participants' dialects are incommensurable, where no hermeneutics and no reparation and reconciliation through the words of a third impartial party are possible, where the collective identities of peoples or of segments of a population are at stake, moral forgiveness can have no mandate. In the circumstances we are referring to – and we are of the opinion that the circumstances the TRC was confronted with before it was set up prove to be very relevant to what we are saying – the protagonists are unable/incapable to (ex)change their points of view. Not only, it is through the assumption of its «own» restricted viewpoint that each party self legitimates itself indefinitely, by submitting an endless list of rights. The coherence of each party appeals therefore to an exterior infinite principle. There is not, among the parties, a common time-frame, because there are no issues/themes shared or to be shared: what is missing, indeed, is the Silvi (Silvi, 2001, pp. 227-228), an analytical philosopher, discusses instead the assumptions of forgiveness. He identifies three kinds of assumption: a) a factive assumption (by forgiving one assumes the topicality of the fact for which forgiveness is granted; b) a negative assumption (by forgiving one assumes that the fact for which forgiveness is granted is a fact that is viewed as being negative); c) an assumption of validity (by forgiving one assumes that he/she who is granted forgiveness is responsible for the deed for which forgiveness is granted). 250 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions opportunity for an exchange based on a common principle. In other words, the resolution of a conflict, the remittance of a debt, the exchange of memories is impossible because the historical identity of each of the opposing parties is inscribed in an immemorable time which cannot be remembered and revived in the present. Everybody speaks a language of their own, narrates their own stories, etc. Must one therefore accept the idea that in situations of irreconcilable disagreement (différend, in French, dissidio in Italian) – what Abel terms the tragic aspect of conflict – one should renounce the possibility of having recourse to forgiveness? Far from it. Abel indeed claims that on this level it proves to be one of the most important forms of what Ricoeur terms «practical wisdom». By reading Hegel not as the philosopher of synthesis but as the philosopher who has most fully explored the notion of «pratical wisdom», Ricoeur reminds us that Hegelian forgiveness rests on the very renounciation by everybody of their partiality, on the acceptance of the idea by each individual that he/she is to abandon what is identical to himself/herself, on the consensus both of he who forgives and he who is forgiven to become other than themselves. «Practical wisdom», claim Ricoeur and Abel, does not consist in abandoning the tragic, but in abandoning onself to the tragic, that is to a wisdom capable of dealing with the destructive effects of disagreement and of enabling the main actors to assume they themselves disagree on what divides them. It is against this wall that «moral forgiveness» crashes and in relation to this wall that it is difficult to place onseself: the parties would rather go on killing one another – an act which paradoxically deludes them they are still communicating – rather than surrender to the idea that they disagree. How can one therefore overcome this heterogeneity of languages, of values, of incommensurable memories? The path recommened by Abel – which we believe can be taken – is to undertake to conceive of forgiveness as the virtue of compromise, a «compromise» which obviously he doesn't see as the mere juxtaposition of two points of view. The disagreement (différend), anyway, as Lyotard teaches, is never reduced. But how can one forgive when confronted with the irreducible? If one attempts to reply, the line of reasoning becomes, if anything, even more complex. Forgiveness here is the the virtue of compromise in the sense that it does not claim, like «moral forgiveness», to re-establish reciprocity, it does not claim to be the starting point of the mutual recognition of the opposing parties. As the terms of the disagreement are incommensurable they are The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 251 neither symmetrical nor asymmetrical. Between them there is no contradiction, there is neither a main nor a secondary aspect, there is neither new nor old. Above all there is neither a winner nor a loser. In other words: what is incommensurable one moment cannot stop being so the next moment, that is the moment the other party in the disagreement is recognised (for example inasmuch as «minority») and historicised. Forgiveness, where there is disagreement, cannot but intervene a latere of the antagonists. Everybody remains inscribed in his or her past (immemorable for the other party), in his or her language, in his or her history. One accepts to forgive knowing that such irriducibility will never cease. The virtue of compromise therefore consists in managing to abandon the constant return of the two separate versions through the exercise of a pratical wisdom which confers awareness to the antagonists: a) that the disagreement cannot be absorbed and one can only find an agreement which accounts for the disagreement; b) that no final word or shared language can be found in which to formulate the wrong done or suffered; c) that the attempt to create a tale, a narrative sufficiently ample and polycentric to contain the plurality of memories and lead them to a point where they can be reconciled in a virtuous compromise, is plausible; d) that the overlapping of different universes is guaranteed by frail words, which combine heterogeneous modes of discourse; e) that it is impossible to try to know a priori which role each party will fill on the scene: after all, we are confronted with neither a forgiving party nor a forgiven one. It follows: a) that forgiveness is what animates a sort of practical imagination, once accepted there is forever the impossibility of formulating a final judgement capable of saying «at the same time» what is universally right for everybody, and what is right for every single individual; b) that by dilating everybody's language to open a space for cohabitation and for co-presence, foregiveness does not eliminate the past but obliges the parties to defuse individual congealed memories and to start a multi-voice narration through which «I» accept that, like me, the others might say «I»; c) that forgiveness obliges each of us to move, to find a new place in the web of history. Could these be the frail premises for a peace possible even for future generations? 252 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions Schedule 1: Truth Commissions Country Uganda Name of Commission Report title and date of Institution publication Commission of Inquiry Report of the Presidential into the Disappearances Commission of Inquiry of People into the Disappearances of People in Uganda since 25 January 1971, 1975 Period investigated 1971- 1974 Bolivia National Commission of No final report Inquiry into Disappearances Presidential 1967 - 1982 Argentina National Commission on Nunca Mas (Never the Disappeared again), 1985 Presidential 1976 - 1983 Uruguay Commission for the Investigation of the Situation of the Disappeared and Related Events Final report of the Parliamentary Commission for the Investigation of the Situation of the Disappeared and Related Events Zimbawe Commission of Inquiry Final report not published Uganda 1973 - 1982 Presidential 1983 Commission of Inquiry Did not finish its work into Violations of Human Rights Presidential 1962 - 1986 Philippines Commission on Human Rights Presidential 1972 - 1986 Chile National Commission for Report of the National Presidential Truth and Reconciliation Commission for Truth and Reconciliation, 1991 1973 - 1990 Did not finish its work The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions Report title and date of publication Commission's report, 1992 253 Country Name of Commission Institution Chad Commission of Inquiry into the Crimes and Misappropriations Committed by ExPresident Habre, His Accomplices and/or Accessories Sudafrica Commission of Enquiry into Certain Allegations made by ex- ANC prisoners, 1992 Germania German Parliament's Final Report, 1999 Study Commission for the Assessment of History and Consequences of the SED Dictatorship in Germany El Salvador Commission on the Truth From Madness to Hope, United Nations 1980 - 1991 for El Salvador 1993 Rwanda International Commission Report of the Nonof Investigation on International governmental Human Rights Violations Commission of international in Rwanda since October Investigation on Human organizations 1, 1990 Rights Violations in Rwanda since October 1, 1990, 1993 Presidential Report of the ANC Commission of Enquiry into Certain Allegations made by ex- ANC prisoners, 1992 Parliamentary South-Africa Commission of Enquiry Report of the ANC into Certain Allegations Commission of Enquiry, of Cruelty and Human 1993 Rights Abuses against ANC Prisoners Period investigated 1982 - 1990 1979 - 1991 1949 - 1989 1990 - 1993 1979 - 1991 254 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions Schedule 2: Summary on Amnesty Decisions - Truth and Reconciliation Commission, 1.11.2000 STATUS Granted/refused No status 1.11.2000 54 24 (1.7.2000) Duplication 37 Scheduled 88 Withdrawn 248 Decision o/s 302 Chamber 142 Hearable 94 (1.7.2000) Granted 849 Refused 5392 Grand Total 7112 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 255 Bibliography A BEL O. (1993), Ce que le pardon vient faire dans l’histoire, in «Esprit», mai-juin, pp.90-101. A BEL O. (2000), Le pardon, ou comment revenir au monde ordinaire, in «Esprit», août-septembre, pp. 72-87. A LLEN J. (1999), Balancing Justice and Social Unity: Political Theory and the Idea of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission, in «University of Toronto Law Journal», vol. XLIX, No.3, pp. 315-353. BALBONI M., Da Norimbergaa alla Corte penale internazionale, in ILLUMINATI G., STORTONI L., VIRGILIO M. (2000) (edited by), Crimini internazionali tra diritto e giustizia. Dai tribunali internazionali alle Commissioni verità e riconciliazione ,Torino, Giappichelli, pp. 3-27. BASSIOUNI M.C. (1996), International Crimes: Ius Cogens and Obligatio Erga Omnes, in «Law and Contemporary Problems», vol. 59, No. 4, pp. 63-74. BASSIOUNI M.C. (2000), The Need for International Accountability and the Protection of Victims in the Context of International Humanitarian Law, Tenth United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders, Vienna, Austria, 10-17 April 2000, A/CONF.187/NGO.1: Offenders and Victims: Accountability and Fairness in the Justice Process, pp. 17-54. BETTINI M. (2000), Forgiveness as Gift, Forgiveness as Identity, Report submitted to the Conference «History, Truth and Justice. The 20th Century and its crimes», Siena, 16-18 March 2000. BORAINE A.(1994), A Project on Transitional Justice, Ronel, CapeTown. BORAINE A. (2000), Dall’Apartheid al nuovo Sudafrica, Comunication at the Conference «Verità e riconciliazione per il III Millennio», Milano, May 2000. CALZINI P. (2000), Order and Justice in the International System, Report submitted to the Conference «History, Truth and Justice. The 20th Century and its Crimes», Siena, 16-18 March 2000. CARON C. (1999), Truth and Justice in South Africa, in «Human Rights Brief», vol. 6, pp. 32-33. CERETTI A. (2000), Mediazione penale. In-contrare una norma, in CERETTI A. ( edited by), Studi in ricordo di Giandomenico Pisapia, vol III, Criminologia, Milano, Giuffrè. CERETTI A., M ANNOZZI G., Restorative Justice. Theoretical Aspects and Applied Models, Tenth United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders, Vienna, Austria, 10-17 April 2000, A/CONF.187/NGO.1: Offenders and Victims: Accountability and Fairness in the Justice Process, pp. 55-97. COHEN S. (2001), States of Denial. Knowing about Atrocities and Suffering, Oxford, Blackwell. 256 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions CRAINZ G. (2000), La giustizia sommaria in Italia dopo la seconda guerra mondiale, Report submitted to the Conference «History, Truth and Justice. The 20th Century and its Crimes», Siena, 16-18 March 2000. DUMONT H. (2000), Le pardon, une valeur de justice et d'espoir, un plaidoyer pour la tolérance et contre l'oubli, in «Canadian Journal of Criminology», 42, 3, pp. 355-379. ELLIS S.M. (1996), Purging the Past: the Current State of Lustration Laws in the Former Communist Bloc, «Law and Contemporary Problems», vol. 59, No. 4, pp. 181-196. FERRAJOLI L., (1989), Diritto e ragione. Teoria del garantismo penale, Bari-Roma, Laterza. FLORES M. (1999), Verità senza vendetta. L’esperienza della Commissione sudafricana per la verità e la riconciliazione, Roma, Manifestolibri. FLORES M. (2000), Confrontare le atrocità: il ruolo dello storico, Report submitted to the Conference «History, Truth and Justice. The 20th Century and its crimes», Siena, 16-18 March 2000. GARRETT G.S. (2000), Models of Transitional Justice - A Comparative Analysis, Report submitted to the Conference International Studies Association 41st Annual Convention, Los Angeles, 14-18 March 2000. GENTILI A. M., LOLLINI A. (2000), L’esperienza delle Commissioni per la verità e la riconciliazione: il caso sudafricano in una prospettiva giuridico-politica, in ILLUMINATI G., STORTONI L., VIRGILIO M. (edited by), Crimini internazionali tra diritto e giustizia. Dai tribunali internazionali alle Commissioni verità e riconciliazione, Torino, Giappichelli, pp. 163-215. GINZBURG C. (1991), Il giudice e lo storico. Considerazioni in margine al processo Sofri, Torino, Einaudi. GINZBURG C. (2000), Rapporti di forza. Storia, retorica, prova, Milano, Feltrinelli. GOLDSTONE J.R. (1996), Justice as a Tool for Peace Making: Truth Commissions and International Criminal Tribunals, «International Law and Politics», vol. 28, pp. 485-503. HAINER P.B. (1994), Fifteen Truth Commissions – 1974 to 1994, «Human Rights Quarterly», vol. 16, pp. 597-655. HAINER P.B. (1996), International Guidelines for the Creation and Operation of Truth Commissions: a Preliminary Proposal, «Law and Contemporary Problems», vol. 59, No. 4, pp. 173-180. HAMBER B. (1995), Dealing with the Past and the Psychology of Reconciliation, Communication at the 4th International Symposium on the Contributions of Psychology to Peace, Cape Town, 27 June 1995. HAMBER B. (1997), Living with the Legacy of Impunity: Lessons for South Africa about Truth, Justice and Crime in Brazil, in «Latin American Report», University of South Africa (UNISA), Centre for Latin American Studies, vol. 13, No. 2, pp. 4-16. HAMBER B. (1998), Who Pays for Peace? Implications of the Negotiated Settlement for Reconciliation, Transformation and Violence in a Post- The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 257 Apartheid South Africa, London, Catholic Institute for International Relations, London Voluntary Sector Resource Centre. ILLUMINATI G., STORTONI L., VIRGILIO M. (2000) (edited by), Crimini internazionali tra diritto e giustizia. Dai Tribunali internazionali alle Commissioni verità e riconciliazione, Torino, Giappichelli. JANKELEVITCH V. (1967) (italian translation 1968), Il perdono, Milano, Istituto di propaganda Libraria. JOINET S. (1997), The Administration of Justice and the Human Rights of Detainees, Annex II, Set of Principles for the Protection and Promotion of Human Rights through Action to combact Impunity – Final Report, Siracusa Impunity Conference. JONAS H. (1984), The Imperative of Responsibility, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press. LANSING P., KING C.J. (1998), South Africa’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission: the Conflict between Individual Justice and National Healing in the Post Apartheid Age, in «Arizona Journal of International and Comparative Law», vol. 15, pp. 753-789 LYOTARD J.F. (1983) (italian translation 1985), Il dissidio, Milano, Feltrinelli. LLEWELLYN J.J., HOWSE R. (1999), Institutions for Restorative Justice: the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, «University of Toronto Law Journal», vol. XLIX, No. 3, pp. 355-388. M ARKEL D. (1999), The Justice of Amnesty? Towards a Theory of Retributivism in Recovering States, in «University of Toronto Law Journal», vol. XLIX, No. 3, pp. 389-445. M ARSHALL T. (1999), Restorative Justice. An Overview, London, H.M.S.O. NAGEL T. (1989), State Crimes: Punishment or Pardon?, Papers and Report of Conference Organized by Justice and Society Program, Queenstown, Aspen Institute, Md.: Wye Centre. NAGEL T. (1991) (Italian translation 1993), I paradossi dell’eguaglianza , Milano, Il Saggiatore. PITCH T. (2001), Il potenziale simbolico del Tribunale internazionale per i crimini contro l’umanità, in FERRARI V., RONFANI P., STABILE S. (edited by), Conflitti e diritti nella società transnazionale, Milano, Franco Angeli. QUARITSCH H. (1991) (Italian translation 1995), Giustizia politica, Milano, Giuffrè. RATNER R.S. (1999), New Democracies, Old Atrocities: an Inquiry in International Law, in «The Georgetown Law Journal», vol. 87, pp. 707-748. RAWLS J. (1972), A Theory of Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press. RAWLS J. (1993), Political Liberalism, New York, Columbia University Press. RESTA E. (1996), Poteri e diritti, Torino, Giappicchelli. RESTA E. (1997), Le stelle e le masserizie. Paradigmi dell’osservatore, Bari-Roma, Laterza. RESTA E. (1998), L’infanzia ferita. Un nuovo patto tra generazioni è il vero investimento politico per il futuro, Bari-Roma, Laterza. 258 The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions RICOEUR P. ( 1986) (Italian translation 1989), Dal testo all’azione, Saggi di ermeneutica, Milano, Jaca Book. RICOEUR P. (2000), Le rôles respectifs du juge et de l’historien, in «Esprit», aoûtseptembre, pp. 48-69. ROUSSET B. (1987), La possibilité philosophique du pardon, in PERRIN M. (edited by), Le pardon. Actes du Colloque organisé par le Centre Histoire des Idées, Université de Picardie, Paris, Beauchesne, pp. 183- 196. SALVATI M. (2001), Amnistia e amnesia nell’Italia del 1946, in FLORES M. (edited by), Storia, verità, giustizia. I crimini del ventesimo secolo, Milano, Bruno Mondatori. SCHARF M.P. (1996), The Letter of the Law: the Scope of the International Legal Obligation to Prosecute Human Rights Crimes, in «Law and Contemporary Problems», vol. 59, No. 4, pp. 41-61. SCHARF M.P. (1999), The Amnesty Exception to the Jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court, in «Cornell International Law Journal», vol. 32, pp. 507-527. SCHEY A.P., SHELTON L.D., ROTH-A RRIAZA N. (1997), Addressing Human Rights Abuses: Truth Commissions and the Value of Amnesty, «Whittier Law Review», vol. 19, pp. 325-344. SILVI M.Q. (2001), Pragmatica del perdono, in «Rivista internazionale di filosofia del diritto», 2, pp. 216-235. SIMPSON G. (1998), A Brief Evaluation of South Africa's Truth and Reconciliation Commission: Some Lessons for Societies in Transition, Centre for the Study of Violence and Reconciliation. TAYLOR T. (1992) (Italian translation 1993), Anatomia dei processi di Norimberga, Milano, Rizzoli. TEITEL R. (2000), Transitional Justice as Liberal Narrative, Report submitted to the Conference «History, Truth and Justice. The 20th Century and Its Crimes», Siena, 16-18 marzo 2000. TOSCANO R. (2000), Il volto del nemico. La sfida dell’etica nelle relazioni internazionali, Milano, Guerini e Associati. TRUTH AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSION (1998), Final Report, website of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission. TUTU D. (1999) (italian translation 2000), Presentation of the Final Reports of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission, in Nociti A., Guarire dall’odio. Come costruire una pace multirazziale: lo straordinario insegnamento del Sudafrica, Milano, Franco Angeli. TUTU D. (1999) (trad. it. 2001), Non c’è futuro senza perdono, Milano, Feltrinelli. UBERTIS G. (1979), Fatto e valore nel sistema probatorio penale, Milano, Giuffrè. UBERTIS G. (1993), La ricerca della verità giudiziale, in UBERT IS G., Sisifo e Penelope. Il nuovo codice di procedura penale dal progetto preliminare alla ricostruzione del sistema, Torino, Giappicchelli. UNITED NATIONS (1996), Subcommission for Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities, Annex II, UN Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1996. The Truth and Reconciliation Commissions 259 VILLA-VICENCIO C. (2000), Living in the Wake of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission. A Retroactive Reflection, Report submitted to the Conference «History, Truth and Justice. The 20th Century and its crimes», Siena, 16-18 March 2000. W ILDSCHUT G. (2000), Il mondo delle vittime, Intervention to the Conference «Verità e riconciliazione per il III Millennio», Milano, May 2000. W OODS M.J. (1998), Reconciling Reconciliation, «UCLA Journal of International Law and Foreign Affairs», vol. 3, 81-127. W RIGHT M. (1991), Justice for Victims and Offenders, Winchester, Waterside. DE ZAYAS A.M. (1990) (italian translation 1996), Il processo di Norimberga davanti al Tribunale militare internazionale, in DEMANDT A. (edited by), Processare il nemico, Einaudi, Torino. ZEHR H. (1990), Changing Lenses: A New Focus for Crime and Justice,WaterlooOntario, Scottsdale. REMARKS ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL COURTS AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSIONS FAUSTO POCAR Professor of International Law, University of Milan, Italy Judge, International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia During the last decades a growing number of emerging democracies have faced the problem of promoting and restoring a climate of reconciliation in the country that might overcome past divisions and conflicts that had characterised the country’s preceding history. Such conflicts and divisions had frequently been marked by serious and widespread violations of fundamental human rights or humanitarian law, depending on whether the violations were attributable to authoritarian governments in peacetime or to governmental agents and individuals in the course of internal armed conflicts. Recent history shows quite a variety of situations of this kind in most regions of the world although it is not the purpose of this paper to analyse them in detail. It has been frequently pointed out that a satisfactory degree of confidence is required for strengthening the new democratic institutions. Such confidence could not effectively be achieved, in such situations, without establishing one credible and definitive truth about the magnitude of the atrocities and abuses committed during the authoritarian rule or in the course of an internal conflict. Different measures may be adopted in this context. Several States – individually but more frequently on the initiative of and in co-operation with international organisations – have established special bodies and entrusted them with the investigation of the violations that occurred over a specific period of time and of the reasons thereof, the identification of the perpetrators, as well as the determination of the relief to be given to victims. In light of their mandate, such bodies have been referred to as Truth Commissions (e.g. in Argentina, Chile, El Salvador, Haiti, Uganda and Chad), Truth and Reconciliation Commissions (e.g. in South Africa and in the draft law of Bosnia and Herzegovina), or another equivalent denomination (like the Commission for Historical Clarification in Guatemala)( 1). See HAINER, (1994), «Fifteen Truth Commissions − 1974 to 1994: A Comparative Study», 16, Human Rights Quarterly, pp.597 ff. (1) 262 International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions Truth and Reconciliation Commissions have been regarded as appropriate tools in light of the fact that criminal prosecutions of individuals responsible for having committed violations of fundamental human rights are frequently difficult in the political situation of States coming out of internal conflicts or a dictatorial government. A Truth Commission, especia lly if accompanied by amnesty laws, may more easily prompt the perpetrators to confess their guilt. More significantly, Truth Commissions have been sometimes regarded as more appropriate for allowing an overall consideration of the violations that occurred. Such a consideration, being officially sanctioned, may also serve the purpose of preserving the memory of past events and of recognising the sufferings of the victims, thus contributing to answer the demands for justice by the people. However, it has also been pointed out that Truth and Reconciliation Commissions may not fully serve their purposes if they are not followed by criminal judicial proceedings, at least as far as the perpetration of major violations of human rights is concerned. A climate of confidence between the people may be difficult to establish if violators of fundamental human rights are not brought to justice. Furthermore, it has also been considered that the conscience of the entire international community would be offended, should crimes of such gravity remain without a trial and the persons responsible for them continue to enjoy impunity. The desirability of prosecuting violators for the crimes committed as a follow up of the activities of these commissions has been, and continues to be, at the centre of legal and political discussions within the countries in which they have been established. But it has to be noted that in recent times the option of criminal prosecution has been followed, both as an alternative to the establishment of a Truth Commission and in conjunction therewith. On the initiative of international organisations, in particular the United Nations, a growing number of criminal tribunals have been set up or envisaged during the last decade, and entrusted with the prosecution of persons responsible for serious violations of human rights and humanitarian law. It is interesting to note that such a course of action has been followed both at the international and at the national level. Besides the International Criminal Trib unal for the former Yugoslavia and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, national ad hoc tribunals have been or are being set up for Sierra Leone, Cambodia, Kosovo and possibly East Timor, with the understanding that an international participatio n would contribute to their composition and management. While some of these tribunals were designed to be the only option to re-establish a climate of confidence in the population of the country concerned, others are intended to co-exist with International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions 263 Truth and Reconciliation Commissions. The former is in particular the case for the international tribunals set up so far, although the establishment of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission is under consideration in Bosnia and Herzegovina, the latter is the case for the national tribunals concerning the four countries mentioned above (2). The trend towards a coexistence of Truth Commissions and judicial criminal bodies (whether international or national with international participation) may or may not appear predominant. But it has to be stressed, in any event, that the option which consists in establishing a Truth Commission that will not be accompanied by the possibility of prosecuting major crimes before judicial bodies will become the more and more difficult, not to say impossible, in the next future. The recent entry into force of the statute of the International Criminal Court on the 1st July 2002 included the pledge, at least for State parties, to prosecute and try persons responsible for genocide, war crimes and crimes against humanity, even when the latter are committed in peacetime. In the absence of the availability of prosecution at the domestic level, the exercise of criminal jurisdiction over such crimes may be taken up by the ICC. The latter’s jurisdiction will therefore concur with actions that may be taken by Truth Commissions established in the State concerned. The choice made by the international community to ensure the prosecution and punishment of persons responsible for major violations of human rights and humanitarian law, whether at the domestic or international level, raises a number of issues so far as the practice of establishing Truth and Reconciliation Commissions is concerned. How far is the coexistence between such commissions and judicial bodies justified? And how can their role and functions be reconciled and harmonised? A positive answer to these questions will require that their respective goals and competence are correctly and clearly defined. In the absence of such a definition, not only may their activities overlap to some extent; they may even represent an obstacle for a full and effective exercise of their competence. As to the goals, the exercise of criminal jurisdiction by international (or quasi-international) tribunals is obviously intended to establish the truth about events that occurred during a civil or ethnic conflict or an authoritarian rule. The establishment of the truth in concrete cases is obviously preliminary to any conviction. In this regard, the functions of an (2) See in particular, with regard to the special court set up in Sierra Leone, Frulli, (2000), «The Special Court for Sierra Leone: Some Preliminary Comments», 11, European Journal of International Law, pp. 857 ff. 264 International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions international tribunal overlap with those of a Truth Commission. However, the legal instruments establishing such tribunals – be they resolutions of the United Nations or the treaty on the Statute of the International Criminal Court − also mention that the crimes falling within their competence have to be regarded as a threat to international peace and security. Therefore, measures adopted to bring to justice persons who are responsible for such crimes are also seen as a contribution to the restoration and maintenance of peace. It is undeniable that such an aim may also be present in the establishment of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission. However, the latter’s contribution to peace and wellbeing of a country or a region may be, and has sometimes been, based on the opposite view, that persons responsible for serious crimes should not necessarily be brought to justice. Just to make an example, a decision to grant amnesty to perpetrators with a view to favouring national reconciliation would certainly claim to contribute to peace. But the same would also clearly obstruct an international tribunal in achieving its goal, which is to contribute to peace by means of submitting those perpetrators to justice. How should the balance be set? Should one of the two bodies take priority over the other? And if so which one? Or should the respective areas of competence be coordinated in a different way? As a first step, it is submitted that areas should be identified, which would be clearly specific to the functions that can better be performed by each body. There are activities that an international criminal tribunal or court (or even a domestic court) would no be able to carry out in its capacity as a judicial body. Other activities, in turn, would not be performed properly by a Truth and Reconciliation Commission, and would have to be handed over to judicial institutions in any event. Such a preliminary identification of areas specific to each institution would clarify their fundamental respective functions and form the basis for a co-ordinated approach (3). One first area in which an international tribunal would appear to have a limited role to play concerns an analysis of all the causes of the conflict or of the authoritarian rule during which the criminal violations occurred. There is no doubt that the judicial activity of an international court may occasionally apply a consideration of relevant aspects related to the origins of the environment, which may have led to the commission of (3) In a recent speech, delivered on 12 May 2001 at a conference in Sarajevo, the President of the ICTY identified some limitations on the activity of the International Tribunal, and suggested that certain activities could be carried out by a Truth and Reconciliation Commission. Some of these limitations are considered hereafter. International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions 265 the crimes submitted to it for trial. However, it is not for a judicial body to analyse all the historical, economic and social causes having determined the existence of such an environment. On one hand, a tribunal has the duty to review the events only from the specific angle of the criminal responsibility of the perpetrators. On the other hand, it is self-evident that a court cannot undertake a systematic review of all events, but is bound to limit its consideration to events that are brought to its attention in the indictments. A systematic review will nonetheless be essential for the purposes of an effective and long-standing reconciliation between the people in the region concerned. Only in the light of such a review, accompanied by a wide and efficient programme of information, will current and future generations avoid falling into confrontations of a similar nature as those that already occurred. A review of this kind can be effectively performed by a truth commission and would justify by itself its establishment. A second area of specific competence of a truth commission, related to the one just mentioned, is to build up a collective memory of the events, based upon a discussion open to all, so that it may be shared by all individuals in the region concerned. The exercise of criminal jurisdiction by a court will certainly play a role also in this respect, but, due to the nature of the procedural requirements for performing a judicial activity, it cannot be the appropriate forum for an open discussion about the past. Its contribution will always be incomplete and limited to the perspective of a consideration of the events that resulted in major violations of fundamental human rights or humanitarian law. There is no doubt that a Truth Commission will provide a more general forum to this effect. In this context, the role to provide a forum for dialogue is stressed by the statutes of the Truth Commissions established so far. Thus, the statute of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission for Sierra Leone declares that the Commission is intended to provide a forum for both victims and perpetrators to tell their stories and facilitate genuine healing and reconciliation. Similarly, the draft law of Bosnia and Herzegovina on the same subject indicates the objective of providing a forum where victims and persons with information about massive human rights violations in the past war can be heard. A third area in which a Truth and Reconciliation Commission may act more efficiently than a tribunal in situations of massive violations of human rights may be in providing reparation for the victims. Actually, providing reparation to victims of crime falls in general terms within the judicial function of a court and is frequently done by national courts in accordance with the provisions of their respective criminal procedural laws. However, while a court may provide reparation to identified victims of a 266 International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions specific crime, it is hardly possible for a court to achieve the same result when massive violations are at issue. This is especially the case with victims of armed conflicts or of activities of paramilitary groups, where a nexus between identified victims and criminal acts cannot be established. The difficulty of finding a solution to the problem of providing reparation to victims of widespread crime has been underlined on several occasions, and it is not necessary to go back here to the resolutions adopted by international organisations, including the United Nations, on this matter. It is sufficient to appreciate that a satisfactory solution cannot easily be found merely by relying on the judicial function and improving its efficiency. It is not surprising therefore that the question of reparation to victims has not been dealt with in the statutes of the existing International Tribunals, even if it has been later discussed both within the tribunals themselves and within the political bodies that established them. While the reasons for starting a debate on this issue may also go beyond the general issue of providing reparation to victims, the outcome of such a debate is far from being predictable. In any event, it is unlikely that it may lead to increasing the functions of the International Tribunals with a view to including therein the provision of reparation to victims other than the moral reparation resulting from the conviction and sentence of the persons responsible for the crimes. A Truth Commission – on the basis of an assessment of the magnitude of the violations suffered by the people affected by the events – would be in a better position to propose appropriate reparations that could be given by the authorities. Besides forms of symbolic or moral reparation designed to take into account the collective nature of the harm suffered by victims, they may include other measures for the rehabilitation of victims of human rights violations, as is envisaged by the Truth and Reconciliation Commission for Sierra Leone. For example, compensation to be provided to victims from a fund available to the commission, whose decisions would not necessarily require the identification of a specific perpetrator. It has to be pointed out, in this connection, that the statute of the International Criminal Court envisages that a trust fund be established for the benefit of victims of crimes within the jurisdiction of the Court, and the families of such victims. However, although the statute gives the Court a role in providing the fund by ordering that money and other property collected through fines or forfeiture is transferred to it, the management of and the distribution from the fund will depend on criteria to be determined by the Assembly of States parties. And it is likely that the trust fund will not managed by the Court in the framework of its judicial functions. International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions 267 The above mentioned issues may easily permit to identify appropr iate criteria for a distribution of competence between international tribunals and Reconciliation Commissions, and to co-ordinate their respective functions and activities. The critical question in this context is whether the persons responsible for offences, which amount to crimes under international law should be prosecuted. In this area the approaches of the two institutions may clearly differ and make it difficult to determine how their role should be co-ordinated. It should be noted, at the outset, that an issue of this nature could arise only as far as a crime will fall within the competence of an international tribunal. The same would apply with respect to a national tribunal with international participation, or also a domestic tribunal to which the prosecution of a crime may have been delegated by an international trib unal. Absent such a situation, the way in which a Reconciliation Commission may deal with crimes committed during a conflict or an authoritarian rule will not interfere with an international tribunal’s activity. The problem would in such a case consist of choosing between the attribution of competence to truth commissions to deal with crimes, and the exercise of criminal jurisdiction through ordinary domestic courts. When a crime falls within the jurisdiction of an international tribunal, it would appear obvious that the concurrent competence of a truth commission to deal with the same crime requires a co-ordination in order to avoid conflicts. A clear rule establishing whose competence takes priority would certainly be welcome in such a situation. Any unclear approach would create misunderstandings and possibly lead to contradictory decisions that may affect the credibility of both institutions. In light of the consideration that both of them pursue the goal of establishing peace and reconciliation through means of action that largely differ, the credibility of both should be preserved, by permitting both of them to perform effectively their basic functions. It has to be noted, however, that the choice of establishing an international criminal tribunal for the prosecution of persons responsible for the violation of serious violations of human rights law as well as of humanitarian law has already been made by the international community. Thus, the only reasonable conclusion appears to be that international tribunals should enjoy priority over truth commissions. The issue may however be raised, and has indeed been raised, whether a co-ordination between the activity of an international tribunal or court and that of a truth commission should be made in light of the gravity of the crimes falling within the competence of the tribunal. In particular, it is suggested that the position of the perpetrator should be taken into 268 International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions account, with a view to submitting to the jurisdiction of an international tribunal only high ranking persons and leaders. Truth commissions’ competence will consequently be limited to dealing with crimes committed by low ranking executioners. Such an approach may be valuable, provided that clear criteria are applied in order to decide which body will be competent in a concrete case. A borderline between high and low ranking perpetrators may indeed not be always easy to determine in a given situation and may have to take into account individual qualifications and factual circumstances. Should such a solution be adopted, it would probably be convenient to leave to the international tribunal to decide whether to exercise uj risdiction on the basis of an assessment of the concrete situation and its implications. It cannot be ignored, however, that other factors should be taken into account in the co-ordination between truth commissions and international tribunals as regards the prosecution of perpetrators. National jurisdiction will necessarily play a significant role in this matter. It is submitted that a correct co-ordination can not be merely between international tribunals and Truth Commissions but should include the attribution of cases to domestic courts. There will certainly be cases that, although their submission to an international tribunal may be regarded as not justified, will still require to be tried by a court of law rather than considered by a Truth Commission. Whatever approach is followed and whatever co-ordination is put in place, it cannot be denied that Truth Commissions should not be excluded altogether from dealing with situations revealing the commission of serious crimes against humanity or war crimes. Confessions of perpetrators before a Truth Commission may be extremely valuable in order to promote national reconciliation. It has been stressed that they constitute recognition not only of the commission of mass crimes but also of the suffering inflicted on the victims. It must be pointed out however that perpetrators would be encouraged to admit their crimes before a commission only if they may derive some benefit from doing so. The problem is therefore to identify what kind of benefit may be made available to them and which body should make it available. At the national level the problem has sometimes been approached by granting amnesties to perpetrators who voluntarily participate in the work of a truth and reconciliation commission. That has been the case, for example, of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission for South Africa(4).However, as has already been mentioned, such an approach would (4) See DUGARD, (1988), «Reconciliation and Justice: The South African Experience», 8, Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems, p. 277. International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions 269 clearly constitute an intrusion in the work of an international tribunal and obstruct the performance of its functions. It would risk nullifying its activity and the reasons for its existence. Moreover, since an amnesty would result in the recognition of the impunity of the perpetrator, it is doubtful whether and how far it would really contribute to the foundation of a solid democracy based on national reconciliation, in partic ular when crimes against humanity and war crimes are at issue. International bodies, such as the Human Rights Committee under the International Covenant on Civil and political Rights, have always regarded amnesty laws with great suspicion ( 5), though especially outside the context of a truth and reconciliation commission. They have pointed out that amnesty laws may sanction the spreading of a climate of impunity that would favour further violations of human rights. On the other hand, it has to be noted that not all perpetrators may be brought to justice and that certain benefits may also be given to perpetrators before international or national courts, when they cooperate with the establishment of the truth. A suggested solution of this dilemma would consist in excluding the possibility for truth commissions to grant amnesties, but allowing or even encouraging them to make their assessment of the behaviour of the perpetrators known to the prosecutors of international tribunals. Their recommendation would allow the voluntary participation in the reconciliation process carried out by the commission to be taken into account as a mitigating circumstance in sentencing, provided that a perpetrator confirms his co-operative attitude before an international tribunal by pleading guilty. Whether such an approach would be sufficient to encourage perpetrators to appear before a Truth Commission to admit their crimes is questionable. But the shortcomings inherent in allowing a Truth Commission to grant amnesty are admittedly greater, unless the granting of amnesty is followed on by measures of publicity such as to be equivalent to a criminal sanction in the eyes of the civil society. It is clear, however, that a satisfactory solution has not been found so far in international and national practice. In conclusion, although different forms of co-operation between truth and reconciliation commissions and international tribunals may be envisaged, they should be compatible with a framework that would ensure the priority of the activity of the international tribunals when serious (5) See POCAR , (1998), La impunidad frente al Comité de derechos humanos de la ONU, "Contra la impunidad. Simposio contra la impunidad y en defensa de los derechos humanos" (Plataforma Argentina contra la Impunidad ed.), Barcelona, at 159 ff. 270 International Criminal Courts and Reconciliation Commissions violation of human rights and humanitarian law are at issue. Thus, only when an international tribunal would decide not to prosecute a crime, either directly or through domestic criminal courts, could a truth commission be entrusted with the competence to deal with it and to set aside, as the case may be, criminal prosecution. It must be stressed, however, that the role that the la tter can perform cannot be underestimated in the delicate area of bringing about a reconciliation process within the context of emerging democracies. JOÃO TIAGO SILVEIRA Director do Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, Lisboa, Portugal Madame Simone Rozès, Presidente da Sociedade Internacional de Defesa Social para uma Política Criminal Humanista (SIDS), Senhor Professor De Figueiredo Dias, Vice-Presidente da SIDS, Senhor Edouardo Vetere, Director do Centro para a Prevenção do Crime Internacional das Nações Unidas, Senhor Bruti Liberati, Secretário-Geral da SIDS, Gostaria, muito rapidamente, de felicitar a SIDS pela organização deste XIV Congresso de Defesa Social, no qual se discutiram temas relevantíssimos quanto ao papel do Direito Penal nas sociedades. Questões como quais os diferentes níveis de responsabilidade em função dos sujeitos em causa, qual a melhor forma de aferir e avaliar a efectividade das soluções, qual a função dos Direitos do Homem e o seu papel simultaneamente legitimador e limitador do papel do Direito Penal ou questões como qual o critério a utilizar para determinar a necessidade de uma resposta penal e alternativas a essa resposta são, sem dúvida, questões da ordem do dia. É por essa razão que gostaria de felicitar a SIDS, na pessoa da sua Presidente, pela organização deste Congresso e, particularmente, pela sua organização em Portugal. É com muito gosto que vos acolhemos e são sempre, naturalmente, bem vindos no nosso País. Uma última palavra, finalmente, para agradecer o trabalho do secretariado da SIDS e do Dr. Miguel Romão, consultor do Gabinete de Política Legislativa e Planeamento do Ministério da Justiça, incansáveis na organização deste Congresso. SIMONE ROZES président de la SIDS Monsieur le Directeur, vous venez de nous remercier, ce qui est très aimable car c'est à nous de vous adresser de très profonds remerciements pour tout ce que vous avez fait pour nous! Nous ne l'oublions pas et nous savons que, si nous avons pu tenir notre quatorzième Congrès, c'est bien grâce à vous, aux efforts du Ministère de la Justice qui ont été constants, grâce aussi à Monsieur le Professeur Jorge de Figueiredo Dias. Nous avons pu bénéficier de facilités remarquables. Croyez bien que ce fut un plaisir de travailler dans des conditions aussi exceptionnelles. Le Centre culturel de Belém est magnifique et nous avons apprécié de pouvoir disposer de ces locaux superbes et modernes face au merveilleux ensemble du Monastère de Jeronimos et de l'une des plus belles villes du Monde. Nous vous en sommes reconnaissants. Nous avons eu aussi beaucoup de plaisir à nous retrouver dans un cadre moins solennel mais très pittoresque, au bord du Tage, pour le dîner que le Ministère de la Justice nous a offert si généreusement. Il est donc bien évident que les remerciements les plus chaleureux ne peuvent s'exprimer que de ce côté-ci! Je veux aussi remercier tous les participants, nos amis, ici présents. Moins nombreux que d'habitude en raison des circonstances vous avez tous tenus à nous apporter votre contribution et je tiens à souligner la qualité des rapports présentés et des échanges intervenus. Comme vous le signaliez il y a un instant, Monsieur le Directeur, nous allons partir, les uns et les autres, avec diverses pistes de réflexion sur les problèmes qui se posent désormais à nous et qui sont si différents de ceux qui nous occupent habituellement tant par leur contenu que par l'approche qui doit être la nôtre dans un contexte qui connaît d'aussi profondes mutations. Notre dernière séance vient encore de confirmer la nécessité d'un approfondissement des questions posées. Nous devons les aborder sous l'angle particulier du Mouvement de défense sociale. La recherche d'une politique criminelle capable de permettre à toute société de vivre paisiblement est certes notre objectif, mais nous savons en même temps que «tous les moyens ne sont pas bons» et qu'il faut beaucoup de vigilance pour que les impératifs de sécurité indispensables ne remettent pas en cause le respect des garanties qui s'attachent aux droits de l'homme. Trouver un juste équilibre est bien notre ambition et je suis heureuse de constater que ce souci est aussi partagé par les plus je u- 276 Séance de clôture/ Closing Session nes d'entre nous qui s'impliquent avec force dans ces travaux. Je les en remercie. Ils appartiennent à cette génération montante dont nous nous préoccupons, car il est dans notre rôle d'être habité par l'inquiétude sur la qualité de l'héritage que nous leur transmettons! Mais j'emporte de cette réunion, de leur contribution, la réconfortante certitude de leur détermination et de leur engagement dans notre Mouvement. Avant de nous séparer je voudrais vous demander, Monsieur le Directeur, d'assurer Madame le Ministre de la Justice de notre très réelle gratitude ainsi que tous ceux qui ont travaillé auprès d'elle à la réussite de ce Congrès. Je me tourne enfin, «but not least», vers les interprètes sans le squels nos débats et travaux seraient vains. Merci, infiniment. LES CONGRES INTERNATIONAUX DE LA SIDS ISSD INTERNATIONAL CONGRESSES Ier Congrès San Remo, 1947 Pour la transformation des actuels systèmes pénaux et pénitentiaires en systèmes d’éducation et de traitement en rapport avec la personnalité individuelle des délinquants. IIe Congrès Liège, 1949 La personnalité humaine du point de vue des droits de la société dans ses rapports avec les droits de l’homme. IIIe Congrès Anvers, 1954 L’individualisation de la sentence et de l’exécution (observation et resocialisation). IVe Congrès Milan, 1956 La prévention des infractions contre la vie humaine et l’intégrité de la personne humaine. Ve Congrès Stockholm, 1958 L’intervention administrative ou judiciaire d’adolescence socialement inadaptées. en matière d’enfance et VIe Congrès Belgrade, 1961 Dans quelle mesure se justifient des différences dans le statut légal et le traitement des mineurs, des jeunes adultes et des délinquants?. VIIe Congrès Lecce, 1966 Les interdictions professionnelles. VIIIe Congrès Paris 1971 Les techniques de l’individualisation judiciaire. 278 Les Congrés internationaux de la SIDS IXe Congrès Caracas, 1976 Marginalité sociale et justice. Xe Congrès Thessalonique, 1981 La ville et la criminalité. XIe Congrès Buenos Aires, 1986 L’internationalisation des sociétés contemporaines dans le domaine de la criminalité et les réponses du mouvement de défense sociale. XIIe Congrès Paris, 1991 Défense sociale, protection de l'environnement et droits fondamentaux. XIIIe Congrès Lecce, 1996 Défense sociale, corruption, protection de l’administration publique et indépendance de la Justice. XIVe Congrès Lisbonne, 2002 Défense sociale et droit pénal pour la protection des générations futures, en présence des risques nouveaux.