45. gt - sociology of constitutions
Transcrição
45. gt - sociology of constitutions
ANAIS CONGRESSO DO MESTRADO EM DIREITO E SOCIEDADE DO UNILASALLE GT – SOCIOLOGY OF CONSTITUTIONS CANOAS, 2015 3766 FROM NATIONAL TO GLOBAL SETTINGS: IS THE SOCIOLOGY OF CONSTITUTIONS “ON THE MOVE”? Alfons Bora, Henrique Carvalho, Pablo Holmes, ABSTRACT: Social research about the emergence of constitutions in a globalized context deserves prominence among the developments, which claims that sociology of law is “on the move”. This is so, because they differ from traditional understandings of state constitutions (Luhmann 1964, 1993; Habermas 1992), from the ones related to the self-constitution of specific social groups in national states (Sciulli 2010), and from the studies of pre-modern constitutions (Thornhill 2011). This shift relates to thesis of constitutional fragments (Teubner 2012), transconstitutionalism (Neves 2013), transnational Law (Viellechner 2013) and constitutionalism in the global realm (Kjaer 2014). The session focuses on two aspects of this shift: How the movement relying on the basis of global constitutionalism may be sociologically described, and, if and how constitutions beyond the state may emerge as a consequence of this movement. Pablo Holmes advances a critical approach to answer these questions: To him, central to the emergence of legal and political structures in the age of global governance qua global constitutional arrangements, was its imposition from American and European countries under the label of development. Instead of setting up the emergence of constitutions beyond the state, the result of such a movement is described as the tentative substitution of the political by science and/or economy in processes of collectively binding decision-making, which leads to the political exclusion of considerable parts of world’s population. Henrique Carvalho points that as in national states norms arise in the global realm as a reaction to existing demands. As all legal norms, constitutions possess a normative and a social dimension, which integer dynamically the realms of Law, Politics and other specialized social fields. They differ from others, as they correspond to the specific structural support, which guarantees the autonomy of one legal order. Hence, constitutions in the globalized world society, be it of a national State, of an international organization, or a NGO, may be described, as long as these dynamic arrangements are identifiable. Alfons Bora discusses the technocratic production of collective binding decisions (Holmes), and the thesis of constitutional Dimensions (Carvalho) by covering its elementary dynamics in the perspective of Regulation. By addressing post interventionist approaches he develops a concept of societal regulation as any operation of a social system that intentionally aims at 3767 deciding, defining, or setting the state of another system (target system) with regard to the production of the commonweal (Gemeinwohl), which allows to analyze post-national decision-making and constitutions as specific forms of regulation. KEYWORD: constitutions; globalization; expertise-based decision-making; legal norms; regulation. 1 INTRODUCTION Sociologically oriented discussions related to the emergence of constitutions in a globalized context have deserved in the last decades a prominent position among the developments, which suggests the characterization of a sociology of law “on the move”. This is so, because they differ from understandings of constitutions within theories of society (Luhmann 1993, Habermas 1992), which are mostly focused on state constitutions. It advances also a step beyond theories of legal pluralism related to the self-constitution of regulatory settings vis-a-vis specific social groups within national states (Sciulli 2010), and even from the studies, which focus on the identification of constitutions or constitutional structures in pre-modern epochs (Thornhill 2011). At least in two perspectives a commonality related to the studies of constitutions in a global or transnational context may be highlighted: The first one says, that all these theories and empirical studies take as point of departure, that a shift from national concentrated actions, communications, discourses, processes and structures to these, which go beyond states territory might be seen as a reality. This may be illustrated by thesis of Governing beyond the State (Zürn 1997), post-national Constellation (Habermas 1998), the Law of open States (di Fabio 1998), constitutional fragments (Teubner 2012), transconstitutionalism (Neves 2013), constitutional evolution in times of global governance (Holmes 2013), transnationalization of Law (Viellechner 2013) and constitutionalism in the global realm (Kjaer 2014). The second commonality of these theses addresses the question, if real constitutions may be already pointed out in contexts beyond the state. When the 3768 major fields are on the one hand concerned with the progressive identification and consolidation of structures and institutions with constitutional quality, which are self-described as global constitutionalization (Peters 2006, Dunnof and Trachtmann 2009), and on the other are the interests focused on the develop of a constitutionalizing agenda for actors beyond the state, which involves a breaking with the paradigm of national settings, also known as global constitutionalism; there are until this moment not quite a lot efforts, which points out where are the transnational constitutions. Taking these commonalities as starting points, the proposed session focuses on basal aspects of this shift of constitutional thinking. From a sociological perspective are the discussions in this panel oriented by the following questions: Firstly, how the movement relying on the basis of global constitutionalism may be sociologically described? With this first question it is not intended to repeat the ideas, that globalization relates with the worldwide connection of communications, discourses or practices. Beyond that it is for this group relevant, to research if and how this changes relate to a – using the congress terminology –, “move” of the legal to arenas beyond the state. Secondly, focuses this panel on the question, if and how constitutions beyond the state may emerge as a consequence of the movement, which is addressed in the point above. Hear it is intended, not only to question if a global, transnational, international or regional constitution may be pointed out, but to address how is it happened, and also how is the emergence of these new constitutions relates to the “move” in the social structures. 2 CONSTITUTIONAL ORDERS BEYOND THE STATE? TRANSNATIONAL CONSTITUTIONAL PLURALISM, ITS ENLIGHTENMENTS AND PITFALLS In today’s world society, constitutional theories1 seem to converge in assigning an emerging role to legal forms of regulation not bound by political systems. Several approaches try to grasp the diversity and multiplicity of different layers, levels and stake-holders which constitute the post-national constellation of See: Holmes, The rhetoric of legal fragmentation and its discontents, Utrecht Law Review 7, 2011, p. 117-119. 1 3769 constitutional orders in today’s global law. Some point out to the “state-making dimension of private law” 2 on the transnational level3, others prefer not to assign a privilege for the private dimension of transnational law, rather assuming the hybridity of transnational forms which cannot be described on the basis of that national-centered distinctions.4 And, yet, some others refer to an inflationary talk about the “transnational” that would miss the point in its description of those constitutional changes in course in our days, by dismissing too quickly the National-State as an important actor on the global realm and within a still existing international system.5 As I understand it, there is an evident paradigmatic shift within constitutional theory that has partially to do with an ongoing crisis of representative politics and liberal democracy.6 Indeed, the paradoxes of national constitutionalism became a pervasive concern in legal and political thought7, what seems to have resonance also in the social movements of the last decade. And, although the limits and contradictions of the Keynesian-Westphalian arrangement8 can be traced back in some measure to political struggles within the nation states, important limitations for the scope of action of the state clearly arise from the pressures of a 2 See, for example: Wai, The Interlegality of Transnational Private Law, p. 107-127; 3 Zumbansen, Law after the Welfare State: Formalism, Functionalism and the Ironic Turn of Reflexive Law, Verfügbar im Internet: http://www.comparativeresearch.net/papers.jsp (last visit: 11/06/2011); Caruso, Daniela: Private Law and State-Making in the Age of Globalization, in: NYU Journal of International Law and Politics 12, 2007, S. 1-74 4 Heyvert, Veerle: Hybrid Norms in International Law, in: LSE, Law, Society and Economy Working Papers 06/2009, London School of Economics, 2009, verfügbar im Internet: http://www.lse.ac.uk/collections/law/wps/wps1.htm (Last visit: /05/12/2011); Sand, IngerJohanne. Hybrid Law – Law in a Global Society of Differentiation and Change, in: Calliess, Gralf-Peter/ Fischer-Lescano, Andreas/ Wielsch, Dan/ Zumbansen, Peer (Org.), Soziologische Jurisprudenz. Festschrift für Gunther Teubner zum 65. Geburtstag, Berlin, De Gruyter, 2009, p. 871-886. 5 Marcelo Neves, Transconstitucionalism, 2009; Kjaer, Constitutionalism on the Global Realm. 6 . Siehe: Fischer-Lescano/Teubner, Regime-Kollisionen, S. 57-65. 7 Hans Lindahl, Constitutent Power and Reflexive Identity: Towards an Ontology of Collective Selfhood, in: Martin Loughin & Neil Walker (Orgs.). The Paradoxes of Constitutionalism, 2008, p. 9-25; Emilios Christodoulidis, Against Substitution: The constitutional Thinking of Dissensus, in: Idem, p. 189-209. 8 This expression was conceived by Fraser. See: Nancy Fraser, “Reframing Justice in a Globalizing World“. New Left Rewiew, Vol 35, pp. 69-88, 2005. 3770 transnationalizing economic system.9 Besides, we can easily notice the emergence of a theoretical consciousness within constitutional thought about the transnational character of social communication in a world society that can only be understood from a global perspective.10 The proliferation of global legal regimes beyond the territorial boundaries of the national constitutional regimes11 shapes an emerging theoretical vocabulary that acknowledges the evolving dynamics of fragmented normative orders on the transnational realm.12 And such a new arrangement can barely be described by the semantics of national constitutionalism, and even less by the vocabulary of the old European “democratic” traditions, be it in its Jacobin-inclusive or in its liberal elitist-versions. Moreover, this emerging transnational legal constellation constrains the operation of national and international normative orders.13 National-centered constitutionalism faced several critiques in the last decades.14 According to its critics, it would wrongfully nurture an excess of expectations vis-à-vis the constitutional legal vocabulary, as if the constitutional order could translate the totality of social complexity into the language of law, making it possible for the state to interfere in every social sphere such as contractual market relations, technological development, risk assessment etc.15 Further, national constitutionalism would suffer from an ethnocentric (not to say Eurocentric) bias, being caught into the pitfalls of its way to frame social conflicts in thoroughly different realities according to the narrow political vocabulary of a 9 John Ruggie (1998), "Globalization and the Embedded Liberalism Compromise: The End of an Era?" In: STREEK, Wolfgang (org.). Internationale Wirtschaft, nationale Demokratie. Herausforderungen für die Demokratietheorie. Frankfurt, Campus, pp. 7998 10 There are though good reasons to believe that one of the reasons of the crisis of national constitutioanlism can be 11 Somek. 12 Teubner, Globalzivilverfassung: Alternative zur Staatszentrierten Verfassungstheorie, in: Neves/Voigt (Hrsg.), Die Staaten der Weltgesellschaft, Niklas Luhmans Staatsverständnis, S. 119-122. 13 For many examples and cases, see: Neves, Moritz. 14 Zu diesen Kritiken zusammenfassend: Walker, The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism, The Modern Law Review 65, 2002, S. 320-33. 15 For the paradoxes of juridification, see: Gunther Teubner, Juridification: concepts, aspects, limits, solutions. In: Gunther Teubner (org.). Juridification of social spheres: a comparative analysis in the areas of labor, corporate, antitrust and social welfare law. Berlin, De Gruyter, pp. 3-48. 3771 very specific and peculiar – north-Atlantic – social context. This limitation would lead to a misconception of different political realities as lacking “adequate constitutionalization”, making furthermore invisible the historical colonial asymmetries which shaped these scenarios. In this piece, I will face the challenge of theoretically conceiving of the transnational constitutional constellation of today’s world society, following the thread let by Gunther Teubner’s theory of transnational constitutional pluralism. From my point of view, this is in many ways one of the most well succeeded theoretical endeavors on this subject. Transnational constitutional pluralism pictures the plurality of legal orders as emerging constitutional orders beyond the state. Further, it brings the concept of constitution to its limit, broadening its scope to the manifold transnational regimes operating beyond and “beneath” the territorial boundaries of national states.16 According to its pluralist standpoint, the proliferation of normative global villages and its emergence as global constitutional fragments would correspond to the radical functional differentiation of a world society which, in the last decade, has become more and more a-topical17, relying its reproduction mainly on rapid and flexible communication media as money and scientific knowledge, as they are produced and managed within – also atopical – private organizations.18 Therefore, it would be at least misleading to confine the concept of legal validity to the territorial limits of politically constitutionalized legal orders. Transnational constitutionalism claims, with support on systems theory, that the concept of legal constitutions must be for once and for all decoupled of its political roots,19 being extended to the increasing transnational – private, hybrid of semi-public – Albert, Legalisation or Global Law Formation. On Evolution of Law in World-Society. Presentation at the CENTRAL-conference on »Transnational Business in the Age of Globalization« Münster, 26 October 2001. Verfügbar bei der Working Group on WorldSociety, Universität Bielefeld. Kritisch zur Möglichkeit eines entterritorialisierten Rechts: Lindahl, A-Legality: Postnationalism and the Question of Legal Boundaries, S. 32ff. 17 Teubner, Constitutional Fragments, Willke, Atopia. 18 Fischer Lescano/Teubner, Fragmentierung des Weltrechts, S. 37ff.; kritisch dazu: Brunkhorst, Die Legitimationskrise der Weltgesellschaft, in: Albert/Stichweh (Hrsg.), Weltstaat und Weltstaatlichkeit, S. 68-76. 19 Teubner, Globale Zivilverfassungen, S. 119. 16 3772 normative orders that operate as self-contained legal regimes responsible for the respective internal management problems regarding legal validity. 20 Teubner’s description is undoubtedly very creative. And, although I deem his diagnose as accurate with regard to the fragmentation and privatization of transnational law as well as to his perception of the shortcomings of the Statecentered semantics of constitutionalism, it seems that the consequences he draws from his interpretation are not as appropriate. The assumption that selfconstitutionalizing transnational regimes, as they operate in world society, can foster an internal dynamics of responsivity, able to function as an functional equivalent to the inclusive dynamics of democratic national politics seem to me to lack sociological explanation. This becomes explicit if we accept the premise that social exclusion as a problem of access to functional performances cannot rely on an equivalent to the positive outputs of the political State on the global Realm, needing to be faced by the responsive operation of self-constitutionalized legal regimes. In what follows, I will present sociological-structural arguments to support the assumption that the transnationalization of law without politics in today’s world society seem to radicalize the pervasive exclusionary tendencies of modern functional differentiation, without presenting the functional equivalents to the inclusive forces of political constitutionalism. 3 CONSTITUTIONS AS LEGAL NORMS IN THE GLOBALIZED WORLD SOCIETY21 In order to grasp the change, which lays behind the shift from exclusive national to global settings, I firstly advance a discussion in the realm of globalization theory, specially related to its connections to the social fields of Fischer-Lescano, Luhmanns Staat und der transnationale Konstitutionalismus, in: Neves/Voigt (Org.), Die Staaten der Weltgesellschaft, Niklas Luhmanns Staatsverständnis, S. 100f. 21 The arguments developed in this section represent a short version of Henrique Carvalho’s PhD thesis, which will be available as book still in 2015. See “Verfassungen in der Weltgesellschaft. Ein systemtheoretischer Beitrag zur Verfassungssoziologie”. Nomos, 2015 (Forthcomming). 20 3773 politics and of law. So as Ulrich Beck22 argues that the national state is a victim of globalization, which destabilizes it, once it has destructive consequences to the fulfillment of its functions, addresses Saskia Sassen23, that neither occupies the national state such a passive function, nor leads the globalization to the end of the national state. Quite on the contrary it might be learned from Sasken‘s theses, that the national State in the 70’s stimulated and paved the path, through it communications, practices and structures from a variety of social realms crossed the states boarders24. As triggers of globalization the states did not have shoot their own feet, they remain as leading actors in the global stage. To be a leading actor means that national states are no longer alone on the global stage. This affirmative leads to the question of, who are the new political and legal actors of the globalized world, as well as to the one of, how the development of politics and law beyond the state took place? A first clue may be gained by the analysis of Anne-Marie Slaugther‘s thesis about the disaggregated state25, in which organizations beyond the State emerge. These new subjects possess autonomy when faced with States, so that their decisions are independent from a single State and at the same time are binding to those, which are organizations members. In that sense it is more than plausible from a functional perspective to assure, that such organizations are political decisionmaking actors, once their decisions are binding to its members. They fulfill as well the legal function, as long as these decisions stabilize demands on normative expectations by their congruent generalization. Beyond that the emergence of new autonomous actors means a rupture with traditional forms of international public and private law, as well as with the international relations, once these fields are state-centered and based of the dialogical and negotiating form of decisionmaking. It remains open the question about why political and legal communications break with the limits of states territories and develop in transnational or global realms. Following Michael Zürn’s lead, that a governmental crisis occurs because 22 See Beck 1998. 23 See Sassen 2008. 24 See Sassen 2007. 25 See Slaughter 2004. 3774 the political answers to political demands with a considerable delay26, I advance the argument, that not only politics, but also the law, only expand the horizons, where its communications take place, where there is previously a demand on political or legal decision. So my answer to the question to the posed question may be so formulated: Law and Politics are social realms, which are characterized by a reactive form of operating. So the function of producing collective binding decisions27 depends on, that divergent political position firstly appears. The function of law, as to congruently stabilize normative expectations28, needs as well, that incongruent expectations of such a form, or otherwise formulated: conflicting counterfactual expectations already exist. And in that sense, political and legal structures and institutions – short: organizations – emerge beyond states borders as a reaction to the political and juridical demands, which results from the globalization from other social sectors. Or with other words: Politics and the Law participate in the process of globalization. This leads to the conclusion that the assumption, that these realms are only organized in the form of states, deserves to be actualized. So instead of talking about a world society (Weltgesellschaft)29 we speak of a globalized world society (globalisierte Weltgesellschaft) when the internal differentiation of politics and law includes, together with national states, other actors, so for instance: the autonomous international organizations. This account serves as a setting the scene, on which the second question of this panel might be discussed: So possible constitutions beyond the state (a) evolves the realms of politics and law, which (b) react to transnational or global demands, (c) might originate new autonomous segments – be it regimes, assemblages, organizations, orders –, and (d) co-exist with national states. One way of addressing all these themes at once, on the level of a national state and of organizations beyond the state, may be the assumption that constitutions are legal norms. This sets at first a generalization, so bills (Gesetze), See Zürn 1997. 27 See Luhmann 2000. 28 See Luhmann 1993. 29 Luhmann 1997. To new discussions about this concept of world society, see also: Neves 2012; Teubner 2012; Kjaer 2014; Thornhill 2011. 26 3775 Orderings (Verordnungen) from the Executive and Decisions from Tribunals (Rechtsprechung) might by placed on the category of legal norms. That means for the sociological systems theory to look for structural couplings: on one side at least to a social sector, and on the other to organs, e.g.: tribunals, parliaments and executives. These constitute and reciprocally settle the limits, which might contribute to the analysis of national and transnational constitutions. Following this path it might be addressed that the European Union and the World Trade Organizations are constitutional orders. 4 SHAPING SOCIETIES – THE REGULATORY DIMENSION OF CONSTITUTIONS If we talk about constitutions on the “move”, the aspect of regulation gets increasingly relevant. Constitutions often have been observed as legal instruments limiting affluent political power and as guarantee for human and civil rights, enabling these rights to prevail and pertain. Both functions can be viewed at from the perspective of regulation, namely as instruments which allow for shaping societal conditions. Recent debates, also labeled as “New Constitutionalism”, have made this additional emphasis more visible. They demonstrate that by enabling certain social phenomena or structures and by limiting others, constitutions have become important media for the regulation of modern societies. To be sure: This aspect of shaping or moulding society is only one among others, when we observe legal structures in general and constitutions in particular. No claim is made here with respect to any kind of priority for this aspect. Nevertheless, the reconstruction of the regulatory effects of constitutions might help understanding their role in the multifold manifestations of the social on local, regional and global levels. In order to put forward my argument, I will briefly touch three points of view: A brief reminiscence is necessary in order to understand the path from steering via reflexive law to governance and to become sensitive to the theoretical oblivion of regulation that took place during this process. These deliberations will then point at the regulatory aspects, which are present in all constitutions, or constitutional 3776 fragments. Some examples will finally try to support my theoretical suggestion. Ethics councils, procedures and commissions of Transitional Justice, and the regulation of Corporate Social Responsibility can be interpreted as instruments of constitutional pressure on social systems. 1. The scholarly debate on constitutionalism that emerged roughly a decade ago has influenced both legal and sociological thinking in a significant way. In a certain sense, this debate regenerates and invigorates the interdisciplinary co-operation between more normatively oriented jurisprudence and legal theory on the one hand and the empirically based sociological theory, not least as regards sociology of law and political sociology. Constitutionalism has become prominent in legal and political theory, especially in studies on the European Union and phenomena of multi-level governance provoking questions of legitimization. Christian Joerges, and many others have promoted this line of argument. With respect to the EU, arguments of legal, rather constitutional pluralism have been put forward and the relation between the different levels of the EU governance have been critically discussed (Pernice, Walker, MacCormick, and others). Often normative claims have been raised for certain standards of co-operation between European states or for a higher degree of supra-national integration (cf. for the following: Carvalho 2015, manuscript p. 57 ff.) Beyond the narrower range of the EU, with a more general impetus and with theoretically far reaching implications, the role of the state in world society becomes ambiguous and contested (agaIn: Carvalho 2015). As a consequence, the relation between politics and law, the normative legitimization of politics become subject to theoretical renegotiation (Slaughter, Zürn). Accordingly, normative theories of the state providing concepts of legitimation for political power in the shape of legal or philosophical constitutional theory gain a strong position in current constitutionalism. Prominent names in this respect are, for instance, Dieter Grimm, Jürgen Habermas, Hauke Brunkhorst and others. Habermas speaks about a post-national constellation demanding for a constitutionalisation of public international law. Grimm, on the contrary, insists on the undissolvable connection between state and constitution. An intermediary position is taken by Anne Peters: 3777 compensatory constitutionalisation of international law. Yet another normative model: Cottier and Hertig, who study constitutional thinking as a necessary prerequisite for the preservation of normative standards in a global world. In his book on »Transconstitutionalism« Marcelo Neves (2013) has suggested the notion of a transversal constitutionalism, which still refers to states as the basis of constitutionalism, but adds the idea of a certain type of rationality that can be exchanged between the different normative spheres of states, supra- and international structures and legal cultures within the realm of state law. A quite different source of current constitutionalism can be seen in sociological steering theory of the 1970ies and 1980ies and its development under the label of governance. The starting question, the "initial puzzle", as Marc Mölders (2015) has called it, was the question, whether the objects of steering “reorganize themselves and adapt to operational criteria which they define themselves, how is mutual influence, intervention or even regulation possible?” (Febbrajo & Teubner 1992, pg. 11). A famous reaction to that question can be found in Teubner's and Willke's essay on "Reflexive Law" (1984), where they applied theories of self-organization and self-regulation to the theory of law. Some of the current contributions to the new constitutionalist debate, as I will argue, are directly attached to concepts of reflexive law that had emerged as a reaction to the impasses of early steering theory and first order cybernetics. Christian Joerges, for instances, claims that Teubner's constitutionalism is a response to certain concerns with new governance models, which for their part, already had been reactions to certain impasses of steering theory (Joerges 2004, pg. 351.) After the decline of rather simple and, to a certain extent, naïve theories of societal steering, in the 1970s and 1980s political scientists, lawyers and sociologists developed more sophisticated approaches in order to understand, how social institutions or systems might be open to influence from different forms of intervention. Debates on regulation often conceived of intervention as state activity affecting private subjects, whereas governance was understood as a multiactor and multi-level activity. Post-interventionist theories and concepts of pluralist societies had raised questions that the idea of governance promised to answer by replacing more rigid concepts of social steering by new ideas of cooperation, 3778 negotiation, coproduction, hybrid communication, and self-regulation. Originally stemming from economy (Coase 1937, Williamson 1975), where it was mainly used to focus on »good governance« in organizations, the semantics of »governance« spread over the political sciences – especially international relations (Rosenau and Czempiel 1992, Rosenau 2000) and policy research (Mayntz 1998). In this tradition «governance» is being understood as a form of statehood mainly characterized by »negotiation« and »co-operation«, in contrast to »hierarchical structures«, which were understood as properties of the democratic national state (Héritier 2002; Kooiman 2002, Rosenau 1995, Schuppert and Zürn 2008, Blumenthal 1995, Willke 2006). Last but not least general sociological theory, namely political sociology and sociology of law build a source of constitutionalism in trying to explain the role or function of constitutions in modern society. I would mention Chris Thornhill (2011) and Poul Kjaer (2014) as examples of this approach, because they are primarily interested in the reconstruction and explanation of the social function of constitutions. These are only some of the main influences that coined the field of New Constitutionalism. Their plurality and heterogeneity causes, to a certain extent, an impression of complexity and obscurity of constitutionalism. 2. Nevertheless, more or less two large fields can be distinguished: a normative debate about the legitimization of constitutions in a post-national world and an empirical perspective asking for the emergence of constitutions and their regulatory capabilities, their suitability for enabling, shaping, and limiting social phenomena. As mentioned above, I would like to draw your attention to the fact that these approaches are often rooted in theories of societal steering and planning, which later-on have been transformed into concepts of reflexive law, societal self-regulation and governance. In order to make this interpretation plausible, let us briefly recapitulate Gunther Teubner’s intellectual move from reflexive law to constitutional theory. His book on »Constitutional Fragments« (2012) is the one of the main references in the current debate. Starting from a critique of the main stream in constitutionalist debate, it argues against normative approaches and against the strong accent on 3779 public law. In so doing it argues from a private law and sociological perspective, strongly influenced by Niklas Luhmann's sociological systems theory. Starting with an account of the crisis of contemporary constitutionalism and with the position of societal constitutionalism Teubner criticizes the propositions of transnational constitutionalism by developing the idea of constitutional fragments, i.e. legally constituted social areas such as functional systems, networks, hybrid regimes. In this world of constitutional pluralism, constitutions fulfill a twofold function (Teubner 2012, pgs. 25/26, 36/37, 46, 120 ff.). They enable and limit the emergence and stabilization of the social areas just mentioned. The enabling function safeguards the autonomy of societal areas. The limiting function prevents them from endangering other areas by their respective »centrifugal« and »expansionist« (46) tendencies. This double role of constitutions very clearly is an aspect of societal steering, intervention, or governance. As a »hybrid meta-code« (169 ff.) constitutional structures encroach on the operations of the entangled systems and regimes. And this does not only relate to states and the political system. Constitutions – or constitutional fragments – are in Teubner's view equally important for the regulation of the relation between non-state actors, organizations and individuals. (»Drittwirkung« – third-party effect in German legal theory, now in Teubner's terms: »horizontal effects (or force)« 214 ff.). The mechanism, through which the autonomous social systems pass through the process of constitutionalisation, is: self-constitutionalisation. Selfconstitutionalisation works by the exercise of external pressure which loads social systems with »capillary power« (135), thus triggering internal constitutionalisation. This figure, again, refers to the core idea of "reflexive law". The conditions, under which these capillary constitutions emerge, are twofold, namely of external and internal nature. Externally, the self-constitutionalisation of social systems is determined by a situation of a »dynamic disequilibrium« (125 ff.) With their respective expansionist tendencies, systems put other systems in their environment under pressure, in a way they endanger their normal operations. Inflationary production of symbols leads to »pathological growth« creating »horizontal threats of integrity« (125). The 3780 relation between the system reaches a »turning point« (»Umschlagpunkt«), where »institutions combating horizontal threats of integrity become imperative.« (125) Internally, self-constitutionalisation is triggered by systemic crisis, by an imminent break-down of the structures. Such a near catastrophe is understood as the »constitutional moment«. In contrast to horizontal threats of integrity, the near catastrophe is an interpretive frame of a single system. Whenever such a system describes itself as approaching a break-down, this self-description becomes a sociological fact for the observing system. In other words, societal constitutionalism emphasizes the possibility of an external power or pressure to trigger operational or structural responses in autonomous social systems via constitutions (Sciulli 2001; Teubner 2012). It explicitly conceives of constitutions of means for influencing and shaping social systems. From this perspective, both the limiting and the enabling functions of constitutions, become instruments of regulation. 3. The term »regulation« has various sources. It has gained a certain prominence in political economy (cf. e.g. the works of Hirsch, Jessop, Aglietta, Boyer and others). From this angle »regulation« stands for the task of taming modern forms of capitalism. Insofar, it is dealing with a very specific aspect that is mainly situated in the relations between politics and economy, firstly, and that is built upon a very particular kind of social theory. In contrast to these approaches, I take the position of sociological systems theory that allows for a broader variety of inter-systemic relations and that also takes into consideration the fact that modern society is not rather poly-centric and so much centred around one single system, be it politics or economy. Against this background, I understand »regulation« as any operation of a social system that aims at deciding, defining, setting the state of another system (goal system) with respect to the production of the commonweal (Bora 2002, Bora 2014, Bora 2015, Bora and Münte 2012). The latter term is meant to represent the German word »Gemeinwohl«, covering approximately the semantic field of common welfare, public weal or public good in a broad sense. This specification operates as confinement of the definition, which would be merely formal and limitless otherwise. Thereby it should become clear, that regulation in our context 3781 does not refer to the sheer control over machines or objects, for example, but always implies a social dimension, namely the (self-) shaping of society, its subsystems and organisations. According to this theoretical concept, »regulation« is not restricted to control and intervention in the sense of regulative law. It encompasses limiting and risk minimizing instruments as well as promoting and enabling ones. Julia Black speaks about »regulation as facilitation«, Sabel and others (2012) have been working on »experimentalist governance«, and German legal scientists are interested in »regulation fostering innovation« (Eifert and Hoffmann-Riem 2009). Schuppert accentuates the fact that governance »largely is regulation« (2008, 395). 4. If we look for examples that might help making the idea of regulatory effects in constitutions plausible, state constitutions are a more or less clear case in this respect. But also the more fluid and hybrid forms of constitutions, which are currently in the centre of theoretical interest, can be described from the proposed perspective of regulation. Some examples may shed light on this point. Corporate Social Responsibility A prominent example is DIN/ISO 26000 regarding corporate social responsibility. Such standards might well be understood as social constitutions in Teubner's sense. The standard intends to assist organizations in contributing to sustainable development and in going beyond legal compliance. The aims of ISO 26000 represent common goods that usually are not in the focus of technical standardization in the exchange between economic actors. These actors rather consider such common goods as »externalities«. The consequences of the externalization of common goods have been described as »tragedy of the commons« (Hardin 1968). Therefore, the law usually has a decisive role in the regulation of commons, as for instance Elinor Ostrom has shown (Ostrom 1990). Against this background, ISO 26000 describes a strategy between strict legal regulation and cultural commitment. The latter was an important answer to the problem of the commons in small communities of medieval and early modern times. Later, the law succeeded to the task of regulating the commons under the more complex conditions of modern society. The new »cultural« standards, such 3782 as ISO 26000 for instance, are softer than positive law, on the one hand, and harder than cultural bonds on the other. In a certain sense, they have a »constitutional« character, as Grahame Thompson (2012) has noted correctly. They do not have direct steering effects, due to their voluntary character. However, they generally have the ability to create and stabilize systemic trust in individual firms and in the market as a whole with respect to their aptitude to safeguard common goods. Establishing such kind of systemic trust seems particularly profitable in a situation, where observers speak of the »moralization of markets«: »In the world of goods and services, not only social relations find their expression, but also societal values and norms become manifest in services and goods or in the reputation of a producer and provider. The economy is not only an exchange of valuable good, but also an exchange of values (Georg Simmel)« (Stehr 2008), 12). Altogether, such standards can be read as constitutions. They couple politics and law – and be it only "soft" law – with economy in order to regulate external effects of the latter with respect to common goods as a goal of regulation. Ethics Councils Rather prominent examples in this respect are also national ethics councils. The main point of this constellation is that – in spite of the ethical reference of these institutions – the law serves as the framework and bottleneck, through which every recommendation of the council has to pass, i.e. as point of reference and as a semantic reservoir for the task of integration and compatibility. Ethics councils have been installed in many states in order to support policy and the respective regulation of socially contested scientific and technological developments. Ethics, as the underlying argument suggests, is supposed to be able to integrate the diverse communications around scientific and technological innovations and thereby to support sound science policies. This development has been described as »ethicisation of technology controversies« (Bogner 2011), »a renaissance of ethics« (Pruzan und Thyssen 1994). Ethics councils usually are established as independent entities, hosted by either ministries or academies of science. In either a presidential/governmental (France/US) or in a mixed model (Germany since 2008), they are mostly 3783 appointed by government. Such councils are usually responsible to government, in some times also to parliament (Germany, NL, Sweden, e.g.). They either have an advisory function, as in most western European Countries, or perform a specific role in drafting legislation, as in many new member states of the EU. Their size varies from five persons in Urugay to over forty in France or Italy (Fuchs 2005, Ahvenharju et al. 2006). If one takes a closer look at the communications of such bodies, it is not so much ethics in most cases, but rather the law, more precisely: constitutional law that integrates the heterogeneous validity claims. The law is the bottle neck, through which all semantics relevant to the respective regulation of science and technology have to pass. It creates a strong framing of the case. This framing is unproblematic only insofar, as in the process of decision-making politics opens the semantic frame again, treating the ethics council's opinions as a form of »coordinated dissent« rather than as an anticipated political decision (Bogner 2011). This political reaction, however, strongly depends on the role of the ethics council in the respective constitutional context. The function of the law, on the other hand, seems to be stabilization again, namely making sure that »ethical advice« is not vanishing in the plurality of moral standpoints and the exuberant multiplicity of preferences and values, neither in the arbitrariness of decisionism. It thereby also fulfils the function of assuring politics that »ethical advice« is politically useful, because it is legally – and, via the bottleneck of the law: scientifically – approved. As a result, the law reduces complexity for politics insofar, as it minimizes the risk of constitutional failure. On the other hand, this configuration also increases the political risk, insofar as it affects political sovereignty, because in this case, law positions itself »before« politics. For political sovereignty as procedure, as the realization of political communication, this is to a certain extent, a paradoxical constellation. From this theoretical point, it is then easy to understand, why ethics councils do not tend to communicate extensively their influence on legislation. Ethics, against this background is not so much the frame constituting the communication within the council, but rather a rhetorical figure making the paradox 3784 relation between law and politics invisible and thereby enabling both sides to smoothly operate. After all, law in ethics councils filters all kinds of semantics, which are assembled under the topic of »ethics«, in a way that makes the communication suitable for the political game. It offers a more or less stable frame of reference for the highly complex relations between diverse validity claims in this hybrid type of intermediary institution. In so doing, it couples politics, science, economy and the law by developing constitutional semantics in order to regulate processes and structures in the respective fields. Transitional Justice Transitional Justice, last but not least, can be seen as a phenomenon of world society (Kastner 2015) that is deeply rooted in the tradition of Human Rights and a constitutional debate on the level of world society. According to its rather diffuse, value-oriented, but not very explicit semantic content it can be used in transitional societies as a means for creating new social identities. Among the examples mentioned, Transitional Justice is perhaps a very clear case of a regulatory effect of constitutional structures. Pablo Holmes's example of the imposition of constitutions Holmes addresses the issue under a specific perspective: the imposition of constitutions in a colonial and post-colonial process by American and European countries. Here we find the regulatory dimension again, in an even stronger sense. One could assume that processes he point at deal with regulation instead of selfregulation, leading to the political exclusion of considerable parts of the world’s population. Insofar, Holmes's argument seems to fit very into my concept. Constitutions may be used even in an "anti-constitutional" sense, as he suggests. 5. The intention of this paper is not in any way to replace or deny any of the theories of new constitutionalism. Rather, I wanted to hint at an additional aspect, a dimension in constitutions that seems to be neglected sometimes. Regulation, in other words, always has been one, if not the effect that norms and law are delivering to all societal fields. This point also holds true with respect to constitutions. 3785 LITERATURE (PROVISIONAL) AHVENHARJU, S.; HALONEN, M.; UUSITALO, S.; LAUNIS, V. and HJELT, M. (2006): Comparative analysis of opinions produced by national ethics councils. Report for the European Commission. Contract No RTD-C3-2004-TOR1. Helsinki: Gaia Group. BLUMENTHAL, J. Von. 1995. Governance – Eine kritische Zwischenbilanz. Zeitschrift für Politikwissenschaft 15, 4, 1149-1180. BOGNER, A. 2011. Die Ethisierung von Technikkonflikten: Studien zum Geltungswandel des Dissenses: Weilerswist: Velbrück Wiss. BORA, A. (2002): Ökologie der Kontrolle. Technikregulierung unter der Bedingung von Nicht-Wissen. In: ENGEL, C.; HALFMANN, J.; SCHULTE, M. (Hrsg.): Wissen, Nichtwissen, unsicheres Wissen. Baden-Baden: Nomos, 253–275. BORA, A. (2014): Rethinking regulation: What governance is all about. In: Portuguese Journal of Social Science 13 (2014), 2, 197-213. BORA, A. 2015. The Shadow of the Law: Intermediary Institutions and the Ruling Part of Governance. In: HARTMANN, EVA and POUL F. K. (eds.), The Evolution of Intermediary Institutions in Europe. From Corporatism to Governance (forthcoming) BORA, A.; MÜNTE, P. (Hg.) (2012): Mikrostrukturen der Governance. Beiträge zur materialen Rekonstruktion von Erscheinungsformen neuer Staatlichkeit. BadenBaden: Nomos. Studien zur Politischen Soziologie 19. CARNEIRO CARVALHO, H. (2015): Verfassungen in der globalisierten Weltgesellschaft. Ein systemtheoretischer Beitrag zur Verfassungssoziologie. Manuskript. Bielefeld. COASE, R. 1937. The Nature of the Firm. In: WILLIAMSON, O.E; WINTER, S.G., The Nature of the Firm. Origins, Evolution and Development. New York u.a. 1971, 18-33. EIFERT, M.; HOFFMANN-RIEM, W. (Hg.) (2009): Innovationsfördernde Regulierung. BerlIn: Duncker & Humblot. FEBBRAJO, A.; TEUBNER, G. (1992): Autonomy and Regulation in the Autopoietic Perspective: An Introduction. In: Ibid. (Ed.): State, Law and Economy as Autopoietic Systems. Regulation and Autonomy in a New Perspective. Milan: Giuffrè, pp. 3–16. 3786 FUCHS, M. 2005. National ethics councils. Their backgrounds, functions and modes of operation compared. BerlIn: Nationaler Ethikrat. HARDIN, G. 1968. The Tragedy of the Commons. Science 162 (3859): 1243–48. HÉRITIER, A. (ed.). 2002. Common goods: reinventing European and international governance. Lanham, Md. u.a.: Rowman & Littlefield. JOERGES, C., I.-J. S., und GUNTHER TEUBNER, Hrsg. 2004. Transnational Governance and Constitutionalism. International Studies in the Theory of Private Law. Oxford: Hart Publishing. KASTNER, F. 2015. Transitional Justice in der Weltgesellschaft. Hamburg: Hamburger Edition (forthcoming) KJAER, P. F. 2014. Constitutionalism in the Global Realm: A Sociological Approach. Routledge Research in Constitutional Law. London [u.a.]: Routledge. KOOIMAN, J. (2002): Governance: A Social-Political Perspective. In: Grote/Gbikpi 2002, 71-96. MAYNTZ, R. 2005. Governance-Theorie als fortentwickelte Steuerungstheorie?. In: Gunnar Folke Schuppert (ed.), Governance-Forschung (Governance research), Baden-Baden: Nomos, pp. 11–20. MÖLDERS, M. (2015): Publicity as a Medium of Intended Change Towards a Concept of Irritation Design. Maunscript. Bielefeld. NEVES, M. 2013. Transconstitutionalism. Bd. 10. Hart Monographs in Transnational & International Law. Oxford and Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing. OSTROM, E. 1990. Governing the Commons : The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Political Economy of Institutions and Decisions. Cambridge [u.a.]: Cambridge Univ. Press. PRUZAN, P., und Ole Thyssen. 1994. The Renaissance of Ethics and the Ethical Accounting Statement. Educational Technology 34: 23–28. ROSENAU, J. N. (1995): Governance in the Twenty-First Century. In: Global Governance 1, 13. ROSENAU, J. N. (2000): Governance and Democracy in a Globalizing World. In: HELD, D.; MCGREW, A. (eds.), The Global Transformations Reader. Cambridge: Cambridge University press, 181-190. 3787 ROSENAU, J. N.; CZEMPIEL, E.-O. (Hg.) (1992): Governance Without Government: Order and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. SABEL, C. and ZEITLIN, J. (2012). Experimentalist governance. In: Oxford handbook of governance, edited by D. Levi-Faur. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 169-183. SCHUPPERT, G. F.; ZÜRN, M. (Hg.) (2008): Governance in einer sich wandelnden Welt. Wiesbaden: VS. STEHR, N. 2008. Moral markets. how knowledge and affluence change consumers and products. Boulder, Colorado: Paradigm Publ. TEUBNER, G., und WILLKE, H. 1984. Kontext und Autonomie: Gesellschaftliche Selbststeuerung durch reflexives Recht. Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie 5 (1): 4–35. TEUBNER, G. 2012. Constitutional fragments/Verfassungsfragmente. Societal constitutionalism and globalization. Oxford constitutional theory. Oxford Univ. Press. THOMPSON, G. 2012. The constitutionalization of the global corporate sphere? Oxford: Oxford University Press THORNHILL, C. J. 2011. A Sociology of Constitutions : Constitutions and State Legitimacy in Historical-Sociological Perspective. Cambridge Studies in Law and Society. Cambridge [u.a.]: Cambridge Univ. Pr. WILLIAMSON, O. E. (1975): Markets and Hierarchies. New York: Free Press. WILLKE, H. 2006. Global governance. Einsichten. Bielefeld: Transcript. 3788 SOCIOLOGY OF LAW BETWEEN NATIONAL LEGAL SYSTEMS AND WORLD SOCIETY Laura Appignanesi Matteo Finco ABSTRACT: According to the luhmannian paradigm of world society, policontestural and characterized by functional differentiation, a regional idea of society should be rejected. However, it is clear that there are still strong differences in national political and legal subsystems, particularly with regard to the fundamental rights recognized to individuals and their effective protection. In particular rights and values recognized by international treaties are often incompatible (see M. Neves, 2013). This work will be compared with the contributions on this issue by N. Luhmann (fundamental rights are institutions that emerge to allow social differentiation, protect it from the expansionist tendencies of the political subsystem and assign individual rights outside of the norm of reciprocity) and by G. Teubner (according to him it is necessary to distinguish between institutional, personal and human rights, the latter "understood as negative limits imposed on societal communications, where the physical and mental integrity of the individuals is undermined by a communicative matrix"). These contributions are representing a sociology of constitutions at present widely discussed in Latin American countries. In order to avoid an anti-humanistic approach, which considers the individuals outside the inter-systemic communication, we need to take into account that, in a contemporary world characterized by less and less differentiated systems, the multisystemic environment is subject to dynamism and reflexive communicative channels (strukturelle Kopplung) between subsystems. Constitutions could be thus combine closure and openness of the legal system by resorting to strategies of institutionalization of internal self-reflection and external communication. KEYWORD: sociology of constitutions; transnationalism; functional differentiation, structural coupling; fundamental rights; world society. 1 INTRODUCTION Nowadays we can see an increasingly evident worldwide hyper-connection, both in economic-financial aspects and in socio-cultural ones. In this context the issue of fundamental rights becomes more and more important, while the 3789 contemporary constitutionalism, anchored to the territoriality of nation-states, shows its limits in the matter. In the first place, it is clear that there are considerable differences in the legal systems of different socio-political contexts; on the other hand, it seems to become more insistent the request to achieve an universally valid legal threshold, concerning the recognition of these rights but also their actual protection. From a legal sociological perspective, we might ask questions such as: is it possible (and if yes, how) to achieve a global governance of fundamental rights in the present complex changing context? What kind of contribution could Sociology of Constitutions (and sociological theory in general) provide in the whole framework of world society? The starting background seems to be a society characterized by less and less differentiated systems (according to Luhmann, we could say a "overintegrated" society). Moreover, within the legal national sphere, at the constitutional level, there are differences that sometimes come into conflict30. Therefore, we focus on the discrepancy between the normative side of the legal system (Charts and International Treaties that institutionalize the "selfreflective" recognition of "global" values and rights) and the concrete reality, namely the environment of the system: individuals that move in an increasingly complex and fragmented context. By dealing with the subject (fundamental rights), that seems to highlight better the tension between localism and universalism of law, we try to abstract theoretical arguments, useful to contribute to the general debate on the relationship between law and society. From a methodological point of view – without forgetting the theoretical roots of classical legal sociology – this analysis uses a systemic approach and the conceptual toolkit provided by the social system theory of Niklas Luhmann. In particular, through the concepts of "operational closure" and "functional See M. Neves, Transconstitutionalism, Trasleted by K. Mundy, Hart, Oxford and Portland Oregon, 2013. 30 3790 differentiation"31, we will try to understand the current relationship between different subsystems of society and the links between them. Although the concept of "relationship between autopoietic systems” is not present in the Luhmann theory, founded on operational closure, systems are not isolated units. They are connected to each other by a constitutive link with their environmental conditions: in this sense the notion of "structural coupling" (strukturelle Kopplung)32 is a pivotal concept. The argumentative structure starts from the current state in evolution of the material dimension (with the related difficulty of contemporary constitutionalism), and it develops by identifying theoretical references, as the contribution of Niklas Luhmann himself and Gunther Teubner in this field. The analysis is enriched by the description of the “transcostitutionalism” provided by Marcelo Neves. In the frame of their homogeneity of systemic approach and conceptual toolkit, we have three different perspectives, that constitute a space of pluralistic theoretical debate. Through this analysis we can try to find an hermeneutic path, useful to understand and to interpret the current crisis in terms of constitutional guarantees of fundamental rights, for trying to identify possible answers. In particular, it seems important to establish conceptual connections, to emphasize the links and to stress the different ideas that emerge within the same systemic vision. From now on, some problematic aspects might be originated, on one hand, from the different speeds of the cognitive process, more and more fast thanks to globalization, and, on the other hand, the lower speed of the regulatory process, anchored in the territorial space of distinct states. The institutionalization of the social reflection at a global level, made by the legislation of supranational treaties, does not seem to operate as an effective structural coupling, between the political See various works by N.Luhmann, e.g. Theory of society, Translated by R. Barrett, Stanford University Press, Stanford California, 2012. 31 32 It is a sociological concept that indicates the connection that can promote and filter the mutual influences and pressures between the different autonomous systems, connecting them in a durable and stable way, but without that the systems lose autonomy. See many works by N.Luhmann, e.g. Theory of Society, vol. 1, op. cit. (2012), pp. 54-56. 3791 subsystem and the legal one, to which we could add the systems of consciousness in the issue of fundamental rights. In sum, the current transition of society towards a model of world society, involves the question of how it is possible to predict (or rather hope) developments in the field of constitutional matters, in the light of the current challenges. 2 FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS AND THE DIFFICULTIES OF CONTEMPORARY CONSTITUTIONALISM During the XXth century the global legal system has been enriched by a set of rules and principles established to protect a set of rights defined as fundamental33. They are provided by various documents (treaties, agreements) internationally established and recognized. In this sense, those rights were born with different purposes, and each of them has different validity and strength. In this regard, we can have two preliminary considerations: in the first place, beyond what it is written in these documents, it is evident that their concrete application is something different (it depends on the existence of specific organisms able to detect conflicts and violations, of specific courts, and so on). Moreover, the plurality and heterogeneity of the rights recognized every time, reflects the different sensitivities of the respective socio-spatial contexts, which, however, are increasingly in contact to each other in a global scenario (the so- 33 We choose not coincidentally the expression fundamental rights (instead of human rights). First of all, in fact, we intend to limit the discussion to the effective rules and principles in a specific legal context (basically: those provided by Constitutions), then by invoking a strictly legalistic conception of rights. On the contrary, for example, A.K. Sen talks about human rights with a "not legally, but ethically founded" approach (Identità, povertà e diritti umani, in Giustizia globale, Il Saggiatore, 2006, p. 16). He conceives them as ideal-legal rights, statements that should ideally be legislated. Moreover, as pointed out by G. Palombella (Diritti fondamentali. Argomenti per una teoria, in «Filosofia Politica», 1999, disponibile online: http://lgxserver.uniba.it/lei/filpol/glp.htm), while the expression human rights concerns strictly human beings, fundamental rights may also be referred to societies, legal or moral systems, and so on. So a theory of fundamental rights “obliges us to focus also on that which is capable of contributing to the existence of a society” (Id., From Human Rights to Fundamental Rights. Consequences of a conceptual distinction, EUI Working Paper LAW No. 2006/34). Finally we point out that the treating of fundamental rights from a sociological point of view, on the basis of N. Luhmann, leaves aside any dogmatism, instead questioning on their function, to find their sense of reality in terms of their substitutability (Grundrechte als Institution: Ein Beitrag zur politischen Soziologie, Duncker & Humblot, 1965). 3792 called world society34). This matter, often, in the international context poses problems of dialogue and could create conflicts between the various parties involved35. G. Teubner36 highlights other obvious difficulties regarding the effect of fundamental rights within transnational social spaces : as it happens regarding the topic of a possible global governance, the discussion usually remains anchored to the national state, lacking a truly transnational inspiration. Moreover, when the authors of violations of fundamental rights are private transnational actors (such as multinationals), they usually are not called to respond to them consequentially, but it is always the community of states that must provide protection with respect their violations37. Basically there is a problem of fragmentation of the world society and its related law: fragmentation due not only to the aforementioned regional differences, but also to the functional differentiation of society38. Fragmentation thus leads to conflicts of rationality, or to non-harmonic relations between different functional subsystems39. We are facing the problem of a global constitutionalism which is struggling to define itself and that it seems to decline himself in an “horizontal” perspective40, in respect of obligations that go imposing itself, as well as to state authorities, also for the private actors. The question therefore is “whether the autonomy of the function systems might not lead to mutual burdens to the limits of their structural 34 We use this term according to Luhmann. See. N. Luhmann, Globalization or world society: how to conceive of modern society?, in «International Review of Sociology», Mar 1997; Id., Theory of society, vol. 1 and 2, Stanford University Press, Stanford (CA), 2012; Luhmann N., De Giorgi R., Teoria della società, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1992. See also E. Morin, Quelle « autre mondialisation »? in «Revue du MAUSS» 20, 2002. 35 Cfr. M. Neves, Transconstitutionalism, Hart, Oxford, 2013. 36 Cfr. G. Teubner, Nuovi conflitti costituzionali, Bruno Mondadori, Milano, 2012. 37 Ibidem. 38 We are referring here to the separation (which is the final step in the evolution of the society’s structures), between the various functional systems, operationally closed, each one characterized by a different communicative medium (money, knowledge, law, medicine, technology, etc.) and inclined to overcome territorial boundaries, building own autonomous global systems. 39 G. Teubner, Ordinamenti frammentati e costituzioni sociali, in Il diritto frammentato, Giuffrè, Milano, 2013. 40 Cfr., in addition to the already cited works by Teubner, see also Constitutionalising Polycontexturality, in «Social and Legal Studies» 19, 2011 and Transnational Fundamental Rights: Horizontal Effect?, in «Rechtsfilosofie & Rechtstheorie», 2011 (40) 3. 3793 adaptability with their very differentiation”41. In this way, Teubner advocates to connect in a network the respective constitutional fragments – nations, transnational regimes, regional cultures – for a constitutional “right of collisions”42. This, of course, does not prevent to consider the issue of the constitutional autonomy of subsystems and their coordination, namely the problem of a latent tension between functional systems, which are not bound to the land, and their constitutions, which instead are43. From these theoretical considerations important practical consequences derive. They arise not only the attention of lawyers, philosophers and sociologists of law: we have not only to conceive fundamental rights as institutions able to protect the autonomy of the individual from states, limiting the action of the latters, ensuring the participation in the communication of the former44, but also – because it is no longer possible to identify the state with the society, or at least the state “as societal organizational form, and politics as its hierarchical co-ordination”, when other “highly specialised communicative media (money, knowledge, law, medicine, technology) appear to gain in autonomy other highly specialized communicative media”45 – to deal with threats coming from the various subsystems. Such as those already highlighted by Marx (relative to the economy) or by Foucault (discussed in reference to models and dynamics of various types: total institutions, governance, etc ..). Problems then arises, Teubner writes, “in numerous social institutions, each forming their own boundaries with their human environments: politics/individual, economy/individual, law/individual, science/individual. Everything then comes down to the identification of the various frontier posts, so as to recognise the violations that endanger human integrity by their specific characteristics. Where are the frontier posts? In the various constructs of persons in the subsystems: homo politicus, oeconomicus, juridicus, organisatoricus, retalis, etc. These may only be constructs within communication that permit attribution, but they are at the same time real points of contact with people ‘out there’”46. 41 Cfr. N. Luhmann, Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, 1997, p. 1087. G. Teubner, Nuovi conflitti costituzionali, Bruno Mondadori, Milano, 2012, p. 22. 43 Ivi, p. 25. 44 N. Luhmann, op. cit., 1965. 42 45 G. Teubner, Transnational Fundamental Rights: Horizontal Effect?, in «Rechtsfilosofie & Rechtstheorie» 2011 (40) 3, pp. 207. 46 Ivi, pp. 208-9. 3794 Therefore we have to face concrete issues, that affect the freedom of action and the integrity of the individuals, both regarding communication and in respect of processing of their personal experience and most basic needs47. 3 LUHMANN AND TEUBNER ON FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS: COMPARATIVE CONSIDERATIONS AND INSIGHTS Before pondering on the possible “dialogue” between constitutions and on the influence that different subsystems of the society have to each other, we should try to observe the effects that the operations of the system of law and, more generally, those of the overall social system, have on the individuals, considering them not only as persons – namely from a strictly communicative point of view – but also in their irreducible bio-psychic, and therefore symbolic, part48. It is also possible to do this within the tradition rooted in systems thinking and that finds in Niklas Luhmann its main representative, despite the superficial objection that this is an “anti-humanistic” sociology, in which the role of individuals is underestimated or anyway subject to the emerging social “impersonal” level49. Luhmann defines fundamental rights as “institutions” , namely expectations of behavior, realized in the context of a social role and relying on social consensus50. Their function lies in the stabilization of the differentiation of the political system, specialized in production of binding decisions. For making this possible, it is necessary that it remains separate from other subsystems (economics, law, etc.) – each subsystem of society, in fact, is always subject to the 47 In this regard, we will refer later to the luhmannian distinction persons/bodies. We use this term with the meaning of E. Cassirer. See An Essay on Man. An Introduction to a Philosophy of Human Culture, Yale & New Haven, 1944. 49 Not only it is possible to trace in that tradition resources and insights for treatments that could take into account the different elements of individuality (As P. Stenner did in Is Autopoietic Systems Theory Alexithymic? Luhmann and the Socio-Psychology of Emotions. In «Soziale Systeme» 10 (2004), 159–85). But, above all, it is necessary to try to understand better modernity in its most different aspects and concrete phenomena, including those that relate more closely individuals in their specificity and in the most different expressions of this specificity: cognitive, affective or normative: see C. Baraldi, Il disagio della società. Origini e manifestazioni, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1999. 50 “Le istituzioni sono aspettative di comportamento generalizzate nella dimensione temporale, materiale e sociale e, in quanto tali, formano la struttura dei sistemi sociali.”: N. Luhmann, I diritti fondamentali come istituzioni, Dedalo, Bari, 2002, p. 45 (Fundamental Rights as an Institution: A Contribution to Political Sociology, 1965; translated in english by us). 48 3795 risk of dedifferentiation – guaranteeing to individual a degree of autonomy and independence from the action of state: fundamental rights are necessary to prevent that “All communications are oriented to specific purposes of the state bureaucracy, making possible the rationalization of these purposes in the sense of a provision functionally specified that must always presuppose the existence in the social order of other benefits, of other systems to pursue of interests, other sources of power and social prestige”51. Fundamental rights, therefore, ensure chance of communication, but at the same time they adjust communication “in such a way that it remains available for differentiation”52, specifically that of the political system. They emerge in a specific historical era of social evolution (in this sense are not ‘eternal’ and immutable), characterized by high complexity and functional differentiation: their function is precisely to stabilize the social structure by maintaining the differentiated autonomy of the political system and its separation from other subsystems. This is done by preventing the political system from ‘invading’ other spheres of social reality (individual personality, socialization, economics, etc.) and by preventing disorientation from its specific function (precisely to establish binding decisions). The separation of the law system from other subsystems is therefore a systemic need for the maintenance of differentiation of the social order: the fundamental rights therefore represent a guarantee towards regression to previous stages of development of society. Therefore they are positive rights: in fact the “separation of the law from religious, moral and scientific representative contexts and its positivization are an acquisition of the modern age”53: the increasing complexity of society corresponds to an increase of the internal complexity of the law, which frees itself from religious and natural law’s ties (legitimacy of divine nature disappear) becoming contingent, changeable. The law is not, however, blind to such contingency: the difficulty in placing values on a continuing basis (just because of the loss of legitimacy of natural law) in a complex reality (the modern 51 Idem, p. 60. Idem, p. 59. 53 Idem, p. 82. 52 3796 one), so it represents the premise to institutionalize tolerance and availability to compromise, as long as it is possible to reach “in a vast temporal horizon, a high pace in the changing of preferences of values”54. Each value and any rule become reversible, but they must remain valid until they will be replaced by others: for this reason, the law must be generalized in time, that is any legal decision “should be taken, in principle, independently of the moment in which it is assumed”55. Law, however, doesn’t decide which are the rules to apply: it must enforce them and stabilize expectations. Political system is the one that establishes valid standards – and can change them. It is responsible for the production of binding decisions, necessary to ensure order and lasting peace: for this it is necessary to establish fundamental rights, so they can limit the expansionist tendencies of the political system, in a way that the exercise of physical force and decisions remains legitimate (and therefore accepted), but at the same time allowing sufficient space and dimensions of freedom to individuals. This also explains the distinction between judicial and legislative function (the separation of powers of the state, another evolutionary achievement of modernity): law and politics must remain separate, because only in this way it is possible to rely on lasting and legitimate (however rebuildable) rules. In this sense, constitutions are the structural coupling between political system and system of law56. 54 N. Luhmann, Il tempo scarso e il carattere vincolante della scadenza, in S. Tabboni (a cura di), Tempo e società, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1985, pp. 120-137, p. 132 (Die Knappheit der Zeit und die Vordringlichkeit des Befristeten, in “Politiche Plannung”, 2 Aufl., Westdeutscher Verlag, 1975, pp. 143-165). 55 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002), p. 247. Law has the function to stabilize over time expectations and behavior, to turn rules in a rational order, so that even if they are disappointed, they will not lose their validity. Law is a kind of immune system: it develops rules to solve conflicts, which are generalized and maintained. The system in this way generates a past that serves in the present as a guide for the future. 56 “The constitution serves the dual function of including and excluding reciprocal perturbations of political and legal operations. Its two-sided form of including and excluding influence maintains the separation of the systems and allows for separate autopoietic reproduction without any confusing overlap. It also characterizes the ways in which the legal system (and on the other side, the political system) avoids isolation (which means entropy) and constructs on its internal screen what can serve within the system as information.”: N. Luhmann, Operational closure and structural coupling, in «Cardozo Law Review» 13 (1991-1992): 1419–1441, p. 1437. See also G. Corsi, On paradoxes in constitutions, in ???, Ashgate, Farnham, 2015. Especially this excerpt: “The idea is that the constitution was invented to regulate the relationships between law and politics, once these two systems are differentiated once and for all and there remains no possibility of polyfunctionality. The concept employed by systems theory to clarify the function of the constitution is that of structural coupling. […] This concept indicates the capacity – and the 3797 According to Luhmann fundamental rights therefore are not statutes, eternal and inviolate values, but tools that ensure the inclusion of individual in society, socialization, ie participation in the social context as a communication partner, ensuring a successful outcome of individual’s self-representation, conceiving it as a character, as form person, “able to report their actions to multiple social systems and to bring together in a personal behavioral synthesis their conflicting demands”57. The modern social order in fact puts the individual in front of an unprecedentedly rich range of possibilities for action, choices, opportunities: the emancipation from traditional constraints based on wealth, on belonging to a defined social class (that characterized functionally layered societies), the increased possibility of movement, they make possible to choose which profession or trade is to undertake and membership in different circles and social groups, allowing access to differentiated roles among the various contexts. However, it is difficult for a single to develop a variety, because it is constantly called to staring purposes and to act accordingly. So the individual is called to be otherwise (contingency)58: in order to do that, however, he needs a correct selfrepresentation as individual. Dignity and freedom, as defined in a functional sense, intervene at this level: they indicate the basic conditions for the success of selfrepresentation, they are preconditions for the socialization of man as an individual, as a partner of the interaction. Beyond their claim as historical values/rights in liberal Western tradition, dignity and freedom for Luhmann are institutionalized as unlimited capacities of contacts (a requirement for inclusion in the communication). They act on the outside (freedom) and on the inside (dignity) of self necessity – on the part of a system to develop specific kinds of awareness towards sectors in its environment, while remaining indifferent to all the rest. The systems theory defines these kinds of awareness as “irritations”, in the sense of disturbances or interferences, so as to underline that they are not cases of input coming in from outside, but of points of contact inside the system itself that generate effects that depend on its own structures and not on those of the irritating factor”. 57 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002), p. 99. 58 Contingency as fundamental character of modern society means that safety becomes improbable, that everything could be otherwise. This is true in every field, also in interpersonal relationships: we are not facing an impersonal mass society, reminds Luhmann. Modern society differs from previous configurations for greater chances of impersonal relations and more intense personal relationships: the differentiation of personal and social systems becomes for people more and more a reason to re-interpret their difference with environment on the basis of own person. See, N. Luhmann, Amore come passione, Bruno Mondadori, Milano, 2008 (Liebe als Passion Zur Codierung von Intimität, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1982). 3798 representation: freedom means that “social action does not end in the fulfillment of the action, but is included in the processes of symbolic attribution”59. It means, in other words, that we have the right to a free development of personality as a selfconscious individuality, to a space of personal action, protected from external interferences and violations (first of all those of the state). Dignity instead means that the roles to which we adhere are reconciled with a self-representation worthy of consideration: it is the knowledge that you can express what you are that lets you identify with your own person. It “indicates the successful self- representations”60; therefore it must be built and nurtured. His loss marks the loss of personality, and consequently of the social role61. Freedom and dignity are products of functional differentiation, not ‘inalienable human rights’: the differentiated social order institutionalized them precisely to ensure the inclusion of the person. The overall social system and the various functional subsystems are oriented in fact to the inclusion of the entire population”62. Obviously every subsystem operates according to its own logic, and decides “how far one can do”63: any individual relates in different ways to different subsystems, in dependence of its aspirations and abilities, but also in dependence on external conditions: citizenship is attributed to the individual based on place of birth and family, as well as the availability of money depends, even more than by the individual talents and commitment to their work, by familiar legacy; and so on. In principle, however, each one should have the opportunity to participate: freedom serves to this. But also another fundamental right, that of equality, fulfills the same purpose: it “creates the preconditions for enlargement of the possibilities of communication because it frees the act by the differences that limited the 59 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002), p. 115. Idem, p. 119. 61 “L’uomo non può usare la sua personalità, se la sua autorappresentazione non ha successo, se non ha dignità. Se non è in grado di effettuare un’autorappresentazione sufficiente, recede da partner della comunicazione e la sua scarsa comprensione delle esigenze del sistema lo conduce al manicomio.”: idem, pp. 120-1. 62 “There is no obvious reason to exclude someone from the use of the money, from the legal capacity or from belonging to a State, from education or marriage, nor to let depend everything 62 that from licenses or special conditions outside the system” : N. Luhmann, Oltre la barbarie, in «Sociologia e politiche sociali», n. 3, 1999. 63 Ivi. 60 3799 generalization and that bound the possibilities of self-representation in predetermined social positions”64. Equality is not an individual right or value65, but a systemic necessity: in this way, it becomes possible “taking decisions on internal problems of the system, about what is equal or unequal” 66, at the same time forcing the political system to relate to citizen regardless of his class, meaning with an equal treatment of individuals. The right to equality therefore does not exclude inequalities: nevertheless they must be justified, motivated. Discrimination can no longer depend on the decision maker, according to his feelings, his preferences, but must be based on objective reasons: the positivised law does not oblige to compliant conduct, but protects those who adapt them; likewise it does not guarantee justice and fairness67, does not prevent the rise and the development of inequalities: it makes unequal treatments possible “as long as sufficiently motivated”68. Human rights of freedom and equality, therefore, are not grounded on ‘human nature’: in modern society, where is no longer possible to define the social context in which everyone have to take action, their (latent) function lies on keeping the future open to further possibilities69. Then, if it could make sense toclaim for a just society – or at least ‘fairer’ – and universal values (whether freedom, equality, tolerance, peace, democracy, etc.), it is possible from a ‘civic’, ‘human’ point of view. Even for this, as already explained, we do not speak of ‘human rights’70 but of ‘fundamental rights’: modern 64 R. De Giorgi, Modelli giuridici dell’uguaglianza e dell’equità, in Disuguaglianze ed equità in Europa, edited by L. Gallino, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 1993, p. 369. 65 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002), p. 249. 66 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002), p. 259. 67 “In un ordine sociale pienamente differenziato le pretese di un agire giusto ingenerano complicazioni enormi e ricche di contraddizioni.” N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002), p. 267. 68 R. De Giorgi, op. cit., p. 365. 69 N. Luhmann, Theory of society, vol. 2, Stanford University Press, Stanford (CA), 2012 (original edition 2007), p. 301. 70 About ‘human rights’ social sciences were traditionally skepticist, starting by philosophers and th th sociologists of XVIII and XIX century (as, for example, Karl Marx: he tought that they were only a façade, masking economic and social inequalities. Rights originated by private property, that clouded social relations arising from the capitalist mode of production. See On the Jewish Question, in Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher, 1844). Cfr. G. Sjoberg, E.A. Gill, N. Williams, A th Sociology of human rights, in «Social Problems» Vol. 48, No. 1, 50 Anniversary Issue, Feb., 2011, pp. 11-47; P. Hynes, M. Lamb, D., M. Waites, Sociology and human rights: confrontations, evasions and new engagements, in «The International Journal of Human Rights» Vol. 14, No. 6, 3800 society – in luhmannian terms – is made of communication71. Society is not ‘unjust’: it simply works at another level than that of individuals72. Stating that does not mean to be cynical, being blind to inequalities and social distress: but is not useful keeping on describing exclusions in the different functional systems through a semantics that uses terms such as ‘exploitation’, ‘social oppression’, ‘marginality’. Instead of an impossible claim (precisely from a systemic point of view: the inclusion must be understood as a form of two sides: the other side is precisely the exclusion, where individuals count only as bodies73) for a total inclusion of everyone or looking for guilty ‘subject to blame’74, theory must try to describe “facts a little better than does the optimistic-critical tradition of our discipline; and precisely the facts that society itself builds”75. In addition to those shown here, Luhmann analyzes other rights, on which we cannot dwell: the right to property (which allows the individual to participate in the economic system), to vote (which offers citizens a role for participation in the political system), the legal protection of marriage and family, and so on76. What is described above, however, reveals what it means to analyze fundamental rights not from the point of view of legal dogmatics, but from the one of sociological theory, functionally-structuralist inspired: it could open the possibility of a more extensive and detailed understanding of legal and political systems, thus allowing November 2010, 810-830; Bryan S. Turner, Outline of a theory of human rights, in «Sociology» Vol. 27, No. 3, August 1993, pp. 489-512. 71 “the distinction between individual and society – since the mid-nineteenth century also individual and collectivity – is external to society.”: N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2012), p. 295. People therefore are in the environment; they are not part of the system. Society requires people, representatives that could communicate. Individuals as psychic systems are in relationship with social system through structural coupling, but this is a contact that occurs at the level of their respective structures. Biological and emotional-sentimental components (and consequently a number of needs of the individual) are not matter of society. It cannot take charge of them in the reproduction of its operations. 72 That is communication, the only genuinely social operation. See N. Luhmann, R. De Giorgi, Teoria della società, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1992, p. 26. 73 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2012), pp. 16-27. 74 A research starting by the idea of a stratified society: See N. Luhmann, op. cit. (1999). 75 Idem, p. 127. O, with different words: “Theory not only formulates what we know but also tells us what we want to know, that is, the questions to which an answer is needed. Moreover, the structure of a theoretical system tells us what alternatives are open in the possible answers to a given question. If observed facts of undoubted accuracy will not fit any of the alternatives it leaves open, the system itself is in need of reconstruction.”: see Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action. A Study in Social Theory with Special Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers, The Free Press, Glencoe (Illinois), 1949, p. 9. 76 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2002). 3801 a more aware and responsible formulation of social problems, primarily those that underlie fundamental rights77. Instead of conceiving fundamental rights merely as values, we look them as institutions, therefore, “it is possible explain our involvement in certain constellations of problems, which let appear as meaningful only a limited range of action”78. The contribute of Gunther Teubner to the discussion on fundamental rights moves from Luhmann’s legacy. However he adds some critical and purposeful ideas: they could be suitable for an operative use: this is especially true if we consider his tripartite distinction of fundamental rights. Teubner, starting by Luhmann, takes note of the problematic expansion of political system in modern society, which tends to cross boundaries of other social subsystems and at the same time impinge the individual “in his attempt to control both the body and the mind of people”79. Also he highlights the “expansionary effects” of other, specialized and autonomous functional systems: so we have to face a “multiplicity of anonymous and now globalized communicative processes” 80 , a society that can be described as an “anonymous matrix” of codified communications, which tends to expand itself without regards of human beings. So fundamental rights should defend the individual not only from the state, but also by the intrusion of other social subsystems, and should protect the autonomy of the various systems function81. Therefore Teubner proposes a tripartite division of the dimensions relating to the protection of fundamental rights, distinguishing them between institutional, 77 Idem, p. 307. Idem, p. 311. Values therefore are points of view for certain preferential consequences of action. They remain valid, fair, even if action or actors disappoint expectations: “I valori sono, cioè, aspettative stabilizzate in modo controfattuale ed in questo sono simili alle norme giuridiche […] Le norme giuridiche implicano un’alternativa chiara tra legalità e illegalità. Nell’universo dei valori, al contrario, non può essere introdotta una tale struttura di alternativa […] Chi si orienta ad un valore, trascura gli altri.” (p. 312). 79 G. Teubner, Ordinamenti frammentati e costituzioni sociali, in Il diritto frammentato, a cura di A. Febbrajo, F. Gambino, Giuffrè, Milano, 2013, p. 386. 80 Idem, p. 389. 81 Fundamental rights, as R. Prandini told, commenting on Teubner, are “contro-istituzioni moderne poste dentro ai sottosistemi funzionali per limitarne il potere. La loro funzione non è semplicemente quella di proteggere l’individuo, bensì anche quella di mettere in sicurezza l’autonomia delle sfere sociali, contro le tendenze espansive di altri sottosistemi.”: R. Prandini, Distinguere aude! Il Grand Récit sociologico di Gunther Teubner, in Il diritto frammentato, edited by A. Febbrajo, F. Gambino, Giuffrè, Milano, 2013, pp. 240-1. 78 3802 personal and human rights. Institutional rights handle with the autonomy of the “social discourses” (such as religion, art, science) against the totalitarian tendencies of the communicative matrix: they work as “conflict of law rules” between different partial social rationalities, trying to protect the integrity of art, family, religion against totalitarian tendencies of science, media or economy82. Personal rights instead concern the autonomy of communication: they protect people as “fictions”, communicative artifacts, ie individuals as they are included in the systems function. Human rights, finally, are “negative bounds on societal communication, where the integrity of individuals’ body and mind is endangered by a communicative matrix crossing boundaries.”83 They are those that concern the individual in its most genuine, less social, aspect, related to his bio-psychic endowment. The operative, already mentioned, potential of this tripartite division lies in the fact that a clear distinction of referents, the rights’ ‘holders’ – or at least of the different dimensions in which it is necessary to establish spaces and actions for protection – facilitates the task of those who are called to design and place actions for protection and preservation of rights. In other words, they become more obvious targets to reach and, together with them, the obstacles to face. Social policies, humanitarian claims, but perhaps also most general instances by groups and organizations, can benefit from a sort of ‘disillusionment’, which, instead of pushing to classify projects with the label of idealism, strengthens them, because it makes more aware their promoters. Just one example: affirming the importance of a particular right and at the same time recognizing it as human, in the sense of Teubner means clearly distinguishing what we are facing not only as ‘citizens’, but also as human beings, as members of the specie: beyond their citizenship, the state in which they are located, their possibility to pay, and so on. This leads us to focus attention on essential data and to exclude from the discussion claims and fears that don’t have anything to do with dimensions that is intended to preserve. Of course the contribution that this tripartite division can provide cannot overcome the intrinsic limits of law: institutional and personal rights in general are more 82 83 G. Teubner, The anonimous Matrix, in «Modern Law Review», 69, 2006. G. Teubner, op. cit. (2013), p. 390. 3803 easily recognized in judicial system than human rights. In this sense, Teubner says, we are faced by “a strictly impossible project” 84 because society cannot “do justice” to real people, as “people are not its parts but stand outside communication” 85. For Teubner, only “the self-observation of mind/body – introspection, suffering, pain – can judge whether communication infringes human rights. If these self-observations, however distorted, gain entry to communication, then there is some chance of humanly just self-limitation of communication.”86 This is a significant shift of paradigm, a purely sociological approach, aware of the inevitability of inequalities and exclusions, that are natural and obvious in a functional differentiated society. On this basis, it is therefore necessary to introduce “new devices of re-inclusion” able to “distinguish between the empirical and existential concreteness of the individual”87, which is more than the person88. Fragmentation of world society imposes this and other challenges: in fact, when rights are established, it needs both referents able to enforce them (such as national, international and transnational courts), and clear information on those who must respect them and have to answer for it in case of violation. This fact is not always clear. What are, for example, duties of transnational private actors who violate fundamental rights? Usually national states are called for the protection of 84 “All the groping attempts to juridify human rights cannot hide the fact that this is a strictly impossible project. How can society ever “do justice” to real people if people are not its parts but stand outside communication, if society cannot communicate with them but at most about them, indeed not even reach them but merely either irritate or destroy them? In the light of grossly inhuman social practices the justice of human rights is a burning issue, but one which has no prospect of resolution.”: G. Teubner, The anonimous Matrix, in «Modern Law Review», 69, 2006. 85 Idem, p. 393. 86 G. Teubner, op. cit. (2006). Human rights therefore represent a great challenge for contemporary society, which could be faced redefining them as ecological rights: “Ciò significa che il diritto della società non deve porsi come finalità l’impossibile inclusione giuridica dell’uomo, bensì l’improbabile relazione con esso, senza alcuna pretesa di risolverlo/ridurlo attraverso comunicazioni giuridiche”, R. Prandini, op. cit. (2013), p. 223. 87 “La matrice sociale deve invece essere capace di riconoscere che l’individuo è sacro e intoccabile e che, proprio per questo, va ricostruito semanticamente all’interno della società in quanto persona.”: Idem, p. 224. 88 It is worth noting that in this sense is at stake not only a general individual “health” or “harmony”, but foremost the validation by people of their individual identity, in its specificity and difference from the one of the form person, exclusively communicative and therefore “always proper”: people do not coincide with consciences, with corresponding psychic systems. See E. Esposito, Identità e persona nella teoria dei sistemi sociali, manuscript, url: www.cisi.unito.it/hal9000/ricerca/tsais/Resposito.doc. 3804 violations. That is, Teubner explains, a “thorny issue” 89 regarding global constitutionalism, called for the challenge of “connecting each other in a network constitutions from global fragments – nations, transnational regimes, regional cultures – , in a constitutional law of collisions”.90 This fragments exist due to the affirmation of different transnational regimes, separated from each other but that can try to govern itself internally, independently, until they ‘positivate’ their standard of fundamental rights, through the decision-making practice: it is the case, for example, of ICANN (Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers) or the WTO (World Trade Organization)91. This fragmentation however generates numerous occasions of conflict between the various constitutional systems, as Teubner highlights. More generally, also, should not be ignored a socio-cultural problem: it is questionable, in fact, if the global order (however you define it: post-national, global, and so on), which is based on heterogeneous elements such as pressure groups, NGOs, social movements, courts, etc., will succeed “to combine itself with some conventions on minimum standards and values, which do not require strict adherence to liberal social contract of Western modernity”92. If we consider threats to individual integrity provided by this fragmented reality, we can see that they don’t come only from political system, but also by various social institutions: economics, law, science, and so on. The research of Michel Foucault on micro-power, biopolitics, governmentality or the ones of Karl Marx in the economic field93, represent valuable contributions in this sense. All these arguments lead us to accept the inevitability of violations of individual 89 G. Teubner, op. cit. (2012), p. 19. Idem, p. 22. 91 The authority designated to appoint IP addresses and Internet domains. See G. Teubner, op. cit. (2012), op. cit. (2006). 92 A. Appadurai, Modernità in polvere, Raffaello Cortina, Milano, 2012 (1996), p. 35 (Modernity At Large: Cultural Dimensions of Globalization, University of Minnesota Press, 1996). 93 G. Teubner, op. cit. (2012), p. 167. “There is not just one single boundary political communication/individual, guarded by human rights. Instead, the problems arise in numerous social institutions, each forming their own boundaries with their human environments: politics/individual, economy/individual, law/individual, science/individual, medicine/individual”: G. Teubner, op. cit. (2012). About the examples cited: references are to the overall work of Marx and on Foucault’s researches on total institutions and biopolitics. See, among many others, La volontà di sapere. Storia della sessualità 1, Feltrinelli, Milano, 1988 (Histoire de la sexualité, 1: la volonté de savoir, Gallimard,1976). 90 3805 integrity in a social system that, in order to maintain the self-renewal of its environmental difference, absorb physical and psychic energy from individuals, through selective perturbative cycles of selective requests and selectively conditioned responses94. We can now try to identify some problematic issues to which theory could be applied. We have seen Teubner’s attention for the protection of bodies and minds: they have therefore, as noted by Prandini95, latent intrinsic rights. We can see, in comparison with Luhmann, a difference: the german sociologist, in fact, dealing with fundamental rights, still maintained a systemic reference, looking at the person as a construction of the social system, which uses it as their own environment. Teubner instead asserts the value and the inevitability of individuals in their concrete difference from society, even if he recognizes that only when psychic and mental suffering are able to irritate communication they could reclaim their validity. The modern challenge, then, is to make systems responsive, that is, at the same time, able to “manage the difference” between system and environment and “respect it, putting it in the conditions to be stay-different”96. The challenge thus consists in a permanent success in distinguishing between social and non-social, and to safeguard the latter, be it psychological, organic, natural. In order to do this are necessary devices, especially policies, able to operate a re-entry, to enter the system/environment distinction again in itself, thus building “a space of mediation between a growing social matrix and an increasingly biological-psychic individual”97. In any case, if we identify fundamental rights as institutions with a specific function – and therefore not as absolute and in this sense not necessary – we have to accept their generality and non-specificity, without classifying them, however, as useless: if fundamental rights don’t determine the actual content of 94 G. Teubner, op. cit. (2012), p.165. Rights to conceive as tendencies to self-subsistence and integrity inasmuch different from societal: R. Prandini, op. cit., p. 228. 96 Idem, p. 266. 97 Idem, p. 267. 95 3806 potential new rules, but they are merely limited to exclude some possibilities, to delimit the scope of intervention, to keep open possibilities for the future, for situations that might be important98, it means that they represent both a resource that could continuously stimulate planning of those who promote the discussion inside legal system, and a tool for theoretical reflection on boundaries between functional subsystems and their definition. Of course the attempt, from a sociological point of view, to develop a critical theory on fundamental rights must use observations – produced by sociology and by other fields of research – on this issue and on the safety of individual’s psychological well-being. In this sense, it is necessary to take into account, for example, the evolution of semantics of rights and human dignity99; semantics of the relation beetwen identity and its public and private dimensions100; and also philosophical research on social order; studies on the correlation between cultural phenomena and psychological and social processes101; theoretical studies on the crisis and the future of Western civilization102; the proposals of a specific sociology of human rights. 98 “It has to establish fundamental rights that are not just an historically recent invention, but are also the product of decisions, so contingent like any other norm. This means that they are fundamental because they are not necessary. […] In the form they have take on today, values and fundamental rights are formulated to be substantially generic or even a-specific. […] These values’ universalism thus seems to oblige them to be semantically empty. […] These rights declare themselves to be unalterable, because that is the only way that they can claim to legitimise the future, while at the same time waiving the right to define it in advance.”, G. Corsi, op. cit. (2015). 99 See, among others, M.C. Nussbaum, Giustizia sociale e dignità umana. Da individui a persone, il Mulino, Bologna, 2012. 100 See T. Dumm, Loneliness as a Way of Life, Harvard University Press, 2010. 101 See, among others: M. Benasayag, G. Schmit, L’epoca delle passioni tristi, Feltrinelli, Milano, 2004 (Les passions tristes. Souffrance psychique et crise sociale, Editions La Découverte, 2003); B.-C. Han: La società della trasparenza, Nottetempo, Roma, 2014 (Transparenzgesellschaft, Matthes & Seitz, Berlin, 2012), Eros in agonia, Nottetempo, Roma, 2013 (Agonie des Eros, Matthes & Seitz, Berlin, 2012), La società della stanchezza, Nottetempo, Roma, 2012 (Müdigkeitsgesellschaft, Matthes & Seitz, Berlin, 2010); G. Piazzi: Julie, Quattroventi, Urbino, 2009; Teoria dell’azione e complessità, Franco Angeli, Milano 1988 (1984); G. Manfré: Le radici culturali del disagio contemporaneo, I libri di Emil, Bologna, 2014; Ripensare l’identità: nuove prospettive di teoria critica, in «Studi Urbinati, B - Scienze umane e sociali», vol. 81, 2011. 102 On current era, characterized by a global financial and economic crisis that affects individual’s state, see, among many others, J. Brassett, N. Vaughan-Williams, Crisis is governance: subprime, the traumatic event, and bare life, in «Global Society» 26:1, 2012, pp. 19-42. On ‘crisis’, see D. Baecker, Culture crisis, in The Financial Crisis in Constitutional Perspective. The Dark Side of Functional Differentiation, edited by P.F. Kjaer, G. Teubner, A. Febbrajo, Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2011; M. Augé, Futuro, Bollati Boringhieri, Torino, 2012; L. Gallino, Finanzcapitalismo. La civiltà del denaro in crisi, Einaudi, Torino, 2010; Z. Bauman, Vite di corsa. Come salvarsi dalla 3807 All these phenomena, in the proposal that is made here, are processed within a framework based on the awareness that in a society characterized by functional differentiation there isn’t - and couldn’t be – a system able to direct all the others, with the resulting “lack of symbolic production capable of holding together the different systems”103. If it is true that modern society in its relation with the complexity of the environment always seems to find new opportunities for adaptation, at the same time we know that sometimes these opportunities do not include the human factor, since society is functionally oriented104. We have to consider: is this a fact that must be taken for granted? Probably yes, but it should be noted, on one hand, the limits of semantics, of conceptual heritage used by the observers, and the constant delay of semantics in the description of the structures of society105; on the other hand, we have to consider the unpredictability of the future, produced by structural conditions106. Not least, it should be noted that nowadays human dignity and the rights attached to it represent prejudices of modernity, inviolable values, tools through which humanity reflected “looking for his most profound unity”107: the emergence of hyper-global value of human dignity would seem to indicate “a road, in the middle of a barbarity that sometimes seems to exceed the ability of a containment” 108 . This could be seen as the product of the reaction of (human) environment towards unacceptable outrageous incidents, inconceivable barbarity, that must be rejected, not only from a moral, but also from an aesthetic point of view109. But it is also necessary to evaluate as the strategic result of contingent and recursive structure of society, that can generate ‘own values’ (eigenvalues), ‘inviolate levels’ tirannia dell’effimero, il Mulino, Bologna, 2009 (Consuming Life, 2008); D. Fusaro, Essere senza tempo. Accelerazione della storia e della vita, Bompiani, Milano, 2010. 103 Paolo F., Crisi della struttura o crisi della semantica, in «Imago. Rivista di Studi Sociali sull'immaginario», Anno II, n. 2, 2013, pp. 18-49, p. 21. 104 Idem, p. 43. 105 Idem, pp. 26-7. 106 See note 13. see N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2013). 107 See Introduzione, in N. Luhmann, Esistono ancora norme indispensabili?, Armando Editore, Roma, 2013 (Are there Still Indispensable Norms in Our Society?, in «Soziale Systeme», 14, 2008, 1, pp. 18-37), p. 31. 108 Idem, p. 38. 109 Idem, p. 35. 3808 corresponding to their organizational archetype110 able to “block the thinking”, allowing the law and society to give themselves “indispensable norms”. 4 TRANSCOSTITUTIONALISM IN A MULTICENTRIC SOCIETY Now we can consider the contribute provided by Marcelo Neves, who adopts, like Luhmann and Teubner, the systemic approach for theoretical speculation. The Brazilian constitutionalist focuses on the new size of the demand for fundamental rights111 as it emerges from world society. In fact, this issue is increasingly becoming relevant to more than one legal order and to different social systems at the same time.112 Thus, from a constitutional perspective, problems of fundamental rights have a shared value and a dimension that concerns the relations between different permanent cross-cutting relationships among legal orders and between them and other subsystems. We might say that the cognitive aspect seems to insist on a space much larger and more complex in comparison to the normative classic constitutionalism, which traditionally is rooted on a defined history and territory. Starting from this premise, Neves first of all rejects the widespread tendency to a metaphorical use of the term “constitutional”. Also he rejects the consequent invitation to create a new constitution whenever new social need arise113. Rather, Neves limits the use of the term “constitution” in its strict semantic and historical sense, and he proposes a new model called “transcostitutionalism”114. For his theoretical work, Neves borrows from Wolfgang Welsch and develops the concept of “transversal reason”115, conceived in the context of a 110 111 112 N. Luhmann, op. cit. (2013), p. 67-8. See also Id. (2012), pp. 301-305. On this, see M. Neves, op. cit. (2013), pp.157 ssg. Ivi, p. 2. Ivi, pp. 5 ss. 114 Ivi, pp. 74 ss. 115 For a deepen treatise, see W. Welsch, Gesellschaft ohne Meta-Erzählung, edited by W. Zap, Die modernisierung moderner Gesellschaft: Verhandlungen des 25. Deutschen Soziologentages in Frankfurt am Main 1990, Frankfurt am Main/New York: Campus, 1991; W. Welsch, Vernunft: Die zeitgenössische Vernunftkritik und das Konzept des transversalen Vernunft 2nd edn, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1996. 113 3809 multicentric society, with reference to language games116. It consists of “an ability not to impose decrees but to make transitions”117. Thus, it is a reason that is not incorporated in the language games but, on the contrary, is involved in the bonds that operate as “bridges of transition” among heterogeneous groups of language118. In other words, it is a meta-narrative, not oppressive but liberating. Welsch proposes the concepts of “all-encompassing transversal reason” and “postmodern supraordered metanarrative”, but according to Neves, they are questionable under the conditions of reproduction of a world multicentric policontestural society119. Therefore, Neves affirms that social pressures to different modes of communication, due to mutual distinct relations (claims of autonomy, selfdescriptions) are difficult to reconcile with the idea of an all-encompassing reason and the related meta-discourse. In fact Neves focuses on the development of stable mechanisms of mutual learning and mutual influence between spheres of communication. From this thought, he develops the concept of “partial transversal rationalities”, able to support constructive relationships between the rationalities of each system of language games. Each partial transversal rationality is structurally coupled with the corresponding particular rationality and it acts as a specific “bridge of transition”120. The existence of structural couplings between subsystems is a necessary but not sufficient condition for the existence of a “transversal rationality”, which thus constitutes an additional concept, and not a substitute. Transversal rationality, integrating the concept of structural coupling, seems to express the cognitive aspect of the legal system, for which, according to Neves, there must be the According to the interpretation by Neves, this means that there is not a higher-level discourse imposed as ruler. In fact, the imposition of one of the fields of language on others would mean the destruction of the heterogeneity of the discourse spheres and of their communication systems. See M. Neves, op. cit., p. 28. 117 W. Welsch, op. cit.,1996, p. 759; W. Welsch, Unsere postmoderne Moderne, 6th edn, Akademie Verlag, 2002, p. 296. 118 W. Welsch, op. cit.,1996, p. 754. 119 See M. Neves, Transcostitutionalism, op. cit., 2013, pp. 28 e ss. 116 120 Ivi, p. 30. 3810 possibility of emergence of transversal rationality, considered a scarce resource in a multicentric society. The integration of concept of structural coupling, developed by Luhmann, with the new concept developed by Neves, thus leads to the construction of a theoretical tool, able to convey the cognitive aspect of constitutional law, which must necessarily be associated to the normative aspect. In summary, the mechanism consisting of structural couplings and transversal rationalities enables interactive communication between systems, which appear less closed and less differentiated, so that we can hypothesize the transition from “functionalism of distinctions” to “functionalism of links”121. At this stage, thus, it seems important to wonder what is the optimal combination of openness and closure of the system, namely the intensity and frequency of transmission of nerve impulses, as well as identify connective tissue diseases. First, we can focus on what Marcelo Neves calls “the two sides of the coin” of structural coupling and “transversal rationality”. In a strictly luhmannian reasoning, based on operational closure, a total system openness would lead, through the mechanism of structural coupling, to “systemic corruption”122, which implies the prevalence of a system on one other, that would prevent the autopoiesis of the latter. Neves identifies the opposite faces, the “downsides” of transversal rationality, calling them “atomization” and “imperialist expansion”123 of the system. The atomization resulting from the closure could lead to “autism” or “idiot specialization”124, whose antidote would be just to build some functional links. In fact, while the internal consistency becomes something of absolute, the harmonization with the environment fails125. On the opposite side, transversal rationality could lead, according to Neves, to “imperialist expansion”, that is the weakening of the system code of communication because of the excessive strength of the other, which does not necessarily coincides with systemic 121 A. Febbrajo, Introduzione a Law and Intersystemic Communication, edited by A. Febbrajo and G. Harste, Ashgate, Farnham, 2013, p.1. 122 M. Neves, op. cit., p. 32. 123 Ivi, pp. 32-33. 124 Idem. See also W. Welsch, op. cit.,1996, pp. 433-5. 125 Excessive external adjustment would produce instead irrationality. See M. Neves, op. cit., p. 32. 3811 corruption, that is, with a rupture of internal communication within a given system due to external blocks. Rather than the two sides of the same coin, it seems appropriate to connote “atomization” and “imperialist expansion” as the endpoints of a continuum126, representing a range of intermediate situations between the total openness and the total closure of system127. 5 FINAL CONSIDERATIONS In a multi-level or multi-center legal system, the issue of “fundamental rights” is directly or indirectly connected to the so-called “transcostitutionalism”. Multidimensional transcostitutionalism of fundamental rights would acquire meaning through the transversality of the different legal systems, by stimulating both cooperation and collisions. For this reason, it is desirable to have a transcostitutional “conversation” through “bridges of transition”, that allow mutual learning of the involved legal systems. The core of the problem seems then the attempt to limit the Teubner’s claim illustrated above, concerning the fragmentation that leads to conflicts of rationality, or to non-harmonic relations between different functional subsystems128. On the one hand, we could say, there is a “demand” for rights protection, that emerge quickly from a global galaxy of social interconnected subsystems; on the other hand, we are facing what Teubner calls the “fragmented law”129, made up of legal systems often autistic in a double way, in their relationships and in the relationships between the legal subsystem and the other ones. A. Febbrajo, op. cit., 2013, p. 1. 127 “Autopoiesis appears to be an amphibius concept which as such combines, in variable degrees, the ability of social sustems to change in order to properly react to external impulses (openess), and the ability to save their own identity to remain recognizable in spite of the changes occurred (closure)”. Ivi, p. 2. 128 M. Neves, op. cit., 2013. 126 129 See A. Febbrajo, “Dal diritto riflessivo al diritto frammentato. Le tappe del neo-pluralismo teubneriano”, in Il diritto frammentato, A. Febbrajo, F. Gambino (a cura di), Giuffrè, Milano, 2013. 3812 In summary, while there is a trend of global society towards a process of diminishing differentiation, within the legal sphere of the single states, at a constitutional level, remain differences which often are in conflict130. Using concepts that belong to economics, we might apply to the Sociology of constitutions the theoretical model of market analysis, in order to identify the issue of fundamental rights as a space where operators produce a rigid supply of constitutional guarantees (because of the substantial aspect regarding the link with their legal culture, and because of the formal aspect regarding the complex procedural process required for adaptation to social changes. By contrast, the demand of users, detected by sociologists, is elastic, depending on environmental changes. In other words, there is an elastic demand in terms of protection of fundamental rights, which is resilient according to certain variables inherent to the social evolution, and there is a supply of normative production more rigid, represented by constitutional systems of different states. According to this scheme, to stabilize the system, we could say that the demand of fundamental rights by world society must meet the supply of constitutional protection. In our case, the offer must adapt to the demand. That is, to get closer to a balance point, we must find a way to make more flexible the normative offer and therefore adequate (or adaptable) to the demand. The problem is then to understand how to do it, since the cognitive process seems to follow logics of global communication that are different from a selfreflective process of the operational closed constitutional system. The answer might lie in the study of mechanisms of connection, which, potentially, are capable of achieving the “trancostitutionalism”. Here, then, the functionalism of links could be modulated along a scale that start from the atrophy and ends with the hypertrophy of the links themselves. This could be the strategic key by which to pass, in the “law of collisions” of Teubner, from conflicts to cooperation. The teubnerian oxymoron of a globalized fragmentation of law is explicated in the statement about the need of “connecting a network of constitutions M. Neves, op. cit., 2013. 130 3813 belonging to global fragments, in a constitutional law of collisions”131 and it expresses, at the same time, the discrepancy between a unique coherent concept of law, and the pluralistic presence of social rules internal and external to the states. Without pretending to provide a comprehensive answer, we could conclude that the law seems to react to social changes through dynamics of the legal systems that identify a boost, still potential, to increase transnational processes, and thus intersystemic communication. First of all, it seems appropriate to identify the mechanisms that make up the connective tissue between the two interacting systems: the material one and the legal one, namely the cognitive aspect and the normative one. The cognitive aspect (exemplified by media) and the normative aspect (represented by constitutional dispositions), have different rates of change. This speed difference creates tensions and therefore instability in the complex system constituted by a galaxy of subsystems that, albeit basically operational closed and autopoietic, are bound together by structural couplings, that are increasingly important in a context in which differentiation and closure, by contrast, are progressively losing their constructivist value. Referring once again to economic models, we can remember how the single currency can work in conditions of stability only when the different monetary “structurally coupled” systems have similar rates of inflation. A very different rate would blow the mechanism, because of the rigidity of the currency that could not, for example, be devalued or issued in an expansive sense by an autonomous country. Similarly, between different legal systems or between different social subsystems, the structural coupling of constitution seems to have to acquire degrees of flexibility enabling the institutionalization of self-reflection within the legal system; that is, making it possible to adjust the normative supply to the demand of fundamental rights. Then, the problem seems to establish adequate bridges between the various subsystems, flexible and thus resilient to change, not rigid and susceptible 131 G. Teubner, op. cit., 2012, p. 22. 3814 to breakage, with the consequent result of detaching the normative process and the cognitive one and therefore preventing institutionalization of internal self- reflection and external communication. The theoretical instrument generated by the integration of structural coupling with transversal rationality (through the assignment of an active valence to cognitive operations of the structural coupling) could, in theory, provide a plausible answer. That is, it could be a mechanism to solve the problem of the right combination of opening and closing, in a complex system where the subsystems are not autistic but incorporated into a framework of relationships that make up a new scenario based no longer, or not only, on autopoietic communication, but also on the inter-system intersystemic communication. BIBLIOGRAPHY APPADURAI, A. Modernità in polvere, Raffaello Cortina, Milano, 2012 (Modernity At Large: Cultural Dimensions of Globalization, University of Minnesota Press, 1996). ARCHIBUGI, D.; BEETHAM, D. Diritti umani e democrazia cosmopolitica, Feltrinelli, Milano, 1998. AUGÉ, M. Futuro, Bollati Boringhieri, Torino, 2012. Amore come passione, Bruno Mondadori, Milano, 1998 (Liebe als Passion Zur Codierung von Intimität, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1982). BARALDI, C., Il disagio della società. Origini e manifestazioni, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1999. BAUMAN, Z. Dentro la globalizzazione. Le conseguenze sulle persone, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 2001 (Globalization. The human consequences, Columbia University Press, 1998). Vite di corsa. Come salvarsi dalla tirannia dell’effimero, Il Mulino, Bologna, 2009 (Consuming Life, 2008). BAECKER, D., Culture crisis, In: The Financial Crisis in Constitutional Perspective. The Dark Side of Functional Differentiation, edited by KJAER, P.F.; TEUBNER, G.; FEBBRAJO, A. Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2011. BARALDI, C.; CORSI, G.; ESPOSITO, E. Luhmann in glossario. I concetti fondamentali della teoria dei sistemi sociali, Franco Angeli, Milano 2002 (1995). 3815 BECK, U. La società cosmopolita, Il Mulino, Bologna, 2003. BENASAYAG, M. e SCHMIT, G., L’epoca delle passioni tristi, Feltrinelli, Milano, 2004 (Les passions tristes. Souffrance psychique et crise sociale, Editions La Découverte, 2003). BOLAFFI, A.; Il fondamento filosofico dei diritti umani, In: Politica della vita. Sovranità, biopotere, diritti, a cura di BAZZICALUPO, L.; ESPOSITO, R. Laterza, Roma-Bari, 2003, pp. 78-87. BRASSETT, J.; VAUGHAN-WILLIAMS, N., Crisis is governance: sub-prime, the traumatic event, and bare life. In: Global Society, 26:1, 2012, pp. 19-42. CASSESE, A. I diritti umani nel mondo contemporaneo, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 1994. CASSIRER, E., Saggio sull’uomo, Roma, Armando, 1971 (An Essay on Man. An Introduction to a Philosophy of Human Culture, Yale & New Haven, 1944). CASTORINA, R. Antropogenesi ed unità tragica, In: CASTORINA, R.; ROCCHEGGIANI, G. Paradossi della fragilità, Mimesis, Milano, 2014. CONSTITUTIONALISING Polycontexturality, In: Social and Legal Studies 19, 2011. CORSI, G., On paradoxes in constitutions, in ???, Ashgate, Farnham, 2015. DE GIORGI, R., Modelli giuridici dell’uguaglianza e dell’equità, In: Disuguaglianze ed equità in Europa, edited by GALLINO, L. Laterza, Roma-Bari, 1993. DIRITTI FONDAMENTALI. Argomenti per una teoria, In: Filosofia Politica, 1999; Disponível em: <http://lgxserver.uniba.it/lei/filpol/glp.htm.> DUMM, T., Apologia della solitudine, Bollati Boringhieri, Torino, 2010 (Loneliness as a Way of Life, Harvard University Press, 2010). DURKHEIM, E. La divisione del lavoro sociale, Edizioni di Comunità, Torino, 1999 (De la division du travail social, Paris, Félix Alcan, 1893). ESPOSITO, E. Identità e persona nella teoria dei sistemi sociali, manoscritto, disponível em: <www.cisi.unito.it/hal9000/ricerca/tsais/Resposito.doc>. EROS IN AGONIA, Nottetempo, Roma, 2013 (Agonie des Eros, Matthes & Seitz, Berlin, 2012). ESISTONO ancora norme indispensabili?, Armando Editore, Roma, 2013 (Are there Still Indispensable Norms in Our Society? In: Soziale Systeme, 14, 2008, 1, 3816 pp. 18-37). FEBBRAJO, A. Constitutionalism and legal pluralism, Ashgate, Farnham, 2015. Funzionalismo strutturale e sociologia del diritto nell'opera di Niklas Luhmann, Giuffrè, Milano, 1975. FOUCAULT, M., La volontà di sapere. Storia della sessualità 1, Feltrinelli, Milano, 1988 (Histoire de la sexualité, 1: la volonté de savoir, Gallimard,1976). FUSARO, D. Essere senza tempo. Accelerazione della storia e della vita, Bompiani, Milano, 2010. GALLINO, L. Finanzcapitalismo. La civiltà del denaro in crisi, Einaudi, Torino, 2010. GLOBALIZZAZIONE e disuguaglianze, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 2000. GLOBALIZATION or world society: how to conceive of modern society?, In: International Review of Sociology, Mar 1997. GEHLEN, A. Prospettive antropologiche, il Mulino, Bologna, 2005 (Anthropologische Forschung, Rowohlt, rde, Nr. 138, Reinbek, 1961). HABERMAS, J., Nella spirale tecnocratica: un'arringa per la solidarietà europea, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 2014 (Im Sog der Technokratie. Kleine politische Schriften XII, Suhrkamp, Berlin, 2013). HAN, B.-C. La società della trasparenza, Nottetempo, Roma, 2014 (Transparenzgesellschaft, Matthes & Seitz, Berlin, 2012). HYNES, P.; LAMB, M.; SHORT, D.; WAITES, M., Sociology and human rights: confrontations, evasions and new engagements. In: The International Journal of Human Rights, Vol. 14, No. 6, November 2010, pp. 810-830. I diritti fondamentali come istituzioni, Dedalo, Bari, 2002 (Grundrechte als Institution: Ein Beitrag zur politischen Soziologie, Duncker & Humblot, 1965). Il rischio dell’assicurazione contro i pericoli, Armando Editore, Roma, 2013 (1987, 1996). Il tempo scarso e il carattere vincolante della scadenza. In: TABBONI, S. (a cura di), Tempo e società, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1985, pp. 120-137 (Die Knappheit der Zeit und die Vordringlichkeit des Befristeten, in “Politiche Plannung”, 2 Aufl., Westdeutscher Verlag, 1975, pp. 143-165). 3817 LA SOCIETÀ DELLA STANCHEZZA, Nottetempo, Roma, 2012 (Müdigkeitsgesellschaft, Matthes & Seitz, Berlin, 2010). LA realtà dei mass media, Franco Angeli, Milano, 2000 (ed. or. 1996). LUHMANN, N., Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, 1997 (Theory of society, vol. 1 and 2, Stanford University Press, Stanford (CA), 2012). LUHMANN, N.; DE GIORGI, R., Teoria della società, Franco Angeli, Milano, 1992. OLTRE LA BARBARIE, In: Sociologia e politiche sociali, n. 3, 1999 (Jenseits von Barbarei, in Modernität und Barbarei, edited by M. Miller, H.G. Soeffner, Sukhamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1996, pp. 219-30). OPERATIONAL closure and structural Coupling: The Differentiation of the Legal System, Cardozo Law Review, 13, 1992, pp. 1419-1441. MAFFETTONE, S., Il re è morto. Viva il re! (Saggio sulla «governance» della globalizzazione), In: Politica della vita. Sovranità, biopotere, diritti, a cura di BAZZICALUPO, L.; ESPOSITO, R. Laterza, Roma-Bari, 2003, pp. 106-19. MAVROFIDES, T., From Humans to Persons: Niklas Luhmann's Posthumanism. Disponível em: <https://www.academia.edu/434382/From_Humans_to_Persons_Niklas_Luhmann s_Posthumanism.> MANFRÉ, G., Le radici culturali del disagio contemporaneo, I libri di Emil, Bologna, 2014. MARCHETTONI, L., Habermas sui diritti umani, In: Jura Gentium. Rivista di filosofia del diritto internazionale e della politica globale, Vol. IX, n. 2, 2012. MARX, K., On the Jewish Question, In: Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher, 1844. MORIN, E., Al di là della globalizzazione e dello sviluppo: società-mondo o impero-mondo?, In: Quale «altra mondializzazione»?, a cura di Alain Caillé e Alfredo Salsano, tratto da Quelle « autre mondialisation »? In: Revue du MAUSS 20, 2002. NEVES, M., Transconstitutionalism, Hart, Oxford, 2013 (Transconstitucionalismo, São Paulo: WMF Martins Fontes, 2009). NUOVI conflitti costituzionali, Bruno Mondadori, Milano, 2012 (2012); PAOLO, F., Crisi della struttura o crisi della semantica, In: Imago. Rivista di Studi Sociali sull'immaginario, Anno II, n. 2, 2013, pp. 18-49. 3818 PIAZZI, G. Teoria dell’azione e complessità, Franco Angeli, Milano 1988 (1984). PALOMBELLA, G., From Human Rights to Fundamental Rights. Consequences of a conceptual distinction, EUI Working Paper LAW No. 2006/34. PARSONS, T., The Structure of Social Action. A Study in Social Theory with Special Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers, The Free Press, Glencoe (Illinois), 1949. PRANDINI, R., Distinguere aude! Il Grand Récit sociologico di Gunther Teubner, In: Il diritto frammentato. FEBBRAJO, A.; GAMBINO, F. (a cura di), Giuffrè, Milano, 2013, pp. 215-67. Introduzione, In: N. Luhmann, Esistono ancora norme indispensabili?, Armando Editore, Roma, 2013 (ed. or. 2008). RIPENSARE l’identità: nuove prospettive di teoria critica. In: Studi Urbinati, B Scienze umane e sociali, vol. 81, 2011. SEN, A.K., Identità, povertà e diritti umani, In: SEN, A. K.; FASSINO, P.; MAFFETTONE, S. Giustizia globale, Il Saggiatore, Milano, 2006. SIMMEL, G, La differenziazione sociale, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 1982 (Über sociale Differenzierung, 1890). SOCIOLOGIA, Edizioni di Comunità, Torino, 1998 (Soziologie. Untersuchungen über die Formen der Vergesellschaftung, 1908). SJOBERG, G.; GILL, E.A.; WILLIAMS, N. A Sociology of human rights. Social Problems, Vol. 48, No. 1, 50th Anniversary Issue. (Feb., 2011), pp. 11-47. STENNER, P. Is Autopoietic Systems Theory Alexithymic? Luhmann and the Socio-Psychology of Emotions. In: Soziale Systeme 10 (2004), Heft 1, S. 159185. TEUBNER, G. Ordinamenti frammentati e costituzioni sociali. In: Il diritto frammentato, FEBBRAJO, A.; GAMBINO, F. (a cura di), Giuffrè, Milano, 2013, pp. 375-95. TRANSNATIONAL Fundamental Rights: Horizontal Effect? In: Rechtsfilosofie & Rechtstheorie, 2011 (40) 3. THE anonimous Matrix. In: Modern Law Review, 69, 2006. TURNER, B. S. “Outline of a theory of human rights”. In: Sociology, Vol. 27, No. 3, August 1993, pp. 489-512. 3819 VACCARO, S. Globalizzazione e diritti umani. Filosofia e politica della mondialità, Mimesis, Milano, 2004. VERSCHAEGEN, G., Hybrid Constitutionalism, Fundamental Rights and the State. A Response to Gunther Teubner. In: Rechtsfilosofie & Rechtstheorie, 2011 (40) 3. 3820 THE IDEA OF PARTICIPATION IN VENEZUELA AND BRAZIL: THE SPACE AS A CORE DIMENSION IN POWER DYNAMIC QUESTIONS Alessandra Maia Terra de Faria Mayra Goulart Silva RESUMO: O objetivo deste artigo é discutir a perspectiva do espaço e sua intersecção com as dinâmicas de transformação do poder, através da comparação entre os casos de Venezuela e Brasil. Conforme a hipótese que orienta este trabalho, na Venezuela, a ideia de participação traduziu-se no empoderamento do cidadão comum, sem mediação de instâncias representativas, um processo que levará a uma radical reconfiguração territorial, um Estado Comunal. No Brasil, o mesmo ímpeto includente fora conciliado à ênfase nas estruturas de representação funcional, dando origem a diferentes instituições participativas relacionadas à implementação de políticas públicas, ligadas à organização da vida nas cidades, como é o caso dos Conselhos de Saúde. Deste modo, recorrendo ao conceito de "fricção do espaço" (Harvey, 2005), buscar-se-á contrastar as formas pelas quais o ímpeto constituinte de transformar as relações de poder se enraizou espacialmente, engendrando novas dinâmicas para a participação popular. PALAVRAS-CHAVE: participação; representação; constitucionalismo; brasil; américa latina. instituições políticas; ABSTRACT: This paper aims to discuss the intersection of space and power by comparing the cases of Venezuela and Brazil, considering a set of political changes outlined in the light of the concept of democracy. According to the hypothesis that guides this work, the idea of participation becomes the core of democratic demands in Venezuela, leading to an ordinary citizen empowerment movement, whose political inclusion dispense the mediation of representative bodies. This movement unfolds into a radical process of reconfiguration of the space-power issue, reaching its peak in the enactment of a Communal State in the country. In Brazil, on the other hand, the same democratizing yearning is reflected in the emphasis of mediated processes and functional representation, giving rise to different participatory institutions related to the implementation of public policies, which are closely connected with the organization of city life, such as Health, Education and Social Assistance Councils. Thus, using the theoretical background provided by the concept of "friction of distance" (Harvey, 2005), will be compared 3821 these two ways in which the constituent impetus to transform power relations are rooted spatially, generating new dynamics and spaces for citizen participation. KEYWORDS: Participation; Representation; Political Institutions; Constitucionalism; Brazil; Latin America. 1 INTRODUÇÃO Segundo observa David Harvey, o domínio do espaço reflete o modo como indivíduos e grupos poderosos dominam a organização e a produção do espaço mediante recursos legais e extralegal. Isso se dá no intuito de exercer maior controle sobre a distância entre espaços (acessibilidade e distanciamento – «fricção da distância», Harvey, 2005: 202) e sobre a forma pela qual o espaço é apropriado por eles mesmos ou por outros. Por outro lado, a apropriação sistematizada e institucionalizada pode envolver a produção de formas territorialmente determinadas de solidariedade social, seja na ocupação do espaço por objetos, como casas, fábricas ou ruas, seja nas atividades (como o uso da terra), ou por indivíduos, classes ou outros grupos sociais. Seu argumento pondera que toda luta para reconstituir relações de poder envolve uma batalha para reorganizar as bases espaciais. Se observado o contexto prévio ao momento constituinte no Brasil e na Venezuela, é possível ilustrar como a dinâmica de movimentação social por maior participação na política trouxe a equação entre representação e participação para a pauta do próprio processo de discussão constituinte, que contou com ampla participação popular. A participação social seria consolidada enquanto um princípio constitucional que entra nas pautas de discussão constituinte, a partir da pressão popular e da mobilização social no país. Todavia, se a aporia entre democracia e representação é constitutiva da relação conceitual entre ambos, na contemporaneidade ela se agrava, visto que se configura um contexto no qual o processo de individuação é cada vez menos coordenado por instâncias de socialização e agregação das vontades. Como é o caso dos partidos, dos sindicatos e até mesmo das famílias. Ocorre, então, a configuração de um panorama de crise mundial nos mecanismos representativos. Deste modo, conforme assinalado por quase todos os trabalhos sobre o tema, 3822 agrava-se ao longo do século XX, o problema da multiplicação das identidades e da “dessubjetivação” do povo enquanto totalidade. No final deste período, tal fenômeno fica, contudo, mais visível, uma vez que os partidos políticos perdem a “centralidade outrora ocupada na ordenação das identidades e preferências dos eleitores, do mesmo modo, mudanças no mercado de trabalho tornaram instáveis e fluidas as grandes categorias populacionais, que acabaram perdendo a capacidade de efetivamente representar os grupos em virtude de sua posição na estrutura ocupacional e social” (LAVALLE, HOUTZAGER e CASTELLO; 2006: 49). Essa crise nas instâncias de agregação e associação dos indivíduos cria, contudo, um impasse para as formas de governo democráticas. Pois, somente ao se agregarem os anseios da população tornam-se passíveis de serem transformados em políticas públicas. Em sociedades de massa, as vontades dos cidadãos participam do processo político de tomada de decisões apenas quando se tornam vontades de grupos, posto que só estas são capazes de se fazer representar na esfera pública. Os partidos políticos durante muito tempo desempenharam inequivocamente esta tarefa, agrupando os eleitores em função de concepções ideológicas, pertencimentos de classe, identidades culturais e religiosas e etc. Porém, em uma situação na qual as preferências políticopartidárias e a identificação sócioeconômica por meio de classes não são mais capazes de mobilizar e reunir de modo determinante os indivíduos em grupos de interesse comuns, a maioria dos partidos políticos entra em decadência e os eleitores acabam pulverizando-se em um agregado de vontades particulares e dispersas. Neste mundo em que o espaço para o comum, para a vida associativa e para a política se encontra cada vez mais restrito, a representação, cujo pressuposto é a existência de vontades compartilhadas, entra em crise. Sendo este um dilema que assombra todos os sistemas políticos contemporâneos, que têm no ideal democrático sua fonte de legitimidade. A ideia de utilizar as Constituições de Brasil (1988) e Venezuela (1999) como ponto de partida da pesquisa aqui exposta, espelha a hipótese de que ambas se caracterizam pela intenção de lidar com essa crise no universo da representação, ampliando os espaços de participação e, por conseguinte, o 3823 envolvimento dos cidadãos na política. Ainda que a participação, segundo Adrian Lavalle e Ernesto Isunza (2011), padeça do excesso de expectativas nela depositadas, do dissenso sobre os efeitos esperados em relação à sua efetivação e do fato de que qualquer tentativa de ponderar o valor da participação pela sua utilidade equivale a desvalorizá-la ou torná-la secundária em relação ao efeito almejado. Neste contexto, a participação seria ao mesmo tempo uma categoria nativa da prática política de atores sociais, uma categoria teórica da teoria democrática, e um procedimento institucionalizado com funções delimitadas por leis e disposições regimentais (LAVALLE e ISUNZA, 2011, p. 101). No caso da Constituição brasileira, a proposta do trabalho é argumentar que a solução encontrada passaria principalmente pela pluralização das esferas de representação e pela flexibilização do dogma sufragista. Isto permitiria à população, quando não satisfeita com a representação situada nos Poderes Executivo e Legislativo, a possibilidade de recorrer a outras instâncias, principalmente àquelas engendradas pelo Judiciário. Quanto à Constituição Venezuelana espera-se constatar que a solução apresentada seja algo diferente. Em vez de flexibilizada, a lógica sufragista é, de certo modo, aprofundada a partir da multiplicação dos mecanismos de consulta e participação direta da população na política. Buscar-se-á, todavia, uma contraposição em relação às análises que apresentam a tensão entre democracia representativa e democracia participativa como um antagonismo entre termos excludentes ou como uma ameaça de recrudescimento autocrático, pela via de uma democracia plebiscitária. Para tanto o artigo realizará uma comparação entre o tratamento jurídico dado nos dois países aos experimentos participativos. Na Venezuela, serão escrutinados especialmente a Constituição de 1999, a Lei dos conselhos Comunais, de 2006, e a Lei de Comunas, de 2010, que declara o país um Estado Comunal. No Brasil, por sua vez, serão analisadas a Constituição de 1988, os dispositivos jurídicos de previsão de participação e representação, e os princípios constitucionais que originaram a legislação dos Conselhos de Saúde, Educação e Assistência Social, ao permitir a estruturação de Conselhos e Fundos nas esferas federal, estadual e municipal como forma de acesso aos recursos enquanto caso exemplar da perspectiva conselhista no país. A natureza jurídica dos conselhos 3824 está presente nos dispositivos constitucionais que instituem e asseguram a participação popular na gestão da coisa pública, na formulação e no controle das políticas, na defesa dos direitos humanos e na distribuição e alocação dos recursos. Os conselhos constituem-se em uma das formas de participação e controle social assegurados nos dispositivos constitucionais, e serão tratados a fundo na discussão sobre a saúde que se estende da esfera nacional à esfera estadual a partir das Leis orgânicas do Sistema Único de Saúde n.º 8080 e 8142, de 1990, e posteriores legislaçoes complementares. Com esta intenção, o contraste entre esses mecanismos será ilustrado através de tabelas que comparem os diferentes dispositivos jurídicos. Esse exercício será feito em três partes. Deste modo, tratar-se-á, respectivamente, (i) dos direitos econômico-sociais; (ii) dos dispositivos que engendram uma participação direta da população e; por fim, (iii) daqueles que possibilitam tal alargamento por meio de uma ampliação nas esferas de atuação das instâncias de representação funcional. Deste modo, a comparação entre esse conjunto de dispositivos jurídicos, realizada neste artigo foi o método escolhido para responder a um questionamento, qual seja: no tocante às relações entre democracia e representação como acontece a espacialização da participação? Nesta medida, as hipóteses que orientaram o trabalho remetem as suas premissas iniciais, que apresentam a participação direta da população em um sistema de autogoverno como um ideal inalcançável que funciona, porém, como fundamento de legitimidade e mito de origem de qualquer regime democrático. Para contemplar tal propósito, a primeira e a segunda seção tratarão, respectivamente, da dinâmica histórica recente da democracia no Brasil e na Venezuela; ambas as análises dedicadas à trajetória delineada pelo conceito de participação no século XX. O propósito de tal divisão é suscitar uma comparação que ressalte as diferenças entre ambos os percursos, de modo a demonstrar a hipótese que estrutura nosso trabalho. Esta, por sua vez, diz respeito à impertinência de associações que, mediante uma aproximação dos dois casos, visam criticar os mecanismos participativos adotados (ou propostos) no Brasil, tendo em vista uma possível ameaça aos parâmetros da Democracia 3825 Representativa, como de fato ocorre na conjuntura atual venezuelana. Tal associação, por fim, será,exemplificada em breves comentários acerca da repercussão da proposta de modificação de alguns mecanismos participativos (dos conselhos) delineada no decreto 8.243, de março de 2004, no Brasil, a nível de conclusão a partir dos argumentos apresentados. 2 PARTICIPAÇÃO E DEMOCRACIA NO BRASIL Quando nos voltamos ao caso brasileiro, observa-se que o marco da discussão sobre a participação se deu em concomitância com a representação política, se tomado o passado recente. Nesse sentido, é possível afirmar que a discussão sobre a participação acompanhou em alguma medida a retomada da democracia no país, a partir dos anos 1970. Segundo observa Claudia Faria (2010) tal processo ocorreu de forma ancorada por um conjunto de crenças que vinculavam seu fortalecimento à consolidação das instâncias tradicionais de participação (e que cotejavam a representação), entre elas o voto, as eleições diretas e os partidos políticos; bem como uma nova perspectiva, a ampliação de canais participativos que pudessem fortalecer os laços societários e estreitar a relação entre a sociedade e a formulação e controle das decisões coletivas. Se observado o contexto prévio ao momento constituinte no Brasil, é possível ilustrar como a dinâmica de movimentação social por maior participação na política trouxe a equação entre representação e participação para a pauta do próprio processo de discussão constituinte, que acabou por contar com significativa participação popular. Não que isso estivesse dado desde o primeiro momento. A participação social foi consolidada enquanto um princípio constitucional, mas ela aparece ao lado da representação. É significativo considerar que a trajetória de sua entrada nas pautas de discussão constituinte, se deve em grande medida à presença de pressão popular, decorrente de mobilização social que atravessou o país, e que foi acolhida e debatida nos 3826 trâmites dos representantes no decorrer da Assembleia Constituinte, cujos contornos foram parlamentares132. Nesse período dos últimos trinta anos, é possível destacar ao menos três momentos diferentes, no tocante à participação e sua interface com a representação no Brasil. Esse esforço de identificação dos momentos se faz útil na medida em que consideramos a participação contemporânea, segundo um determinado feixe de preocupações, como observado por Adrian Lavalle e Ernesto Isunza (2011). A participação seria a um só tempo “categoria nativa da prática política de atores sociais, categoria teórica da teoria democrática, e procedimento institucionalizado com funções delimitadas por leis e disposições regimentais” (Lavalle & Isunza, 2011:100). Portanto, ao elencar três ênfases e momentos no tocante à participação, o que aparece muitas vezes na literatura sobre o tema, sugere-se que eles estão contiguamente relacionados à forma de sua institucionalização, à dimensão territorial que adquirem no país, bem como às expectativas em relação aos resultados da própria participação. Longe de considerar que os termos propostos exaurem as questões a esse respeito, apresentá-los assim visa facilitar o seu estudo e os critérios a ressaltar. Num primeiro momento (1) a marca forte era a polarização com a representação, uma aposta na autonomia dos atores que se traduzia principalmente na oposição ao regime militar, que vai dos anos 1970 a 1988. Esse foi talvez o momento que mais aproximou o Brasil do caso venezuelano, mas dentro do próprio processo constituinte no país é possível destacar como a ideia de participação por aqui se amalgamou à representação. Um dos exemplos contundentes a esse respeito foi o movimento Diretas Já (Bertoncelo, 2009), quando muitos desejavam eleições diretas e com ampla participação popular, mas para ensejar o sistema representativo e os poderes executivos e legislativos no âmbito da federação. Em seguida o momento (2) de institucionalização dos arranjos participativos, e a perspectiva de controle social do Estado por parte da Ver PILATTI, 2008; CITTADINO, 2009; FARIA, A., 2014. 132 3827 sociedade, ao longo dos anos 90; aonde a participação ocorre no esteio de elaboração das políticas públicas. Nesse momento ela toma feições que acordam com princípios constitucionais de representação funcional, paritária e estando previsto o controle social para temas setoriais, que estarão, mais uma vez organizados acompanhando as três esferas da representação no plano federativo: municipal, estadual e nacional. O momento (3) de autocrítica dos arranjos participativos, seria aquele que começa a partir dos anos 2000, e culmina com a proposta recente de decreto presidencial n. 8.243 de maio de 2014, que visava oficializar a Política Nacional de Participação Social (PNPS) e o Sistema Nacional de Participação Social (SNPS). Em relação ao primeiro momento, ressalta-se que poucas associações existiam no Brasil antes da década de 1970.133 Isso porque, no Brasil, a passagem para o mundo moderno e a internalização consciente dos processos de modernização tiveram, como pré-requisito institucional, a afirmação da prevalência da comunidade sobre o indivíduo liberal, na forma decidida pela Revolução de 1930 até meados de 1964.134 Assim, enquanto no período de 1930 a 1964 pairava um consenso de que o público deveria ter primazia em relação ao privado, durante a ditadura militar a lógica se inverte, e ganharam espaço práticas sociais centradas no puro interesse econômico. O autoritarismo posterior ao golpe de 1964 e o período de ditadura militar se modificou com a progressiva incorporação de parte significativa da população pobre do país junto a associações populares urbanas na luta por direitos.135 Essa situação se intensifica no limiar dos anos 80, culminando com a diminuição do domínio militar na política, momento de negociação da transição política. Nesse contexto, a participação era percebida como parte de um movimento espontaneísta, ligado à perspectiva de autonomia. As interpretações a 133 CONNIF, 1975 descreveu como a tendência a formar associações voluntárias para ajuda mútua e proteção que atingiu o médio proletariado e organizou grupos de interesse em torno do trabalho nos anos 30, foi desarticulada com o Estado Novo (1937 -1945), o que perduraria até o início dos anos 70. Sobre a ausência de participação civil e política da população pobre no Brasil nos anos 70 ver KOWARICK, 1980. 134 WERNECK VIANNA, CARVALHO, 2004. 135 LAMOUNIER, WEFFORT, BENEVIDES, 1981; SANTOS,1993; CARVALHO, 2001. 3828 seu respeito consideravam que a participação promoveria uma mudança na cultura política. E as críticas já presentes, indicavam que o caminho para a democracia no país não poderia se desvincular da perspectiva da representação para atingir seus objetivos. O problema à época da Constituinte não era simples, como foi destacado por Fabio Wanderley Reis (1986) no tocante a relação entre social e político. Se a democracia social era fundamental para o estabelecimento de uma democracia política, Reis destacava que, para haver eficácia seriam necessárias alterações político-organizacionais que pudessem ser bem sucedidas do ponto de vista institucional no sentido de lançar raízes democráticas no contexto social, mantendo a perspectiva da representação. Como ver-se-á na próxima seção, no Brasil, o tom se diferenciava daquele observado no caso venezuelano, na medida em que a recusa ao corporativismo ocorreu com empenho e fortalecimento das instituições da democracia representativa, e o desenvolvimento da perspectiva participativa instituiu nexos fecundos entre essas duas, bem como a perspectiva de regulação democrática alicerçada na presença de associações e movimentos sociais como partícipes da deliberação de políticas públicas a partir de 1988. Segundo Lessa (2008), é possível destacar uma teoria da agência democrática na nova Constituição. O sentido original de autogoverno direto teria sido moderadamente recuperado a partir da adoção de institutos de ação direta. Mesmo assim, observa: “A subordinação liberal da ideia de democracia ao esquema da representação – para empregar a expressão de Madison – d, evidentemente, mantida".136 Nela, o cidadão democrático seria um sujeito constituído por direitos que, para serem plenos, dependerão de sua atenção e energia políticas e cognitivas para pôr em movimento os mecanismos propostos de jurisdição constitucional. Apesar disso, o autor é crítico das novas possibilidades de representação funcional dos operadores do sistema de justiça. Seu ponto é. que eles 136 LESSA, 2008, p. 363-395. 3829 desestabilizariam o equilíbrio de poderes, deixando à margem a representação partidária. Nesse sentido, a Constituição de 1988 abriu o caminho para importantes modificações no país, incluindo o acesso a direitos sociais e a criação de novas estruturas participativas, dentro da própria estrutura do poder executivo. Cardoso (2004) observa como novas formas de participação levaram os movimentos a se relacionarem mais diretamente com as agências públicas. Esse processo caracteriza o segundo momento da participação no Brasil, momento o qual Lavalle e Isunza (2011) consideram que a participação teria sofrido um deslocamento em seu uso, em virtude da diminuição da polarização entre participação e representação. Avritzer (2009) considera que o Brasil passou de um país conhecido pelos baixos níveis de participação política a um país conhecido pelas suas instituições participativas. Por outro lado, sabe-se que ao longo do tempo algumas concepções em torno da participação tiveram maior atenção dos legisladores e operadores do direito do que outras. Tais preferências, é possível afirmar, se desdobraram em instituições participativas concretas. Pouco foram utilizadas, por exemplo, possibilidades de participação previstas na CF como plebiscitos, referendos e iniciativas populares de lei. A perspectiva em que a participação teve maior desdobramento diz respeito, em especial, aos conselhos e conferências por políticas públicas e por sujeitos de direitos, como no caso de mulheres, negros, indígenas, cadeirantes, idosos dentre outros. A literatura destaca, no caso brasileiro, uma forte trajetória por políticas públicas específicas, como é o caso da Saúde, da Educação, e da Assistência social. Se por um lado há no Brasil uma forte trajetória por políticas públicas específicas, segundo pesquisa recente de Teixeira (2013) sua ênfase tem sido em estruturar estas políticas a partir do direito, mesmo que muitas vezes de forma fragmentada, e sem as devidas interconexões entre elas. A autora relembra como a lógica do “direito a ter direitos” nos moldes de Hannah Arendt (2000) conecta essa perspectiva com a forma de atuação dos movimentos sociais brasileiros. Avritzer (2009) também observa que o perfil de enfoque em políticas públicas do Brasil é um diferencial em relação a outros países, e com seus 3830 vínculos com o sistema político elegendo políticos que representam ou vocalizam suas lutas. A perspectiva de espaços participativos – conselhos de políticas públicas, orçamentos participativos e conferências –surgiu no Brasil exatamente do argumento de que a política municipal passava longe das demandas da população. Era preciso, se pensada uma política pública consoante às expectativas da população, que canais participativos fossem postos em prática. Do ponto de vista da dinâmica territorial, é possível reforçar que o fato de haver a conjugação entre participação e representação, teve como impacto a criação de estruturas participativas a partir desse momento amplamente alicerçadas na dinâmica federativa –ia lógica que parte do plano federal, desdobra-se no momento estadual, e municipal. Essa lógica será diferenciada no caso venezuelano, como será abordado na próxima seção. Esse marco, de institucionalização, ocorreu ao longo dos anos 90, após a promulgação da Carta Cidadã. Foi o marco também da territorialização dos conselhos no Brasil, e de uma mudança em relação às expectativas depositadas na própria efetivação da participação. Tendo em vista a perspectiva municipal e sua dimensão territorial no Brasil, é possível destacar a dimensão concreta de reorganização social que a participação ensejou nos municípios. Segundo dados do IBGE de 2001, dos 5.565 municípios brasileiros, se tomados apenas os Conselhos Municipais gestores mencionados como áreas estratégicas na Constituição, existiam nada menos do que 5.426 Conselhos Municipais de Saúde, 4.072 de Educação e 5.178 de Assistência Social137. A esses conselhos municipais se desdobram suas instâncias nos planos estadual e nacional, consecutivamente. As conferências nacionais se desenvolveram mais recentemente, mas também segundo o critério territorial que acompanha o plano federativo: ciclos de conferências municipais e 137 Segundo dados atualizados na MUNIC 2011, os totais perfazem o avanço para 5.553 Conselhos Municipais de Saúde e 4.718 Conselhos Municipais de Educação. É possível mencionar também avanço em outras áreas: Conselho Municipal de Habitação (3.240); Diferentes Mecanismos de Controle Social de Saneamento Básico ( audiências públicas, consultas públicas, conferências das cidades e órgãos colegiados) 2.450; Conselho Municipal de Direitos da Criança e do Adolescente 5.446; Conselho Municipal de Política para Mulheres 872; Conselho Municipal do Idoso 2.868. 3831 estaduais as precedem e trabalhos recentes relatam que entre 1988 e 2009 foram realizadas ao menos oitenta delas (Santos; Pogrebinschi, 2010). Há ainda o Orçamento Participativo, que entre 1995 e 2005 registrou em torno de duzentas experiências no país (Baiocchi, 2003; D’ávila, 2000). Assim, o processo que se estabeleceu ao longo dos anos 90 estava apoiado em um consenso em torno da relevância da participação da sociedade no que diz respeito às políticas públicas, processo que Evelina Dagnino (2002) cunhou como “confluência perversa”. O problema diagnosticado por Dagnino será o propulsor do terceiro momento aqui apresentado, de autocrítica dos processos participativos. Ao tornar explícita a discussão em torno da disputa sobre o significado da participação entre projetos políticos oponentes, Dagnino contribuiu para o desenvolvimento de estudos sobre as experiências participativas relacionando-as com seus respectivos projetos políticos, como é o caso dos trabalhos de Tatagiba & Blinkstad (2011) e Almeida (2010), da crítica da burocratização dos processos Durán (2013), bem como das questões envolvendo a perspectiva do contexto econômico neoliberal como destaca Vera Telles (2001), dentre outros. A despolitização da perspectiva de gestão que aparece com frequência nos ambientes participativos é destacada por Feltran (2006), e se faz presente em estudos regionalizados e municipais, como no caso do Rio de Janeiro destacado em Faria (2014), onde é possível encontrar o perfil “gestor” como uma tradição com antigas raízes nos processos de reterritorialização impostos na dinâmica histórica da cidade. Segundo observa David Harvey, o domínio do espaço reflete o modo como indivíduos e grupos poderosos dominam a organização e a produção do espaço mediante recursos legais e, que podem também possuir caráter extralegal. Isso se dá no intuito de exercer maior controle, seja sobre a distância entre espaços (acessibilidade e distanciamento –s fricção da distância”, Harvey, 2005: 202), ou sobre a forma pela qual o espaço é apropriado por eles mesmos ou por outros. Seu argumento pondera que toda luta para reconstituir relações de poder envolve uma batalha para reorganizar as bases espaciais. Nesse sentido, o capitalismo desterritorializa com uma mão e reterritorializa com a outra. 3832 Portanto, nesse processo de autocrítica da participação, se tomado o debate em torno da representação da sociedade que acontece nos espaços participativos, Lavalle e Isunza (2011), por exemplo, atribuem à participação uma feição das instituições do Estado brasileiro, ou seja, ela “transbordou o estatuto de reclamo dos atores sociais e de orientação política programática de governos e partidos –embora preserve esse caráter duplo –, atingindo um desenvolvimento institucional sem paralelo em outros contextos138”. É comum na literatura internacional, a menção à participação enquanto uma instituição informal, como praticada nas instituições participativas no Brasil. Lavalle e Isunza (2011) chamam de “experiências extraparlamentares de participação”, - ou seja, o caso brasileiro, que conta também com a mediação política de atores da sociedade civil -, visto que não compreende o aspecto da autorização formal da sociedade via eleições. Sabe-se que a literatura no Brasil sobre os formatos da participação, seja pela diversidade, abrangência territorial e graus de institucionalização ao longo dos diferentes níveis de autoridade da federação, se deparou no país com uma dinâmica privilegiada para o estudo de tais mecanismos. A literatura, no processo de entendimento sobre essas estruturas, acabou por desenvolver um amplo debate sobre os ditos “espaços participativos”, o que produziu análises que passaram a lidar com a perspectiva da chamada representação extraparlamentar, e apontaram para o processo de pluralização da representação.139 Contíguo a tal processo passou-se a discutir sob o prisma teórico de uma aproximação entre participação e representação, e não mais sob uma perspectiva antagônica entre ambas; bem como a perspectiva de que a existência de espaços participativos não tem por objetivo suplantar a democracia representativa, mas lidar com a perspectiva de legitimidade ao incorporar um grupo maior de pessoas no processo de elaboração de políticas públicas. Para as pretensões desse artigo, destacar a recuperação de teorias da representação para desenvolver análises sobre as dinâmicas participativas, é mais um indício que reforça a ideia de que, diferentemente do caso venezuelano, LAVALLE & ISUNZA, 2011, p. 121. 139 Ibid; LUCHMANN 2011; ALMEIDA 2010. 138 3833 a ser abordado na próxima seção, no Brasil não está presente esse antagonismo entre participação e representação. Haja vista, que as práticas de participação previstas na elaboração de políticas públicas atualmente existentes não possuem como premissa a superação dos parâmetros do regime democrático representativo rumo a um ideal de democracia direta, como argumentam por vezes as críticas ao decreto 8.243, que será retomado na conclusão. 3 PARTICIPAÇÃO E DEMOCRACIA NA VENEZUELA A origem da demanda por participação social também é longínqua na Venezuela, onde desde o início da década de 1970 se observam nos centros urbanos a criação de organizações comunitárias comprometidos com as necessidades internas das comunidades. Estruturados em associações de moradores e entidades de caráter local, a sociedade civil se organizava para lidar com os problemas comunitários dos bairros e vizinhanças, lutando pela melhoria de serviços públicos e se articulando em grupos de interesse voltados a questões trabalhistas, feministas, ecológicas, desportivas, religiosas, dentre outras. Não obstante, ao longo da década de 1980 essa efervescência entra em declínio em função de uma crise sistêmica, tomando um rumo diverso do já mencionado no caso brasileiro. Ao longo da década de 90, era notória a crise que abalava a IV República, regime político amparado, juridicamente, na Constituição de 1961. Socialmente, por sua vez, esse sistema, celebrado no chamado Pacto de Punto Fijo140, se enraizava por meio de pactos entre partidos (em especial, Ação Democrática e Comité de Organização Política Eleitoral Independente, que se alternavam na Presidência do país) e entre estes e as instâncias de organização social (sindicatos, associações de empresários e etc). Nas décadas finais do século XX, contudo, o arranjo que, por meio de mecanismos de cooptação e repressão, alcançava grande parte das instituições e 140 Pacto celebrado em 1958 na Quinta Punto Fijo –9propriedade do líder copeiano Rafael Caldeira e localizada no bairro caraqueño de Sabana Grande – entre os líderes da AD (Rómulo Betancourt) do Copei (Caldeira) e da União Republicana Democrática (Jovito Villalba). 3834 sujeitos coletivos do país já havia sofrido importantes deserções, responsáveis por abalar sua frágil sustentação política. A crença da população na legitimidade deste regime – alicerçada na ideia de democracia, cujo significado remetia aos princípios de estabilidade institucional e justiça social – havia sido seriamente comprometida141. Cristalizada em mecanismos formais e informais, a relação entre autoridades públicas e representantes da sociedade criou na Venezuela uma dinâmica de troca entre: o governo, que oferecia o acesso privilegiado à maquina estatal; e as organizações da sociedade civil que, em contrapartida, garantiam o apoio de seus membros aos partidos no poder. Não obstante ser essa articulação essencial para sua manutenção fática, era a ideia de democracia que funcionava como fundamento de validade para o sistema político vigente em todo o período, que se desdobra entre a promulgação da Constituição de 1961 e sua derrogação, pela Carta bolivariana de 1999. No entanto, conforme se disseminava a percepção de que o acesso às dinâmicas decisórias e aos benefícios do Estado eram distribuídos em função da afinidade com aqueles que detinham o poder, o puntofijismo foi tendo seu conteúdo normativo esvaziado. Mesmo nas instâncias locais, a participação era condicionada pelos interesses dos partidos no poder, que as usavam como lugar de disputa e controle, o que levou por fim a desgastá-las. A descrença generalizada nos partidos, sindicatos e instituições da chamada IV República desarticula, também, as organizações comunitárias. O resultado é um tecido social com pouca estrutura organizacional e capacidade para influenciar na dimensão pública, aumentando o descontentamento face a uma dimensão política que não abria canais de participação para a sociedade, praticamente o reverso do Momento Constituinte de 1988 no Brasil, conhecido por uma conciliação entre participação popular intensa e debate constituinte partidário. Todavia, a longa crise de legitimidade que levou ao fim da IV República, deu início a uma série de movimentações por parte da sociedade civil e de 141 Tal crise se deflagra, sobretudo, após os eventos que ficaram conhecidos como Caracazo, ocorrido em 1989, quando milhares de cidadãos expressaram sua indignação pelas ruas de Caracas, tendo sido fortemente reprimidos pelas forças de segurança. 3835 autoridades políticas dispostas a oferecer novos mecanismos de canalização para o descontentamento geral dos cidadãos. A princípio, estas dinâmicas se organizavam em torno de alguns temas centrais: (a) Aprofundamento da democracia nos partidos políticos; (b) Reforma da Lei Orgânica do Sufrágio; (c) Eleição popular, direta e secreta para governadores e; (d) Reforma da lei Orgânica Municipal. Por outro lado, tais iniciativas, que respondem a um significativo crescimento das demandas por mecanismos de participação, permitiram também o fortalecimento das paróquias, das juntas paroquiais e das associações de moradores (Juntas Vencinales). Com este propósito, a Lei Orgânica do Regime Municipal, de 1989, define as associações de vizinhos enquanto comunidade concreta, unida para defender a qualidade da vida comum, fundamentalmente centrada e originada por características ou problemas específicos da cidade. Estas novas instâncias previam procedimentos como assembleias deliberativas e referendos para a tomada de decisões referentes ao interesse geral (como, por exemplo, questões orçamentárias) e inclusive a possibilidade de revogação dos mandatos dos prefeitos. Embora sua relevância tenha sido limitada por estarem concentradas em bairros de classe média e alta, pelo menos no tocante a estas comunidades, as associações de vizinhos conseguiram funcionar como elemento de articulação entre os planos locais e nacionais. É, contudo, fundamental atentar para a inserção dessa perspectiva em um contexto nacional de ressignificação da democracia, instaurado pela perda de credibilidade dos canais de representação (os partidos e sindicatos) que ocupavam um lugar central no sistema democrático puntofijista. Deste modo, a ideia de que a própria comunidade, por meio de sua participação direta, deveria reunir-se para buscar respostas aos seus próprios problemas, emerge como demanda vinculada ao ideal democrático e disseminada entre diferentes estratos econômicos. Aqueles ligados à classe média encontraram, ainda nos anos setenta, nas associações de moradores um lugar para expressar esse novo entendimento. No entanto, a maioria da população, oriunda das camadas populares, por enfrentar mais dificuldades e empecilhos para uma autoorganização com efetiva capacidade de execução, encontrará, apenas nos 3836 Conselhos Comunais, criados, amparados e organizados pelo governo chavista, uma forma de estruturação efetiva da ação coletiva142. Ainda que durante a IV República tenha existido um processo organizativo de matiz corporativista englobando sindicatos, organizações de trabalhadores, movimentos estudantis, camponeses e organizações não governamentais; é com o chavismo que ocorre uma explosão na organização e articulação no plano comunal. Outorgando, a partir do Executivo, um tratamento constitucional à organização popular nos principais setores produtivos da comunidade143 (PONCE, 2011, p. 191- tradução nossa). A despeito de consagrar os anseios de ruptura com relação ao regime anterior, a Constituição Bolivariana de 1999, não assume feições revolucionárias, embora seu texto possa ser considerado como o ponto de partida de um novo paradigma no contexto do constitucionalismo regional. Nesta perspectiva, as principais inovações, dizem respeito: (i) à ressignificação do ideal democrático, que passa a ser definido pelo adjetivo participativa(o), termo que é)usado 8 vezes ao longo da Carta (no preâmbulo e nos artigos: 6º, 18º, 84º, 86º, 118º, 171º e 299º) e nenhuma vez (como adjetivo) na Constituição de 1961; e (ii) à implementação dos mecanismos de democracia direta, enquanto instrumentos essenciais a esta nova acepção de democracia. É interessante observar, contudo, que a ênfase nos direitos humanos e sociais era igualmente apresentada como diretriz do ordenamento jurídico anterior, ainda que de um modo distinto. Esta diferença, diz respeito aos meios para concretizar direitos socioeconômicos, constitutivos às duas acepções dadas ao conceito de democracia, até porque ambas se referiam também ao plano material. No sistema puntofijista, todavia, os principais instrumentos para esta concretização eram os partidos e as corporações (sindicatos de trabalhadores e patrões). No projeto chavista, por sua vez, é a participação direta do cidadão, 142 Após 2005, os Conselhos Comunais se tornam o núcleo do conceito de democracia participativa e protagônica conformará a IV República. 143 No original: Aunque siempre existiu en Venezuela un proceso organizativo como el cooperativismo, sindicatos y organizaciones de trabajadores , movimientos estudiantiles, campesinos y organizaciones no gubernamentales (ONG); es en la década más reciente y con el chavismo que ocurre una explosión en la organización y articulación de la comunidad. Dando desde el Ejecutivo rango constitucional a la organización y participación popular en los principales sectores productivos del país” (PONCE, 2011, p.191) 3837 compreendida como protagonismo do povo, que surge como alternativa do núcleo normativo do projeto bolivariano. O ordenamento jurídico de 1961 enquadrava-se no paradigma Neoconstitucional, que estruturava um Estado Democrático e Social de Direito voltado ao bem-estar dos cidadãos, o mesmo que estruturará a Constituição brasileira de 1988. Diante disto, é crucial mencionar o esforço, empreendido por autores como Viciano Pastor e Martínez Dalmau, de conferir um caráter paradigmático à Carta de 1999. Para isso, alguns de seus elementos são transformados em atributos definidores do chamado Novo Constitucionalismo Latino americano, sucedâneo do Neoconstitucionalismo, de origem europeia, surgido neste subcontinente das Américas. Tais características, no plano formal, dizem respeito, sobretudo, à ênfase no poder constituinte e na preocupação de que sua vontade não seja bloqueada por eventuais ocupantes dos poderes constituídos144. Não obstante o reconhecimento de tais diferenças conquanto a ordem anterior, é fundamental observar também os elementos de continuidade. Estes dizem respeito, sobretudo, a uma trajetória de centralização de poder, enquanto componente tradicional do hiperpresidencialismo venezuelano, cuja democracia historicamente afasta-se do cânone liberal. Tal viés se institucionaliza através de um mecanismo de delegação de faculdades legislativas ao Executivo, amplamente utilizado durante a IV República e previsto, na Constituição de 1961, pelo inciso 8°, do artigo 190°, que estabelecia como atribuição do presidente da República: "ditar medidas extraordinárias em matéria econômica ou financeira quando assim o requeresse o interesse público e houvesse sido autorizado para isso por lei especial". A despeito de suas pretensões transformadoras, a Carta de 1999 incorporou um instituto análogo dando prosseguimento a essa tradição de centralismo no país. Delineado no artigo 203°, o instituto determina que: "São leis habilitantes as sancionadas pela Assembleia por três quintas partes de seus 144 O que explica não apenas sua extensão, voltada à expressão detalhada de tal vontade, de modo a orientar os processos de interpretação e aplicação judiciários; mas, também a rigidez constitucional, isto é, a definição de critérios procedimentais que visem dificultar a alteração do texto pelos legisladores ordinários. 3838 integrantes, a fim de estabelecer as diretrizes, propósitos e marco das matérias que se delegam ao Presidente ou Presidenta da República com status e valor de lei". Ao ser mobilizado como principal mecanismo da transformações executadas pelo governo bolivariano, as leis habilitantes viabilizam e atestam o hiato entre os ideais de democracia e participação reverberados pelos discursos chavistas e aqueles mobilizados pela tradição liberal. Sendo assim, é a partir deste instituto que o governo venezuelano aprova, em dezembro de 2010, a Lei Orgânica do Poder Popular LOPP) e a Lei das Comunas que iniciam, segundo a hipótese delineada neste trabalho, a mais radical etapa do proceso de cambio consagrado pela Carta de 1999. Com elas a ressignificação do conceito de democracia puntofijista alcança o ponto máximo de ruptura, deslindando uma efetiva transformação do modelo político-econômico e administrativo do país, agora determinada pelo conceito de Socialismo, desprovido de qualquer adjetivação suavizante (como, por exemplo, a alusão ao século XXI anteriormente utilizada). Assim, por meio de duas leis redigidas pelo Executivo e aprovadas em caráter excepcional, a Venezuela se declarou Socialista e Comunal145. Essa nova forma de organização, embora diferenciada, pode ser vista como uma radicalização do ideal federativo incorporado na tradição liberal, pois mantém inclusive uma análoga preocupação com a divisão dos poderes (Executivo, Legislativo e Judiciário) no interior de cada instância administrativa. Ela conforma, portanto, um esquema representativo de tipo piramidal, que parte da Assembleia de Cidadãos (definida no artigo 8º da LOPP), sendo que em cada instância os membros escolhem, por sufrágio, os membros da instância superior, A partir da leitura dos textos da Lei de Comunas e da LOPP percebe-se que o Estado comunal é apresentado como um desdobramento do projeto de democracia participativa e protagônica consagrado na Constituição. Esse argumento, sustentado pelas lideranças chavistas, visa alicerçar a legitimidade da nova legislação em sua continuidade com a Carta bolivariana que, diferentemente de ambas as leis, aprovadas mediante lei habilitante, foi amplamente apoiada e sufragada pela população. Em especial, esse argumento ganha força quando contemplamos o artigo 184º da Constituição, que determina a criação de mecanismos abertos e flexíveis para que os estados e os municípios descentralizem e transfiram às comunidades e associações de vizinhos organizadas os serviços que estes administram e demonstram previamente a capacidade de estar promovendo. 145 3839 havendo em todas elas a possibilidade de revogação de mandatos. Nesta medida, com a aprovação da LOPP e da Lei de Comunas, na Venezuela, passaram a conviver paralelamente dois sistemas de representação: um de origem na tradição liberal, outro de origem na tradição comunista. Essa convivência, segundo o argumento a ser aqui desenvolvido, não se dá, contudo, sem prejuízo para as autoridades eleitas pelos mecanismos de representação tradicional, que perdem espaço para aqueles ligados ao exercício da democracia direta. Esse é o elemento determinante no contraste com a trajetória dos mecanismos participativos no Brasil. Deste modo, quando observados os novos dispositivos legislativos, fica claro o objetivo de que, gradualmente, as instâncias federativas cedam lugar às instâncias do Poder Popular. Para regular essa transição, foi promulgada em 15 de junho de 2012, através de Lei Habilitante, a Lei Orgânica para a Gestão de Competência e outras atribuições do Poder Popular, cujo artigo primeiro declara: “O presente Decreto com propósito, valor e força de Lei Orgânica tem por objeto desenvolver os princípios, normas procedimentos e mecanismos de transferência da gestão administração de serviços, atividades, bens e recursos, do Poder Público nacional e das entidades político territoriais ao povo organizado”. Em seu artigo segundo, por sua vez, o decreto deixa claro o compromisso do governo nacional em “impulsionar o processo de planificação comunal como mecanismo de participação das organizações do poder popular na construção de um novo modelo de gestão pública”. O esvaziamento dos poderes associados à Democracia Representativa se estabelece, todavia, sob a lógica da restituição, uma vez que as capacidades transferidas axiologicamente se originariam no povo, de acordo com a ressignificação operada pelo chavismo nos conceitos de democracia e participação146. Esta intenção, por sua vez, é operacionalizada por uma dinâmica de “Transferência de Competências”, definida pelo mesmo artigo como “processo mediante o qual as entidades político territoriais restituem ao Povo Soberano, através das comunidades organizadas e às organizações de base do Poder Popular aqueles serviços, atividades, bens e recursos que podem ser assumidos e gestionados. 146 3840 No que diz respeito ao provimento financeiro de tais competências concedidas às instâncias do Poder Popular, o artigo 15ºcda referida Lei Orgânica para a Gestão de Competência estabelece que eles devem ser “postos à disposição do sujeito de transferência receptor, até o término do exercício fiscal correspondente, pelas entidades político-territoriais transferentes”. No entanto, o mesmo artigo outorga ao Conselho Federal de Governo a responsabilidade prover um montante adicional no “Fundo de Compensação Interterritorial”, com o propósito de otimizar a designação de recursos necessários para financiar as atividades transferidas. Tal provimento, será realizado por meio de acordos entre “os órgãos e entes do Poder Público Nacional e as entidades político territoriais, que adotarão as medidas necessárias para que os sujeitos de transferência gozem de prioridade e preferência nos processos de celebração e execução dos respectivos convênios, para a transferência efetiva da gestão e administração de serviços, atividades, bens e recursos”147. Porém, uma vez que a legislação não esclarece quais serão os critérios para a concessão de tais recursos adicionais, é possível sugerir que o governo nacional possui uma ampla margem de discricionariedade. Esse panorama apenas reforça o argumento original acerca do chavismo, ou seja, de que as iniciativas de fortalecimento do protagonismo popular, através da incorporação de mecanismos de democracia direta e autogestão, convive com a predominância do Executivo148. A leitura da LOSEC permite observar que os mecanismos de participação cidadã não se encontram endereçadas somente ao plano político, uma vez que dirigidas à implementação de um sistema econômico comunal. Entendido como 147 Conforme o artigo 15º da Lei Orgânica para a Gestão de Competência e outras atribuições do Poder Popular. 148 Para reforçar tal argumentação, cabe observar o artigo 7º,da Lei Orgânica do Sistema Econômico Comunal (LOSEC), promulgada em 21/12/2010, que define o Poder Nacional como órgão coordenador e financiador dos projetos socioprodutivos. Do mesmo modo a Lei Orgânica para a Gestão de Competência, em seu artigo 10º, atribui ao Conselho Federal de Governo a tarefa de “resolver os conflitos que se apresentem entre os sujeitos de transferência e os estados, municípios e órgãos do Poder Público Nacional, em relação às solicitações de transferência da gestão e administração de serviços, atividades, bens e recursos”. 3841 ferramenta fundamental para a construção de uma nova sociedade e de um sistema de produção alternativo ao capitalismo, o ciclo produtivo comunal é estruturado a partir de princípios socialistas como Democracia participativa e protagônica, diversidade cultural, igualdade social e primazia dos interesses coletivos. Conforme determinado nesta lei orgânica, também promulgada sob a forma de Lei Habilitante, o socialismo é definido como um modelo de produção dirigido à satisfação das necessidades populares, através de novas formas de geração e apropriação, baseadas na propriedade social, e orientado para a eliminação da divisão social do trabalho, que caracteriza o capitalismo. Dessa forma, o estabelecimento de uma correlação necessária entre o socialismo e as iniciativas de participação cidadã também é um elemento determinante na diferenciação com o caso brasileiro. É inequívoco que a guinada venezuelana rumo ao socialismo, por ser o resultado de um conjunto de decretos legislativos e não o produto de uma ampla discussão no seio da sociedade, suscita diferentes críticas, sobretudo por parte daqueles que, são marginalizados por apresentarem posicionamentos distintos. Dessa maneira, há o perigo de que quando atrelados a um modelo produtivo alternativo e socialista, os Conselhos Comunais se fechem àqueles que apresentam interesses econômicos diferentes149. Nessa camponeses, nova configuração, pescadores e apenas instâncias do conselhos Poder de Popular trabalhadores, devidamente reconhecidas pela legislação e registrada no Ministério das Comunas (GARCÍA, 2013; p.71), são entendidas como entidades dignas do exercício da soberania, o que certamente implica em uma restrição incompatível com os valores de 149 De acordo com os dados da Fundacomunal, em 2011, já haviam sido implementados na Venezuela 37.665 Conselhos Comunais, número que alcança à surpreendente cifra de 40.035, na contagem realizada pelo censo comunal de 2013 (inserir dados). Essa grandiosidade, permite que os CCs sejam admirados como a mais importante organização social da história do país (e quiçá(de toda América Latina); principalmente quando se leva em conta a amplitude de competências a eles transferidas –mesmo que, infelizmente, não esteja disponível um registro preciso e acessível que nos permita quantificá-las. Sua importância, contudo, é posta em risco por um contexto polarização política radical, fragilidade institucional e insegurança jurídica, que ameaça afastá-los da sociedade civil, reduzindo-os a mero braço executor das políticas do governo. 3842 universalidade e pluralidade que permeiam o horizonte normativo das sociedades modernas. Tal situação ainda se agrava em um contexto no qual esse reconhecimento não está devidamente controlado por regras objetivas, o que amplia o risco de discricionariedade, favorecimentos e restrições ao exercício do Poder Popular. Ainda que não tenham sido colocados à disposição da opinião pública internacional sinais inequívocos de que esta discriminação ocorra, levando em conta que tais mecanismos são em grande parte boicotados pela oposição, é preciso que o chavismo assegure o compromisso com a principal conquista da revolução bolivariana: o empoderamento do cidadão comum. Este é o seu legado e principal diferença face ao regime puntofijista que a precedera, no qual a participação popular era limitada apenas àqueles vinculados aos partidos e sindicatos ligados ao governo. Sendo assim, a estratégia de engendrar uma profunda reforma no ordenamento jurídico-político do país por meio de Leis Habilitantes, de acordo com a argumentação aqui empreendida, deve ser entendida como continuidade de uma tradição de hiperpresidencialismo, personalismo e desrespeito às instituições liberais. Ela não é uma afronta apenas aos princípios do liberalismo político, mas, à própria ideia de democracia participativa e protagônica que aparece como leitmotiv dos discursos de Hugo Chávez e do proceso de cambio por ele conduzido. 4 CONSIDERAÇÕES FINAIS Nesta medida, conforme o argumento que estrutura este trabalho, o que ocorre na Venezuela, em 2010, seria uma busca por alternativas aos mecanismos representativos tradicionais –cuja perda de legitimidade precede a chegada de Hugo Chávez ao poder. Essa tentativa foi desenvolvida por meio de uma reconfiguração espacial das unidades políticas a serem representadas. Assim sendo, se antes a Federação se organizava em municípios, estados e união, cada um com seus representantes eleitos em suas circunscrições, agora se sobrepõem a eles as comunidades e Comunas, também representadas por autoridades eleitas. Com isso, a ideia de participação adquire um novo significado, cuja 3843 radicalidade almeja superar os parâmetros da democracia representativa, rumo à implementação de um sistema de democracia direta. Esta mesma pretensão não se observa na mobilização do ideal participativo por parte dos dispositivos legais implementados no Brasil que, diferentemente do que atualmente se observa na Venezuela, não se apresentam de modo concorrente ou antagônico face ao regime democrático representativo. No processo de autocrítica recente mencionado no caso brasileiro, são inúmeros os desafios, que mostram como ainda são tímidos os alcances da participação no Brasil. Algo a destacar é que além da variedade de resultados sobre a participação nos estudos de caso, está presente o questionamento sobre o fato de que a ampliação e diversidade dos espaços participativos não significa que esteja superada a carência de qualidade ou eficiência da participação posta em prática. Conforme sublinha a literatura, é possível perceber que os conselhos, por exemplo, por sua dinâmica setorial, com frequência enfrentam uma desarticulação entre os distintos lócus de participação. Em entrevista recente sobre o assunto, Pedro Pontual (2014) declara como os conselhos setoriais não necessariamente se articulam com as conferências, ou mesmo entre si, ou com os debates que ocorrem nas audiências públicas, cujos respectivos graus de legitimidade também podem variar muito. Se analisada a proposta contida no decreto 8.243 de 23 de maio de 2014, o objetivo apresentado é fortalecer e articular os mecanismos e as instâncias democráticas de diálogo e a atuação conjunta entre a administração pública federal e a sociedade civil. Seriam elas: conselho de políticas públicas; comissão de políticas públicas; conferência nacional; ouvidoria pública federal; mesa de diálogo; fórum interconselhos; audiência pública; consulta pública e ambiente virtual de participação social. São propostos enquanto meios de articulação, a maior parte deles de espaços já existentes e previstos constitucionalmente. Por outro lado, fundamental a destacar, que atualmente no Brasil a grande parte dos espaços participativos não possui poderes decisórios, apenas de monitoramento das políticas públicas. Mesmo os que são deliberativos e, portanto, podem formular resoluções, possuem fraco alcance administrativo como resultado de suas propostas. 3844 É inegável que houve, em 2014 e no início de 2015, reações exageradas veiculadas em meios de comunicação e, até mesmo, na Câmara dos Deputados, onde reverberou com frequência a ideia de que a participação em questão seria uma forma de ataque à democracia representativa. Conforme debatido na primeira seção, a Constituição de 1988 estabeleceu as bases de uma democracia que pretende amalgamar participação e representação, a qual vem sendo institucionalizada por meio de diversos atos administrativos e legislativos, inclusas emendas constitucionais, ao longo de diferentes governos. Os conselhos existentes hoje no Brasil indicam a materialização institucional de preceitos constitucionais e, nesse sentido, a literatura inclusive contribui para destacar que não ameaçam em nada a democracia representativa, pelo contrário, seu objetivo é arejá-la incluindo mais atores sociais nos processos de formulação de políticas públicas. O presente artigo visou contribuir através da discussão sobre a dimensão territorial que assumiram ao longo do tempo as iniciativas participativas no Brasil e na Venezuela. Buscou-se destacar que as estruturas que o decreto 8.243 propõe expandir no caso brasileiro, já existem e foram reguladas pelo país mediante leis aprovadas pelos próprios poderes legislativos municipais, estaduais e nacional, de modo que é difícil imaginá-las enquanto usurpadoras da perspectiva de representação eleitoral. Por outro lado, não há como esquivar o fato de que a proposta por decreto, fez com que a própria base dos movimentos sociais olhasse com desconfiança a tentativa de promoção de uma rede de integração entre os até então pulverizados conselhos setoriais. Deste modo, demonstrou-se que a crítica responsável por associar participação a uma ameaça aos mecanismos representativos tradicionais não faz sentido no Brasil, onde a participação sempre foi vista como veículo de aperfeiçoamento do governo representativo. Não obstante, atestou-se sua pertinência conquanto ao caso venezuelano, onde a própria Constituição aponta para um sistema de transferência de competências, regulamentado e radicalizado nos decretos implementados por lei habilitante após 2010. 3845 REFERÊNCIAS ALMEIDA, D. (2010). “Metamorfose da representação política: lições práticas dos conselhos de saúde no Brasil”. In: AVRITZER, L. (org.). A dinâmica da participação local no Brasil. São Paulo: Cortez. AVRITZER, L. (2009), Participatory Institutions in Democratic Brazil. Washington: Woodrow Wilson Center Press; Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. BAIOCCHI, G. (2002/2003), ‘Synergizing Civil Society: State Civil Society Regimes. In: Porto Alegre, Brazil.’y Political Power and Social Theory 15:3-86. BERTONCELO, E. (2009) Eu quero votar para presidente”: uma análise sobre a Campanha das Diretas. Lua Nova, São Paulo, 76: 169-196. CARDOSO, R.. (2004). “A trajetória dos movimentos sociais” In: DAGNINO, Evelina (org). Anos 90: política e sociedade no Brasil. São Paulo: Brasiliense. CARVALHO, J. M.(2001). Cidadania no Brasil: O longo caminho. Vol 1. Rio de Janeiro: Civilização Brasileira CITTADINO, G.. (1999) Pluralismo, direito e justiça distributiva: elementos da filosofia constitucional contemporânea. Rio de Janeiro: Lumen Juris, 1999. CONNIFF, M..(1975) 9Voluntary associations in Rio: 1870-1945”. Journal of Interamerican Studies and World Affairs. , vol. 17, n 01, p. 64-82. CONSTANT, B.. (1985) Da liberdade dos antigos comparada a dos modernos. Revista Filosofia Política no. 2. CONSTITUCIÖN de la República de Venezuela (1961). Disposiciones Transitorias. Gaceta Oficial de la República de Venezuela: No. 662, extraordinaria, 23 de enero de 1961. CONSTITUCIÖN de la República Bolivariana de Venezuela (1999). Gaceta Oficial de la República de Venezuela. Año CXXVII-Mes III. Caracas, jueves 30 de diciembre de 1999. DAHL, R..(2012) A Democracia e seus críticos. São Paulo: Martins Fontes. D’ÁVILA, P. M. (2000). Democracia, clientelismo e cidadania: a experiência do orçamento participativo no modelo de gestão pública da cidade de Porto Alegre. Tese de Doutoramento, Rio de Janeiro: Iuperj/Ucam. 3846 DURAN, P.R.F. (2013) Dilemas do controle social na construção do Sistema Único de Saúde (SUS) no âmbito do Estado do Rio de Janeiro: um estudo sobre o Conselho Estadual de Saúde (CES/RJ). Tese [Doutorado em Ciências na área de Saúde Pública]. Rio de Janeiro: Escola Nacional de Saúde Pública Sérgio Arouca. FARIA, C. F.(2010). Estado e Organizações da sociedade civil no Brasil contemporâneo: construindo uma sinergia positiva? Rev. Sociol.Polít., Curitiba, v.18, n. 36, p. 187-204, jun. FARIA, A. M. T. (2014), Participação e representação: as políticas públicas de saúde no Rio de Janeiro. Tese de doutoramento, Rio de Janeiro: Departamento de Ciências Sociais, Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro GARCÍA-GUADILLA, M. P.. (2007). El poder popular y la democracia participativa en Venezuela: los Consejos Comunales, ponencia presentada en la XXVII Conferencia Internacional de la Latin American Studies Association (LASA), Montreal, Canadá. GARCÍA, X.. "Las Organizaciones Sociales Venezolanas como espacio de actuación del Trabajo Social. Caso Consejos Comunales. CONSIDERACIONES TEORICAS e INTERVENCION DEL TRABAJO SOCIAL". RUMBOS TS, año VII, Nº 8, 2013. pp. 59-71 HARVEY, D. (2005). A condição Pós-Moderna. 14ª ed. São Paulo: Loyola. IBGE. 2001. Indicadores dos municípios brasileiros. IBGE. 2012. MUNIC 2011. Perfil dos municípios brasileiros. KOWARICK, L.. A espoliação urbana. Rio de Janeiro, Paz e Terra, 1980. LAMOUNIER, B.; WEFFORT,F.; BENEVIDES, M. (1981) eds. Direito, Cidadania e Participação. São Paulo: T. Queiroz. LAVALLE, A.; ISUNZA, E..(2011) A Trama da crítica Democrática: Da participação à representação e à accountability. Lua Nova, São Paulo, 84: 95139, 2011. Ley de Los Consejos Comunales (2006). Gaceta Oficial de la República Bolivariana de Venezuela No 5.806, Extraordinario, de fecha 10 de abril de 2006. Ley Orgánica del Poder Popular (2010). Gaceta Oficial de la República de Venezuela: Nºe6.011, Anõ.CXXXVII- Mes III. Caracas, Martes 21 de diciembre de 2010. 3847 Ley Orgánica de la Planificación Pública y Popular (2010). Gaceta Oficial de la República de Venezuela: Nºl6.011, Anõ.CXXXVII- Mes III. Caracas, Martes 21 de diciembre de 2010. Ley Orgánica de las Comunas (2010). Gaceta Oficial de la República de Venezuela: Nºl6.011, Anõ.CXXXVII- Mes III. Caracas, Martes 21 de diciembre de 2010. Ley Orgánica del Sistema Económico Comunal (2010). Gaceta Oficial de la República de Venezuela: Nº 6.011, Anõ.CXXXVII- Mes III. Caracas, Martes 21 de diciembre de 2010. LESSA, R.. “A Constituição Brasileira de 1988 como experimento de filosofia pública: um ensaio”. In : A Constituição de 1988 na vida brasileira. BRANDÃO, RIDENTI & OLIVEN (org.). São Paulo: Aderaldo & Rothschild : Anpocs, 2008, p. 363-395. LÓPEZ MAYA, M. (2008). “Innovaciones participativas y poder popular en Venezuela” (En: PACHANO, S. comp. Temas actuales y tendencias en la ciencia política). Ecuador : FLACSO-Ecuador: Ecuador. Ministerio de Cultura, pp.197-205. LUCHMANN, L. (2011). Associações, Participação e Representação: Combinações e Tensões. Lua Nova, São Paulo, 84: 353-364. PATEMAN, Carole. (1970) Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge University Press. PILATTI, A.. (2008) A Constituinte de 1987-1988. Progressistas, Conservadores, Ordem Econômica e Regras do Jogo. Rio de Janeiro: Lumen Juris. PONTUAL, P.. (2014) In: Lavalle, Adrian Gurza, & Szwako, José.. Origens da Política Nacional de Participação Social: Entrevista com Pedro Pontual. Novos Estudos - CEBRAP, (99), 91-104. REIS, F. W. (1986) Cadernos de Conjuntura: IUPERJ. n.7, setembro. SANTOS & POGREBINSCHI. (2011) Participação como Representação: O Impacto das Conferências Nacionais de Políticas Públicas no Congresso Nacional. DADOS –lRevista de Ciências Sociais, Rio de Janeiro. Vol. 54: 259-305. SANTOS, W. G. (1993) Razões da Desordem. Rio de Janeiro: Rocco. SINERGIA, I. (2012). Cifrando y descifrando la sociedad civil. Disponível em: < http://www.sinergia.org.ve/wp-content/uploads/2012/01/isc-venezuela-informeanalicc81tico-de-paicc81s1.pdf>. Acessado em setembro 2012 3848 TATAGIBA, L. & BLINKSTAD. 2011. “Como se fosse uma eleição para vereador”. Lua Nova, São Paulo, 84: 175-217. TEIXEIRA, A., (2013). Para além do voto: uma narrativa sobre a democracia participativa no Brasil (1975-2010). Tese de doutoramento: Campinas, Universidade Estadual de Campinas. Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. TELLES, V.. (2001). Pobreza da cidadania. São Paulo: Editora 34. VICIANO PASTOR, R.; MARTÍNEZ DALMAU, R.. (2010) Aspectos Generales del Nuevo Constitucionalismo Latinoamericano. In: El nuevo constitucionalismo em America Latina. Quito: Corte Constitucional. WERNECK VIANNA, L..; CARVALHO, M. A. R. de. Experiência brasileira e democracia. In: CARDOSO, S. (Ed.). Retorno ao Republicanismo. Belo Horizonte: Editora da UFMG, 2004.